ORIGINAL PAPER
If Addiction is not Best Conceptualized a Brain Disease,
then What Kind of Disease is it?
Sally L. Satel & Scott O. Lilienfeld
Received: 10 August 2016 /Accepted: 22 August 2016
#
Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016
Abstract A modest opposition t o the brain dis ease
concept of addiction has been mounting for at least the
last decade. Despite the good intentions behind the brain
disease rhetoric to secure more biomedical funding for
addiction, to combat Bstigma,^ and to soften criminal
approaches the very concept of addiction as a brain
disease is deeply conceptually confused. We question
whether Lewis goes far enough in his challenge, robust
as it is, of the brain disease concept. For one thing, the
notion that addiction is a disease (especially within the
behavioral realm) is challenging to refute or confirm
because the disease concept itself is poorly defined in
medical and psychological nosology. More important,
quibbling over what kind of disease addiction is unlikely
to be productive. The rational response to adjudicating
whether addiction is a brain disease is not to engage in
potentially fruitless debates over the question of disease
classification but rather to view addiction as an enor-
mously complex set of behaviors that operate on several
dimensions, ranging from molecular function and
structure and brain physiology to psychology, the psy-
chosocial environment, and social and cultural relations.
Keywords Addiction
.
Brain disease
.
Reductionism
.
Levels of analysis
.
National Institute on Drug Abuse
.
Neurocentrism
.
Philosophy of medicine
.
Over-
medicalization
What is a Disease?
In his thought-provoking essay, Lewis makes the case
that addiction is not a brain disease because it can be
overcome as a result of willpower, changing perspec-
tives, changing environments, mindfulness, or emotion-
al growth. Although we are sympathetic to many of
Lewiss arguments, we part ways with him in several
respects.
Lewis, like most participants on both sides of this
ongoing debate, appears to assume that the question of
whether a given condition, in this case the condition of
addiction, is or is not a Bdisease^ is scientifically an-
swerable. This assumption causes Lewis (and his cham-
pions and critics alike) to neglect a basic point: the very
question of what constitutes a disease entity in psychi-
atry, and in other domains of medicine, is largely or
entirely unresolved. Philosophers of medicine have long
debated, and continue to debate, the criteria used to
adjudicate whether a given condition is a disease. They
have advanced various criteria, including statistical rar-
ity, degree of social impairment, patientsordoctors
perceived need for treatment, biological dysfunction,
Neuroethics
DOI 10.1007/s12152-016-9287-2
S. L. Satel
American Enterprise Institute, Washington DC, USA
S. L. Satel (*)
Yale University School of Medicine, New Haven, CT, USA
e-mail: slsatel@gmail.com
S. O. Lilienfeld
Samuel Candler Dobbs Professor of Psychology, Emory
University, Atlanta, GA, USA
e-mail: slilien@emory.edu
and decrea sed evolutionary fitness. Yet all of these
criteria have their serious shortcomings, and none ap-
pears to be sufficient to account for all conventional
diseases [1, 2]. Others in the field, such as Donald Klein
and Jerome Wakefield, have argued that disease is in-
stead a hybrid concept involving a conjunction of evo-
lutionary dysfunction (a breakdown in a naturally se-
lect ed system) and harm (distress or impairment in
everyday life), but this view, too, has its critics [35].
Still other authors have maintained that Bdisease,^ much
like many other concepts in nature (e.g., mountain,
continent, planet), is inherently a fuzzy, family-
resemblance concept that does not lend itself to a strict
definition [6, 7]. From this lattermost perspective, the
question of whether a given condition (e.g., addic-
tion) is t ruly a Bdisease^ is as scientifically unre-
solvable as the question of whether a given large
object orbiting the solar system (e.g., Pluto, Ceres)
is truly a Bplanet^ [8]. Although we do not intend to
resolve this knotty conceptual controversy here, suf-
fice it to say that before one can decide whether a
given set of behaviors constitutes a brain disease,
one must first decide whether it constitutes a dis-
ease. At present, it is not at all clear that this issue
can be resolved strictly by means of scientific data.
If not a Disease, then What?
The rational response to adjudicating whether addiction
is a brain disease, we believe, is not to engage in poten-
tially fruitless debates over the question of disease clas-
sification but rather to view addiction as a complex set
of behaviors that operates on several dimensions, rang-
ing from molecular function and structure and brain
physiology to psychology, the psychosocial environ-
ment, and social relations [6]. Given the myriad concep-
tual ambiguities associated with the disease concept, we
are concerned here with the more pressing and arguably
more important question of whether addiction is best
construed as a brain disease.
Addiction is typically associated with brain changes,
to be sure, but in contrast to conventional brain pathol-
ogies, such as Alzheimers disease, those alterations
rarely if ever preclude individuals capacity to alter their
behavior based on foreseeable consequences. The term
Bbrain disease,^ which in most cases implies a lack of
control over behavior, obscures that crucial distinction.
Moreover, although severe addictions are partly rooted
in genetic predispositions that are themselves manifest-
ed in brain functioning, these conditions can be profit-
ably understood at multiple levels of analysis (e.g.,
psychological, social, cultural) in addition to the neural
level.
These dimensions are best organized not as a sim-
plistic reductionist scheme arrayed hierarchically from
least complex to most, but rather as a side-by-side
arrangement in which each level is complex in its own
way. We imply no sense of a pinnacle, or ultimate frame
of analysis; the point is that each dimension plays a
distinctive explanatory role in addiction, with some
being more clinically or scientifically relevant than
others depending upon the question posed and the con-
text in play. We start with the neurobiological level,
which comprises the central nervous system, and most
prominently the brain and its constituent cells. Genes
help to direct neuronal development; neurons assemble
themselves into brain circuits. Information processing,
or computation, and neural network dynamics are next.
The subsequent dimension consists of conscious mental
states, such as thoughts, feelings, motives, perceptions,
knowledge, and intentions. Social and cultural spheres,
which play powerful roles in shaping our thoughts,
feelings, and behavior, occupy the next phases.
Problems arise when we ascribe too much importance
to only one dimension, as in the case of the brain disease
model and brain-based explanations, and not enough to
psychological or social ones. Psychiatrist Kenneth Kendler
warned of the hazards of Bfervent monism,^ that is, the
tendency to value one approach to human nature while
undere
mphasizing or neglecting others [9]. The heart of
what we term B neurocentrism^ is a particular brand of
fervent monism, one that prioritizes brain-based explana-
tions for human behavior above all others [1012]. Just as
one obtains differing perspectives on the layout of a
sprawling city while ascending in a skyscrapersglass
elevator , we can acquire different insights into human
behavior at different dimensions of analysis [13].
Consider a da Vinci painting It is an assemblage
of subatomic particles, but it is not merely an
assemblage of such particles. Conceptualizing it exclu-
sively at only the subatomic level misses critical aspects
of analysis, especially the level of the meaning afforded
by the nua nced higher-orde r i nteractions am ong
the features of the painting [14]. Philosopher Daniel
Dennett referred to this brand of eliminative
reductionism as greedy reductionism, because it ad-
vocates replacing one level of analysis with others rather
Satel S.L., Lilienfeld S.O.
than attempting to integrate them by constructing bridg-
ing laws across them [15, 16]. Psychologist Steven
Pink er has aptly argued for an alternative brand of
reductionism: Good reductionism (also called hierar-
chical reductionism) consists not of replacing one field
of knowledge with another but of connecting or unify-
ing them [17]. Such an ecumenical approach to addic-
tion would, in our view, would be far more fruitful than
the effort to conceptualize this enormously complex
behavioral condition by means of a single and inevitably
myopic lens.
The key to this approach is recognizing that some
explanations are more informative for certain purposes
than others. This principle is profoundly important in
therapeutic intervention. A scientist trying to develop a
medication for Parkinsons disease will work within the
biological realm of the explanatory spectrum, perhaps
developing compounds aimed at boosting the activity of
dopamine in affected brain regions. In contrast, a psy-
chotherapist helping a distraught spouse who has recent-
ly undergone a divorce must focus on the psychological
realm of analysis. Efforts by this therapist to understand
the patients psychological pain by subjecting his or her
brain to an fMRI could be worse than useless because
doing so would draw attention away from his or her
thoughts, feelings, and assumptions about the world
the domains in which intervention would be most
helpful.
Overemphasizing the neural dimension of analysis
when conceptualizing addiction impedes our progress in
treating and preventing it. This is because it distracts us
from considering users motives, their unappreciated, if
constrained, decision-making capacities, and their well-
documented abilities to respond to incentives, central
psychological factors in the theatre of addiction. Ironi-
cally, Lewis emphasis on the neurobiological dimen-
sions of addiction in his essay and in his 2011 book,
Memoirs of an Addicted Brain inadvertently reinforces
the notion that addiction is a brain disease. Although he
focuses on the Blearning^ aspects of addictive behavior,
an undeniably useful perspective on mechanism, the
story he tells is rendered almost exclusively in the lan-
guage of biology the lingua franca of physical disease
[18]. As a consequence, we are doubtful that Lewis
otherwise careful analysis will sway champions of the
brain disease model of addiction because it does not
explicitly address the value of levels of explanation
beyond the biological. To be fair, Lewis does present
textured patient vignettes in depth in his 2015 book, The
Biology of Desire, and he mines his own experience in
his 2013 book, Memoirs of an Addicted Brain.Indeed,
he attributes his own recovery to psychological
transformation.
To be sure, addiction can be explained in part accord-
ing to how it operates neurobiologically. Indeed, scien-
tists studying the role of dopamine transmission in rein-
forcement will, naturally, address themselves to to neu-
rophysiology. In this respect, arguably, addiction is in
part a pathological condition of the brain. At the same
time, however, it is every bit as much a personality
disease, a motivational disease, a social disease, a cul-
tural disease, and so on. Why privilege one aspect of
analysis above all of the others? On every one of those
dimensions we can find elemen ts that contribute to
excessive and repeated drug use. Understanding those
elements can lead to strategies that help individuals
bring their behavior under control.
The NIDA Misconception
Some background about the nature of the debate sur-
rounding the Bbrain disease^ formulation is in order. By
the mid-1990s, the longstanding truism Bonce an addict,
always an addict^
was reinvigorated and repackaged
wi
th a neurocentric twist: BAddiction is a chronic and
relapsing brain disease^ [19]. This view was promoted
tirelessly by psych ologist Alan I. Leshner, then the
director of the National Institute on Drug Abuse
(NIDA), the nations premier addiction research body
and part of the National Institutes of Health. It is now the
dominant view of addiction in the scientific field [20].
The brain disease model is a staple of medical school
education and drug counselor training and even appears
in antidrug lectures given to high-school students [21,
22]. Rehab patients similarly learn that they have a
chronic brain disease. The American Society of Addic-
tion Medicine, the largest professional group of physi-
cians specializing in drug problems, calls addiction Ba
primary, chronic disease of brain reward, motivation,
memory and related circuitry^ [23]. Drug czars under
Presidents Bill Clinton, George W. Bush, and Barack
Obama have all endorsed the brain disease framework at
one time or another [2426]. From being featured in a
major documentary on HBO, on talk shows and Law
and Order, and on the covers of Time and Newsweek,
the brain disease model has become dogma in most
What is Addiction?
quarters. Like all articles of faith, it is typically accepted
without question, as Lewis observes [24, 2729].
A recent article in the New England Journal of
Medicine confirms that the brain disease formulation
is the government-approved narrative for addiction.
Three esteemed researchers, including NIDA head
Dr. Nora Volkow and National Institute on Alcohol
Abuse and Alcoholism chief Dr. George Koob, both
of whom work under the auspices of the National
Institutes of Health, wrote the article, entitled
BNeurobiologic advances from the brain disease
model of addiction.^ They laid out the neural path-
ways involved in various stages of drug abuse, such
as anticipation and craving, intoxication, and with-
drawal. It is a fine summary of the latest brain-based
findings.
They begin: In the past two decades, r esearch has
incr easingly supported the view that addiction is a dis-
ease of the brain. the underlying concept of substance
abuse as a brain disease continues to be questioned,
perhaps because the aberrant, impulsive, and co mpul-
sive behaviors that are characteristic of addiction have
not been clearly tied to neurobiology [30].
As two vocal critics of the brain disease model, we
can attest to the fact that their interpretation is incorrect.
The brain disease model indeed Bcontinues to be
questioned^ by us and others, but not because the link-
ages between addiction and biological processes have
not always been clearly tied to neurobiology. Those
linkages, regardless of how detailed they are, demon-
strate only that the brain is somehow involved with drug
addiction. This assertion is merely a scientific truism
given that virtually all contemporary neuroscientists
agree that the mind is ultimately what the brain and rest
of the central nervous system do. The linkages between
brain and behavior do not, per se, make the case that
addiction is best conceptualized as a brain-based phe-
nomenon. Nor does the trivial fact tha t a da Vinci
painting is composed of subatomic particles implies that
it is best conceptualized as a subatomic phenomenon
that is most profitably analyzed by chemists and phys-
icists. Indeed, we fully expect more details about the
biology of addiction to be uncovered in the near future;
as important as they may be, such discoveries will not
make addiction any more a brain disease than it is or is
not at present.
Similarly, to contend that knowing about the brain in
addiction makes addiction a brain disease makes no
more sense than concluding that because we now know
more about the role of personality traits, such as neurot-
icism, in increasing risk for anxiety disorders, we can, at
last, recognize that anxiety disorders are purely disor-
ders of personality. The brain disease model captures
only one important part of a remarkably multilayered
causal story.
To be sure, addiction is associated with and contrib-
utes to brain changes. Individuals with such brain alter-
ations are sometimes less likely to make certain deci-
sions and find it more difficult to act on certain choices,
but those changes do not come close to eradicating the
capacity to choose. Volumes of research show that most
people who are addicted respond to incentives and
consequences, such as small cash payments, the oppor-
tunity to participate in work programs, or threats of an
overnight jail stay [31]. The implications for contingen-
cies, choice, and motivation in recovery are well
established [32, 33]. The data on the power of rewards
and sanctions in reducing drug use are potent evidence
that addiction is a set of behaviors that many, if not most,
users can control when consequences are foreseeable. In
contrast to many neurological illnesses, addiction thus
has an important voluntary dimension. In his writing,
Lewis makes the point that users indeed make choices,
and that some of these are self-destructive whereas
others are life-saving. He emphasizes that these positive
changes, like addiction itself, also represent a form of
learning. Imagine, by way of contrast, promising a re-
ward to people with amytrophic lateral sclerosis (Lou
Gehrigs disease) if they could prevent their neurological
symptoms from worsening. That would be both pointless
and cruel because the kinds of brain changes intrinsic to
this illness leave sufferers resistant to rewards or penalties.
The same would hold for dementias, such as Alzheimers.
Hence, the oft-cited analogy between addiction and most
other neurological diseases does not hold.
On
e of the major shortcomings of the neurocentric
view of addiction is that it ignores the fact that people
use drugs and sustain their addiction because substances
temporarily quell their pain: persistent self-loathing,
anxiety, alienation, deep-seated intolerance of stress or
boredom, and pervasive loneliness. The brain disease
model is of little use here because it does not accommo-
date the emotional logic that triggers and sustai ns
addiction.
The brain disease model can also lead us to over-
value medication. As commonly conceptualized, this
model implies that addicts cannot stop using drugs until
their brain chemistry returns to normal, and it
Satel S.L., Lilienfeld S.O.
overemphasizes the value of brain-level solutions, such
as pharmace utical interventions. In 1997 , Leshn er
ranked the search for a medication to treat methamphet-
amine addiction as a Btop priority^ [33]. A decade later,
Volkow forecasted that BWe will be treating addiction as
a disease [by 2018], and that means with medicine^ [21,
29]. The search for a magic bullet is folly and even
NIDA concedes that it has finally given up hope of
finding a wonder drug but the brain-disease narrative
continues to inspire unrealistic goals and guide funding
priorities.
Methadone and buprenorphine, both opiate substi-
tutes, suppress withdrawal and craving and are thus
stabilizing for many patients. But rarely are medications
sufficient to change longstanding habits of behavior
responding to psychic distress with other self-defeating
behavior, yielding to cue-induced craving without
professional counseling or a self-imposed schedule of
self-binding. Self-binding refers to devising ways to
shield oneself from predictable provocation, to cope
with stress, and to maintain the motivation to do so.
Closing and Policy Implications
Lewis rightly views addiction as a learned behavior that
can also be unlearned. This visi on clashes with the
standard NIDA-approved brain disease model that fo-
cuses on Btissue damage,^ as Lewis puts it, and that
denies the capacity for choice making. We find Lewis
insights to be valuable. At the same time, we believe that
a more explicit consideration of the alternative dimen-
sions of analysis would enrich his conceptualization of
addiction.
In his policy writings, Lewis recommends laissez-
faire policies for addicts (e.g., sanctioned drug distribu-
tion; decriminalization of minor drug-related crime). His
prescriptions reflect one way of seeing the addict: name-
ly, as a person who can make better choices in a different
environment and who does not require external control
or benign paternalism. We draw somewhat different
policy conclusions, however. We urge accountability
and applaud strategies that divert non-violent substance
abusers into contingency management programs with
the goal of achieving abstinence or responsible use of
opiate replacement medications. This course of recovery
will involve shifts in personal identity, social networks,
and values dimensions that Lewis, too, rightly regards
as important.
The recent opiate epidemic in America has afforded
an opportunity to replay longstanding debates surround-
ing conceptualizations of drug addiction and the addict.
The major emphasis among public health officials and
addiction experts has been on opiate replacement be-
cause, as the standard narrative goes, addiction is a
Bbrain disease.^ We agree that medications can be useful
and in some cases even necessary one of us works in a
methadone clinic but they must not be emphasized at
the expense of the other dimensions of recovery that
take place on the psychological, social, and environ-
mental levels. A neurocentric view of addiction, which
Lewis analysis paradoxically reinforces despite his
overt rejection of the simplistic brain disease model,
can lead us into such a trap. Once the nature of choice
in addicti on i s better app reciated, the value of
employing contingency management and of modifying
expectations of user behavior becomes apparent.
Acknowledgments The a uthors would like to thank Mr.
Clayton Hale, research assistant at the American Enterprise Insti-
tute, for his astute technical and editorial help.
References
1. Kendell, Robert E. 1975. The concept of disease and its
implications for psychiatry. The British Journal of
Psychiatry 127(4): 305315.
2. Wakefield, Jerome C. 1992. The concept of mental disorder:
on the boundary between biological facts and social values.
American Psychologist 47(3): 373388.
3. Klein, Donald F. 1978. A proposed definition of mental
illness. In Critical issues in psychiatric diagnosis,ed.
Donald F. Klein and Robert L. Spitzer, 4171. New York:
Raven Press.
4. Henriques, Gregg R. 2002. The harmful dysfunction analy-
sis and the differentiation between mental disorder and dis-
ease. The Scientific Review of Mental Health Practice 1(2):
157173.
5. Lilienfeld, Scott O., and Lori Marino. 1995. Mental disorder
as a Roschian concept: a critique of Wakefields Bharmful
dysfunction^ analysis. Journal of Abnormal Psychology
104(3): 411420.
6. Lilienfeld, Scott O., and Lori Marino. 1999. Essentialism
revisited: evolutionary theory and the concept of mental
disorder. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 108(3): 400411.
7. Kendell, Robert E. 2002. The distinction between personal-
ity disorder and mental illness. The British Journal of
Psychiatry 180(2): 110115.
8. Zachar, Peter, and Kenneth S. Kendler. 2012. The removal
of Pluto from the class of planets and homosexuality from
the class of psychiatric disorders: a comparison. Philosophy,
Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 7(4).
What is Addiction?
9. Kendler, Kenneth S. 2014. The structure of psychiatric sci-
ence. American Journal of Psychiatry 171(9): 931938.
10. Satel, Sally and Lilienfeld, Scott O. 2013. Brainwashed.
New York: Basic Books.
11. Gold, Ian. 2009. Reduction in psychiatry. Canadian Journal
of Psychiatry 54(8): 506520.
12. Schwartz, Seth J., Scott O. Lilienfeld, Alan Meca, and
Katheryn C. Sauvigné. 2016. The role of neuroscience with-
in psychology: a call for inclusiveness over exclusiveness.
American Psychologist 71(1): 5270.
13. Watson, David, Lee A. Clark, and Allan R. Harkness. 1994.
Structures of personality and their relevance to psychopa-
thology. Journal of Abnormal Psychology 103(1): 1831.
14. Kagan, Jerome. 2006. An argument for mind. New Haven,
CT: Yale University Press.
15. Dennett, Daniel. 1995. Darwins dangerous idea.NewYork:
Simon & Schuster.
16. Lilienfeld, Scott O. 2007. Cognitive neuroscience and de-
pression: legitimate versus illegitimate reductionism and five
challenges. Cognitive Therapy and Research 31: 263272.
17. Pinker, Steven. 2003. The blank slate: the modern denial of
human nature. New York: Penguin.
18. Lewis, Marc. 2011. Memoirs of an addicted brain: a neuro-
scientist examines his former life on drugs. New York:
Public Affairs.
19. Leshner, Alan I. 1997. Addiction is a brain disease, and it
matters. Science 278(5335): 4547.
20. Dentzer, Susan. 2011. Substance abuse and other substantive
matters. Health Affairs 30(8): 1398.
21. Satel, Sally, and Lilienfeld, Scott O. 2013. Addiction and the
brain-disease fallacy. In Brainwashed,4971. New York:
Basic Books.
22. Whitten, Lori. 2001. NIH develops high school curriculum
supplement on addiction. NIDA Notes 16(1): http://archives.
drugabuse.gov/NIDA_Notes/NNVol16N1/NIH.html.
Accessed 2 August 2016.
23. Public Policy Statement: Definition of Addiction. 2011.
American Society of Addiction Medicine. http://www.
asam.org/advocacy/find-a-policy-statement/view-policy-
statement/public-policy-statements/2011/12/15/the-
definition-of-addiction. Accessed 2 August 2016.
24. Massing, Michael. 2000. Seeing drugs as a choice or as a
brain anomaly. New York Times. http://www.nytimes.
com/2000/06/24/arts/seeing-drugs-as-a-choice-or-as-a-
brain-anomaly.html?pagewanted=all&src=pm. June 24,
Accessed 2 August 2016.
25. Tran, Quynh-Giang. 2002. Drug policy chief looks to the
root of addiction: U.S. eyes 10 % reduction in abuse in two
years. Boston Globe, July 10, A3.
26
. Biden, Joseph. 2009. Remarks of the vice president and chief
kerlikowske on his nomination as the new director of the
office of national drug control policy. Office of the Vice
President: https://www.whitehouse.gov/the-press-
office/remarks-vice-president-and-chief-kerlikowske-his-
nomination-new-director-office-nat. Accessed 2 August
2016.
27. Rose, C., and Volkow, N. 2011. The Charlie Rose Brain
Series, Year 2. The Charlie Rose Show, PBS. New York.
28. Lemonick, Michael D. 2007. How We get addicted. Time.
http://www.time.com/time/magazine/article/0,9171
,1640436,00.html. July 5, Accessed 2 August 2016.
29. Interlandi, Jeneen. 2008. What addicts need. Newsweek.
http://www.newsweek.com/what-addicts-need-937 67.
February 23, Accessed 2 August 2016.
30. Volkow, Nora D., George F. Koob, and A. Thomas
McLellan. 2016. Neurobiologic advances from the brain
disease model of addiction. The New England Journal of
Medicine 374: 363371.
31. Higgins, Stephen T., Silverman, Kenneth, and Heil, Sarah
H., eds. 2008. Contingency management in substance abuse
treatment. New York: The Guilford Press.
32. Satel, Sally, and Scott O. Lilienfeld. 2010. Signing the brain
disease blues. AJOB Neuroscience 1(1): 4647.
33. Leshner , Alan I. 1997. Treatment: effect on the brain and body .
National Methamphetamine Drug Conference. https://www .
ncjrs.gov/ondcppubs/publications/drugfact/methconf/plenary2.
html. Accessed 2 August 2016.
Satel S.L., Lilienfeld S.O.