united states copyright office
authors, attribution, and integrity:
examining moral rights in the
united states
A REPORT Of ThE REgisTER Of cOPyRighTs APRiL 2019
authors, attribution, and integrity:
examining moral rights in the
united states
A REPORT Of ThE REgisTER Of cOPyRighTs APRiL 2019
united states copyright office
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
It is my pleasure to deliver this report focusing on the personal rights of individual
authors and artists, who have often been excluded in broader conversations about
copyright legal reforms. The report represents a comprehensive review of this important
topic by many people within the U.S. Copyright Office, and in particular, in the Office of
Policy and International Affairs. Senior Counsels for Policy and International Affairs
Kimberley Isbell and Chris Weston served as principal authors. Without their efforts in
managing the complex research and writing needed to tackle this difficult subject, and
their keen insight in identifying policy paths forward, this Report would not have been
possible.
I am also grateful to Katie Alvarez, Brad A. Greenberg, Emily Lanza, and Aurelia J.
Schultz, Counsels for Policy and International Affairs, for their significant research and
drafting contributions. Deputy Director of Policy and International Affairs Maria Strong
shepherded the public symposium on moral rights and played a leadership role in
completing this project. The entire team worked diligently and creatively to address the
numerous domestic and international issues raised.
General Counsel and Associate Register of Copyrights Regan A. Smith contributed
valuable insights and advice, as did Deputy General Counsel Kevin Amer. Barbara A.
Ringer Copyright Honors Program Fellow Sarah Gersten provided drafting assistance;
Law Clerks Mitisha Chheda, Caitlin Costello, Tiffany Hightower, Ryan Kwock, and Zhao
Zhao delivered research support; and Policy and International Affairs Assistant Ashleigh
Mayo provided production support.
Finally, I would like to thank the many individuals and organizations who participated
in our symposium and provided comments in this docket.
Karyn A. Temple
Register of Copyrights and
Director, U.S. Copyright Office
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
EXECUTIVE SUMMARY ........................................................................................................................ 3
I. INTRODUCTION AND STUDY HISTORY................................................................................... 6
II. DEVELOPMENT OF MORAL RIGHTS IN THE UNITED STATES AND ABROAD ................ 9
A. International Development of the Concept of Moral Rights............................................... 10
B. Variability in the Protection of Moral Rights Internationally ............................................. 13
C. U.S. Accession to the Berne Convention .............................................................................. 18
1. Efforts to Join the Berne Convention .............................................................................. 19
2. The Moral Rights Patchwork .......................................................................................... 24
D. Post-Berne Developments: New WIPO Treaties ................................................................. 25
III. GUIDING PRINCIPLES FOR REVIEW OF MORAL RIGHTS REGIME ................................... 27
A. Respect for Foundational Principles of U.S. Law ................................................................ 28
1. Moral Rights and the First Amendment ........................................................................ 28
2. Moral Rights and Fair Use............................................................................................... 30
3. Moral Rights and Copyright Term Limits ..................................................................... 33
B. Importance of Attribution and Integrity to Creators ........................................................... 34
C. Recognize and Respect Diversity Among Creative Industries and Types of Works ........ 36
IV. DISCUSSION AND FINDINGS .................................................................................................... 37
A. Federal Law ............................................................................................................................ 40
1. Misappropriation and Unfair Competition: The Lanham Act .................................... 40
a) Pre-BCIA Case Law ................................................................................................... 40
b) The Supreme Court’s decision in Dastar .................................................................. 42
c) Post-Dastar Case Law ................................................................................................ 44
d) The Implication of Dastar for the Moral Rights Patchwork .................................... 54
e) Potential Lanham Act Changes ................................................................................ 58
2. Visual Artists Rights Act (“VARA”) ............................................................................... 59
a) Limitations of VARA ................................................................................................. 60
(1) VARA Applies Only to “Visual” Works ............................................................ 61
(2) Not All Visual Art Works are Covered by VARA ............................................ 63
(a) Works Made for Hire................................................................................... 64
(b) Commercial Art ........................................................................................... 66
(c) Applied Art .................................................................................................. 68
(d) Non-copyrightable Art ................................................................................ 70
(e) Preparatory Works ...................................................................................... 71
(f) Site-specific Art ............................................................................................ 72
b) Actionable Conduct: VARA Rights of Attribution & Integrity .............................. 74
(1) Right of Attribution ............................................................................................. 74
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
(2) Right of Integrity ................................................................................................. 76
(a) Prejudicial to Artist’s Reputation ............................................................... 76
(b) Definition of ”Work of Recognized Stature” ............................................. 77
c) Duration ..................................................................................................................... 81
d) Waiver ........................................................................................................................ 82
3. Section 1202 of Title 17 .................................................................................................... 83
a) Section 1202 Protections vis-à-vis the Right of Attribution ..................................... 86
b) Applicability to Analog as Well as Digital CMI ...................................................... 87
c) Challenges Applying Section 1202 to Moral Rights Protections ............................ 90
(1) No Right to Be Credited ...................................................................................... 90
(2) Difficult to Prove Knowledge Requirement ...................................................... 93
(3) Difficulties for Non-Rightsholder Authors ....................................................... 99
4. Other Title 17 Provisions ............................................................................................... 100
a) Derivative Works Section 106(2) ........................................................................ 100
b) Compulsory Licenses for Nondramatic Musical Works — Section 115(a)(2) ..... 103
c) Termination of Transfers — Section 203 ................................................................ 105
B. State Law ............................................................................................................................... 107
1. Defamation ..................................................................................................................... 107
2. Privacy and Publicity ..................................................................................................... 110
a) Post-BCIA Case Law ............................................................................................... 112
b) Considering a Federal Right of Publicity ............................................................... 117
3. Misrepresentation and Unfair Competition................................................................. 119
4. State Moral Rights Laws ................................................................................................ 120
5. Contracts and Licenses .................................................................................................. 127
a) The Role of Contracts in Moral Rights ................................................................... 129
b) Concerns about Protecting Moral Rights Through Contract................................ 133
(1) Privity ................................................................................................................. 133
(2) Alienability ........................................................................................................ 134
(3) Concerns Unique to Works Made for Hire ...................................................... 137
6. Other Forms of Private Ordering.................................................................................. 138
a) Plagiarism ................................................................................................................. 138
b) Voluntary Initiatives ................................................................................................ 140
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
3
EXECUTIVE SUMMARY
Moral rights is not a topic that has generated significant policy focus within the United
States until the past several years. Some may suggest this is a result of the United Stateslack of
strong protections in this area. Thus, the current Report represents the first comprehensive
review of the United States’ moral rights regime in three decades.
1
It provides a much-needed
and comprehensive overview of how the rights of attribution (the right to be credited as the
author of one’s work) and of integrity (the right to prevent prejudicial distortions of one’s work)
are protected in the United States through a patchwork of federal and state laws, as well as
industry customs and other forms of private ordering. It also suggests some potential changes to
the patchwork that could, if implemented, enhance moral rights protections for all types of
authors.
The landscape of moral rights in the United States is complex. At the time the United
States formally agreed to recognize the rights of attribution and integrity with ratification of the
Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic Works (“Berne Convention”) in 1988,
Congress relied on a combination of federal and state law protections to do so, electing to forego
adoption of a generally-applicable moral rights provision in federal copyright law. While the
interests underlying moral rights have been legally protected, in varying degrees, for decades in
the United States, the contours and substance of the patchwork of protections for these interests
have shifted over time—enlarged by federal and state legislation, including certain narrowly
tailored additions to title 17 adopted by Congress in the 1990s,
2
and contracted by judicial
decisions limiting the availability of unfair competition and misappropriation laws, particularly
lower courts applying the Supreme Court’s 2003 decision in Dastar Corp. v. Twentieth Century Fox
Film Corp. (“Dastar”).
3
At the same time, a rich landscape of contractual agreements and other
private ordering has risen up to further supplement the protections for authors’ attribution and
integrity interests available in the United States; these practices are well-established and vary
substantially from industry to industry. Adding to the complexity, the U.S. moral rights
1
The last government review occurred prior to the United States acceding to the Berne Convention for the Protection of
Literary and Artistic Works (“Berne Convention”) in 1989. The need for a review of U.S. moral rights protections was
first suggested by House Judiciary Committee Chairman Bob Goodlatte and Representative Jerrold Nadler in 2014, and
formally requested by House Judiciary Committee Ranking Member John Conyers in 2015. See Moral Rights,
Te rmi nati on Rights, Resale Royalty, and Copyright Term: Hearing Before the Subcomm. on Courts, Intellectual Prop., & the
Internet of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary, 113th Cong. 4 (2014) (2014 Moral Rights Hearing”) (statements of Rep. Bob
Goodlatte, Chairman, H. Comm. on the Judiciary; Rep. Jerrold Nadler, Ranking Member, H. Subcomm. on Courts,
Intellectual Prop., & the Internet); The Register’s Perspective on Copyright Review: Hearing Before the H. Comm. on the
Judiciary, 114th Cong. 49 (2015) (“Register’s Perspective Hearing“) (statement of Rep. John Conyers, Jr., Ranking Member,
H. Comm. on the Judiciary).
2
Expansion of the protections for the rights of attribution and integrity include the passage of the Visual Artists Rights
Act (“VARA”) of 1990, the addition of section 1202 to title 17, and the passage of additional state statutes in the areas of
the right of publicity and moral rights for authors of visual art works.
3
Dastar Corp. v. Twentieth Century Fox Film Corp., 539 U.S. 23 (2003).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
4
patchwork as it exists today also coexists and intersects with important limitations on the
economic rights of authors as well as important First Amendment values.
In analyzing the U.S. moral rights framework, the Copyright Office embraced three
general principles to guide its analysis. First, any potential changes to the U.S. moral rights
framework must be harmonized with other critical elements of U.S. law, particularly the First
Amendment, fair use, and respect for the constitutional requirement of limited copyright terms.
Second, the vital importance to authors of adequately protecting their attribution and integrity
interests cannot be overstated. Third, a review of U.S. moral rights protections must recognize
that there is broad diversity among creative industries and categories of works, and that,
accordingly, effective moral rights protections are not one-size-fits-all.
Based on all of these considerations, the Copyright Office concludes that many diverse
aspects of the current moral rights patchwork—including copyright law’s derivative work right,
state moral rights statutes, and contract law—are generally working well and should not be
changed. Further, the Office concludes that there is no need for the creation of a blanket moral
rights statute at this time. However, there are aspects of the U.S. moral rights patchwork that
could be improved to the benefit of individual authors and the copyright system as a whole.
Accordingly, the Office concludes that Congress may wish to consider narrow legislation in
certain very specific cases:
Lanham Act. While the Supreme Court’s Dastar decision narrowed the ability of
authors to bring moral rights type claims under section 43(a) of the Lanham Act, there
are still several avenues left for successful Lanham Act claims. Specifically, the Office
believes that the text of the Lanham Act and the reasoning of the Dastar decision leave
open claims for mis- or non-attribution of creative works in the following cases: (i)
claims for passing off or material distortions of a work; (ii) false advertising claims
under section 43(a)(1)(B),
4
and (iii) claims for repackaging of expressive works in a
way that misattributes them. However, Congress may want to consider adopting an
amendment to section 43(a) of the Lanham Act that would expand the unfair
competition protections to include false representations regarding authorship of
expressive works. Any such amendment should be narrowly crafted to protect only
against consumer confusion or mistake as to authorship or attribution of such works,
and not to provide copyright protection or afford the author any additional control
over permissible uses of the work. A narrowly focused amendment would mitigate
4
Section 43(a)(1) applies to “false designation[s] of origin, false or misleading description[s] of fact, or false or
misleading representation[s] of fact.” Subsection (a)(1)(a) allows claims for such statements when they are “likely to
cause confusion. . . as to the origin, sponsorship, or approval of his or her goods,” while subsection (a)(1)(B) provides a
claim in connection with such statements when they are used “in commercial advertising or promotion[ to]
misrepresent[] the nature, characteristics, qualities, or geographic origin of his or her or another person’s goods.” 15
U.S.C. § 1125(a).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
5
the Dastar court’s policy concerns about overlapping IP doctrines generally, and
limitations on public domain uses specifically.
Visual Artists Rights Act. The Office has identified three relatively minor legislative
improvements to the Visual Artists Rights Act (VARA”), codified in title 17 as section
106A, for consideration by Congress. VARA provides limited moral rights of
attribution and integrity to authors of qualifying “works of visual art.” Specifically, it
protects a qualifying artist’s right to claim or disclaim authorship in a work, and
provides a limited right to prevent the distortion, mutilation, or modification of a
work, as well as preventing the destruction of a “work of recognized stature.” The
first proposed change would clarify that VARA’s exclusion for “commercial art” is
limited to artworks both created pursuant to a contract and intended for commercial
use. The second proposed change would add language clarifying how courts should
interpret the “recognized stature” requirement, requiring courts to consult a broad
range of sources. The third proposed change would provide that no joint author could
waive another joint author’s moral rights under VARA without the written consent of
each affected author. These changes, taken together, would improve significantly the
usefulness of VARA to protect artists’ attribution and integrity interests―addressing
some of the limitations that have hampered successful VARA claims without
expanding VARA’s scope beyond the sorts of works that Congress sought to protect.
17 U.S.C. § 1202. Congress may want to consider adding a new cause of action as
section 1202A to title 17, which would offer a creator the ability to recover civil
damages upon proof that a defendant knowingly removed or altered copyright
management information (“CMI”) with the intent to conceal an author’s attribution
information. Such a dual intent standard would, in a manner similar to the existing
section 1202, protect against liability for innocent or good faith removal of CMI, while
giving creators a new tool to prevent deliberate efforts to conceal their authorship of a
work. This would address the difficulty in proving intent to commit infringement,
while narrowly focusing on issues of authors’ attribution rights.
Right of Publicity. Congress may also wish to consider adoption of a federal right of
publicity law as a means to reduce the uncertainty and ambiguity created by the
diversity of state right of publicity laws. A federal right of publicity law, rather than
preempting state laws, could serve as a floor for minimum protections for an
individual’s name, signature, image, and voice against commercial exploitation during
their lifetime. Any such law, if adopted, should include an exception for First
Amendment-protected activities and may require significantly more government
analysis since this was not the sole focus of the current review.
The Copyright Office believes that the U.S. moral rights patchwork continues to provide
important protections, despite acknowledging the value of targeted improvement in some areas.
Title 17 and other federal and state laws, including unfair competition and misappropriation
doctrines, combined with a robust private ordering landscape, provide an author with a
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
6
patchwork of means by which to protect and enforce their interests in being credited as the
author of their work and to preserve the integrity of that work. Nonetheless, this patchwork has
been narrowly interpreted over the years in ways that could undermine the important rights of
individual authors and artists. Should Congress wish to strengthen—and/or streamline—the U.S.
moral rights framework, this Report provides a roadmap for doing so.
I. INTRODUCTION AND STUDY HISTORY
Taken from the French phrase droit moral, the term “moral rights” generally refers to
certain non-economic rights that are considered personal to an author.
5
Central to the idea of
moral rights is the idea that a creative work, such as a song or book, actually expresses the
personality of the author.
6
Society has long recognized the importance of such a bond between a
creative work and its author: as far back as the early 1500s, courts in France recognized that only
the author has a right to publish their work.
7
Over the course of the last two centuries, countries
have increasingly codified this close connection between the author and their work, first through
judicial doctrines and limited statutory protections for certain aspects of moral rights, such as a
right of first publication, and later through formalized statutory moral rights schemes.
8
While countries have come to recognize a variety of different moral rights, the two most
commonly recognized moral rights are the right of an author to be credited as the author of their
work (the right of attribution),
9
and the right of an author to prevent prejudicial distortions of
their work (the right of integrity), both of which were codified at the international level in the
5
See 1 SAM RICKETSON & JANE C. GINSBURG, INTERNATIONAL COPYRIGHT AND NEIGHBOURING RIGHTS: THE BERNE
CONVENTION AND BEYOND 10.02, at 586–87 (2d ed. 2006) (“RICKETSON & GINSBURG”). However, while moral rights are
typically considered non-economic, study commenters pointed out that the right of attribution in fact has economic
importance for an author as well as a reputational importance. See Session 4: The Importance of Moral Rights to Authors,
in Symposium Transcript, Authors, Attribution, and Integrity: Examining Moral Rights in the United States, 8 GEO. MASON J.
INTL COM. L. 87, 91 (2016) (“Session 4, Symposium Transcript”) (remarks of David Lowery, songwriter/recording artist)
(noting the importance of proper attribution for building a fan base and achieving ancillary licensing deals).
6
As used in this Report, the term “author” includes all human creators of copyright-protected works, including visual
artists and performers.
7
See MARK ROSE, AUTHORS AND OWNERS: THE INVENTION OF COPYRIGHT 18–19 (1993) (“ROSE, AUTHORS AND OWNERS”)
(discussing decisions by the Parlement of Paris (acting as a court of first instance) prohibiting booksellers from
engaging in the unauthorized printing and selling of certain works, ultimately granting the authors of those works the
exclusive right to publish the works at issue).
8
See infra Section II.A.
9
Attribution can include both positive and negative rights, i.e., the authors right to be identified as the author of their
work as well as the right to not be identified as the author of works they did not author. See WORLD INTELLECTUAL
PROPERTY ORGANIZATION, GUIDE TO THE BERNE CONVENTION FOR THE PROTECTION OF LITERARY AND ARTISTIC WORKS (PARIS
ACT, 1971) 41 (1978) (“GUIDE TO THE BERNE CONVENTION”), available at https://www.wipo.int/edocs/pubdocs/en/
copyright/615/wipo_pub_615.pdf; Adolf Dietz, The Moral Right of the Author: Moral Rights and the Civil Law Countries,
19 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS 199, 219 (1995).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
7
1928 Rome revision of the Berne Convention.
10
It was not until 1989, however, that the United
States became subject to an obligation to provide moral rights protections for authors by joining
the Berne Convention.
11
At that time, Congress determined that the United States provided
protection for the rights of attribution and integrity through an existing patchwork of laws.
12
This
patchwork included federal laws such as the Lanham Act and certain provisions of the Copyright
Act, as well as state laws relating to privacy and publicity, contracts, fraud and misrepresentation,
unfair competition, and defamation.
13
The exact contours of this patchwork of protections for
moral rights in the United States has changed over the ensuing three decades, with Congress
adding two additional elements to the patchwork: in 1990, Congress passed VARA, which
guarantees to authors of “works of visual art” the right to claim or disclaim authorship in a work
and limited rights to prevent the distortion, mutilation, or modification of the work;
14
and in 1998
Congress added section 1202 to title 17, which prohibits both providing false copyright
management information (“CMI”) and removing or altering CMI in certain circumstances.
15
Along with the post-Berne accession changes wrought by VARA and the advent of section
1202, significant changes in technology and business practices have altered how rights of
attribution and integrity are experienced by authors in the United States.
16
Most notably, the
growth of the internet as the primary locus for buying, selling, and licensing works of authorship
has meant that original works in digital form have become more accessible to more people. On
the one hand, this has meant that the attribution and integrity of works have been more
susceptible to mishandling and manipulation. For example, the metadata containing attribution
and other information for creative works is very simple to remove (or “strip”) or replace with
10
Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artist Works art. 6bis(1), Sept. 9, 1886, as revised June 2, 1928, 123
L.N.T.S. 233, 248, 250 (“Rome Text”) (“Indépendamment des droits patrimoniaux d'auteur, et même après la cession
desdits droits, l'auteur conserve le droit de revendiquer la paternité de l'oeuvre, ainsi que le droit de s'opposer à toute
déformation, mutilation ou autre modification de ladite oeuvre, qui serait préjudiciable à son honneur ou à sa
réputation.”). English did not become an official language for the Berne Convention until the 1967 Stockholm Text. For
an unofficial English translation of the Rome Text, see id. at 249, 251 (“Independently of the authors copyright, and
even after the transfer of the said copyright, the author shall have the right to claim authorship of the work, as well as
to object to any distortion, mutilation or other modification of the said work which would be prejudicial to his honour
or reputation.”).
11
See Berne Convention Implementation Act (‘‘BCIA’’) of 1988, Pub. L. No. 100-568, 102 Stat. 2853 (codified in scattered
sections of 17 U.S.C.).
12
See H.R. REP. NO. 100-609, at 37–38 (1988); S. REP. NO. 100-352, at 9–10 (1988).
13
See id.
14
Visual Artists Rights Act (“VARA”) of 1990, Pub. L. No. 101-650, 104 Stat. 5128, 5128–29 (codified at 17 U.S.C. § 106A).
15
Digital Millennium Copyright Act (“DMCA”), Pub. L. No. 105-304, 122 Stat. 2860, 2872–74 (1998) (codified as
amended at 17 U.S.C. § 1202).
16
See Study on the Moral Rights of Attribution and Integrity: Notice of Inquiry, 82 Fed. Reg. 7870, 7874 (Jan. 23, 2017)
(“Moral Rights NOI”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
8
erroneous information. A work stripped of proper identifying information then can be
disseminated widely to the detriment of both the author’s reputation and ability to profit from
the work.
17
Similarly, the increasingly accessible video editing technology behind “deepfake”
software can not only fundamentally alter the content of an author’s work, but can also lead to
social and moral harm for the artists and the subject of the video through malicious use.
18
On the
other hand, digital technologies such as fingerprinting and visual recognition software that allow
photographers to identify and track metadata related to their works on the internet have enabled
authors to combat some of these threats to their attribution and integrity interests.
19
Whether
considered as a useful tool or a threat to protection of integrity and attribution interests, there is
no question that technology has transformed the moral rights landscape in the United States.
Acknowledging this transformed landscape of moral rights protections in the current era,
Congress held a hearing on July 15, 2014, on the topic of moral rights protections in the United
States as part of its broader review of U.S. copyright law. At the hearing, both the Chairman of
the House Judiciary Committee and the Ranking Member of the Committee’s Subcommittee on
Courts, Intellectual Property, and the Internet expressed interest in knowing more about how
existing U.S. law, including provisions found in title 17 of the U.S. Code and other federal and
state laws, protects the moral rights of attribution and integrity, and whether any additional
protection is advisable in this area.
20
At a subsequent hearing in 2015, responding to a suggestion
from then-Register of Copyrights Maria Pallante, the Ranking Member of the House Judiciary
Committee requested that the Copyright Office conduct a moral rights study.
21
17
See, e.g., Session 4, Symposium Transcript, 8 GEO. MASON J. INTL COM. L. at 90–91 (remarks of David Lowery,
songwriter/recording artist) (commenting on the negative effects of having a song of his misattributed for several years
to Tom Petty on online music sites); Coalition of Visual Artists, Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright
Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 25 (Mar. 28, 2017) (“CVA Initial Comments”) (“The Internet displays images
and allows the copying and theft of those images by a simple right click of a mouse without permission from the
creator. In the process, sometimes the metadata is stripped from the image. The loss of attribution causes the visual
creator to lose control and income from his/her work and lose the ability to license those images.”).
18
See, e.g., I Never Said That! High-Tech Deception of ‘Deepfake’ Videos, CBS NEWS (July 2, 2018),
https://www.cbsnews.com/news/i-never-said-that-high-tech-deception-of-deepfake-videos/; George Dvorsky, Deepfake
Videos are Getting Impossibly Good, GIZMODO (June 12, 2018, 1:05 PM), https://gizmodo.com/deepfake-videos-are-getting-
impossibly-good-1826759848.
19
See Session 4, Symposium Transcript, 8 GEO. MASON J. INTL COM. L. at 93 (remarks of Yoko Miyashita, Getty Images)
(discussing the digital fingerprinting technology used by Getty Images).
20
See 2014 Moral Rights Hearing at 4 (statements of Rep. Bob Goodlatte, Chairman, H. Comm. on the Judiciary; Rep.
Jerrold Nadler, Ranking Member, H. Subcomm. on Courts, Intellectual Prop., & the Internet).
21
Register’s Perspective Hearing at 49 (statement of Rep. John Conyers, Jr., Ranking Member, H. Comm. on the Judiciary).
The Department of Commerces Internet Policy Task Force has also been touching on these issues in its exploration of
the digital marketplace for copyrighted works, particularly with respect to how technology can aid in connecting
attribution to works and facilitating creator control of downstream uses. The most recent public meeting of the task
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
9
As part of the preparation for this Study, the Copyright Office co-hosted a daylong
symposium on moral rights in April 2016 in order to hear views about current issues on this
subject from authors, scholars, and other stakeholders. On January 23, 2017, the Copyright Office
published a Notice of Inquiry in the Federal Register announcing the study and soliciting public
input.
22
The Copyright Office received 46 initial comments and 16 reply comments from a broad
range of interested stakeholders in response to the Notice.
23
This Report evaluates the current state of protections for the rights of attribution and
integrity in the United States, assessing the myriad changes to the moral rights landscape that
have resulted from significant legal, technological, and business developments over the past
thirty years. The Study’s record reveals a great diversity of opinions among different
stakeholders concerning the strength of existing, and the potential need for additional, moral
rights protections. Based on the Office’s review of the record, as well as additional research
conducted by the Office, we do not recommend the introduction of a blanket moral rights statute
at this time. Instead, we conclude that many aspects of the U.S. moral rights landscape remain
useful for authors and performers. We also acknowledge the desirability of certain targeted
changes to strengthen protections for individual creators.
24
Thus, should Congress wish to take
further steps to update the moral rights regime, this Report offers possible pathways for
improvements in the areas of the Visual Artists Rights Act (“VARA”), section 1202 of title 17, the
Lanham Act, and the right of publicity.
II. DEVELOPMENT OF MORAL RIGHTS IN THE UNITED STATES AND ABROAD
To lay the foundation for this Report’s discussion of current U.S. moral rights issues, it is
necessary to sketch the development of the legal concept of moral rights internationally, as well
as its evolution in the United States.
force was held on March 28, 2019. Further information about the task force’s work on this area can be found at
https://www.ntia.doc.gov/category/copyright.
22
See Moral Rights NOI.
23
A transcript of the symposium and links to all written comments, as well as other background material on this Study,
are available at https://www.copyright.gov/policy/moralrights/. A list of symposium participants is attached to this
Report as Appendix A, the text of the Notice of Inquiry is attached as Appendix B, and a list of commenters in response
to the Notice is attached as Appendix C.
24
In addition to this Report, the Office recently issued a letter to Congress discussing responses to challenges faced by
authors of visual works. See Letter from Karyn A. Temple, Acting Register of Copyrights & Dir., U.S. Copyright Office,
to Lindsey Graham, Chairman, Comm. on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate, and Dianne Feinstein, Ranking Member, Comm.
on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate (Jan. 18, 2019), available at https://www.copyright.gov/policy/visualworks/senate-letter.pdf;
Letter from Karyn A. Temple, Acting Register of Copyrights & Dir., U.S. Copyright Office, to Jerrold Nadler, Chairman,
Comm. on the Judiciary, U.S. House of Representatives, and Doug Collins, Ranking Member, Comm. on the Judiciary,
U.S. House of Representatives (Jan. 18, 2019), available at https://www.copyright.gov/policy/visualworks/house-
letter.pdf.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
10
A. International Development of the Concept of Moral Rights
The rights of attribution and integrity have long histories; the concepts embodied therein
have been recognized in some form in many countries of the world for centuries. In the cultures
of Nigeria, oral literature was put into written form with attribution to the original author.
25
Similarly, some scholars see precursors of both the rights of attribution and integrity in social
norms dating back to Roman times.
26
Formal statutory codification of moral rights, however, is a
more recent development.
Some of the earliest legal recognitions for something analogous to modern moral rights
date back to the Renaissance, when courts and legislatures began to recognize that authors had a
reputation-based interest in controlling at least the initial public dissemination of their works. In
France, often considered the birthplace of modern moral rights, a court recognized that only the
author has a right to publish his work as early as 1504.
27
Other countries began recognizing a
similar right of first publication in the decades that followed. Such a right was recognized in a
public edict by the Venetian Council of Ten in 1545, while the English Parliament issued a decree
in 1642 requiring publishing houses to receive author consent before publishing works.
28
In fact,
in many countries recognition for a first publication right predated the legal recognition of
copyrights, which began to be codified throughout Europe during the eighteenth century.
29
At the same time countries were codifying economic copyright protections for authors, the
rights of attribution and integrity began to receive explicit, but limited, statutory legal protection.
The French National Assembly codified in national law a proto-right of attribution and integrity
25
See Nkem Itanyi & Madunatu Chikaodili Nwamaka, An Appraisal of the Operational Problems Hindering the Protection of
Performer’s Rights as Copyright in Nigeria, 14 U.S.-CHINA L. REV. 608, 610 (2017).
26
See Katharina de la Durantaye, The Origins of the Protection of Literary Authorship in Ancient Rome, 25 B.U. INTL L.J. 37,
68–76 (2007).
27
ROSE, AUTHORS AND OWNERS 18–19.
28
ROSE, AUTHORS AND OWNERS 20–22.
29
See, e.g., An Act for the Encouragement of Learning, by Vesting the Copies of Printed Books in the Authors or
Purchasers of Copies, during the Time therein mentioned (“Statute of Anne”), 8 Ann., c. 19 (1710) (Gr. Brit.); Décret du
19 julliet 1793 de la Convention Nationale relatif aux droits de propriété des Auteurs d'écrits en tout genre, des
Compositeurs de musique, des Peintres et des Dessinateurs [Decree of July 19, 1793 of the National Convention
regarding the property right of authors to writings of all kinds, of composers of music, of painters and illustrators] (Fr.).
The impetus for such “copyright” statutes grew out of the philosophy of John Locke, with his idea of ownership
stemming from the mixing of man’s labor with anything man removes from nature, along with the European
Renaissance’s romanticized notion of the author. See ROSE, AUTHORS AND OWNERS 5, 18; see also JOHN LOCKE, TWO
TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT 287–88 (Peter Laslett ed., Cambridge Univ. Press 1988) (1690).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
11
for playwrights in 1791.
30
Similarly, early forms of protection for the rights of attribution and
integrity were codified in the German Laws of 1870 and 1876.
31
Although copyright protections were harmonized at the international level in 1886
through the adoption of the Berne Convention, over forty years elapsed before the first
international codification of the emerging rights of attribution and integrity. In 1928, the Berne
Convention was updated to add a requirement for recognition of the rights of attribution and
integrity as article 6bis, which read:
. . . the author shall have the right to claim authorship of the work, as well as the
right to object to any distortion, mutilation or other modification of the said work
which would be prejudicial to his honor or reputation.
32
At the time of the 1928 revisions to the Berne Convention, recognition of these moral
rights had been statutorily codified in a few, but not all, signatory countries.
33
While Japan added
a statutory moral rights provision as early as 1899,
34
many other countries did not adopt such
statutory protections until years later. Canada added a statutory protection for the rights of
attribution and integrity to its copyright law in 1931.
35
Later adopters of statutory moral rights
30
See Susan P. Liemer, On the Origins of Le Droit Moral: How Non-Economic Rights Came to be Protected in French IP Law,
19 J. INTELL. PROP. L. 65, 108–09 (2011).
31
See 1 RICKETSON & GINSBURG 10.03, at 588.
32
Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artist Works art 6bis(1), Sept. 9, 1886, as revised June 2, 1928, 123
L.N.T.S. 233 (“Rome Text”). Relatedly, but in a separate section, in 1948 WIPO members amended the Berne
Convention to include a requirement for attributing the source and name of the author of a quotation. See Berne
Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic Works art. 10(3), Sept. 9, 1886, as revised June 26, 1948, 331
U.N.T.S. 217 (“Brussels Text”). Additional international recognition of moral rights was provided in the 1948 Universal
Declaration of Human Rights, which states, “[e]veryone has the right to the protection of the moral and material
interests resulting from any scientific, literary or artistic production of which he is the author.” G.A. Res. 217 (III) A,
Art. 27(2), at 76, Universal Declaration of Human Rights (Dec. 10, 1948). However, the Declaration is “not a treaty or
international agreement . . . impos[ing] legal obligations.” Sosa v. Alvarez-Machain, 542 U.S. 692, 734-35 (2004) (internal
quotation marks omitted).
33
By the mid-1920s, Bulgaria, Czechoslovakia, Finland, Germany, Italy, Japan, Poland, Romania, and Switzerland had
all adopted statutory protections for the right of attribution, the right of integrity, or both. See 1 RICKETSON & GINSBURG
¶¶ 10.03–10.06, at 587–90.
34
Article 18 of the Copyright Act, Law No. 39 of 1899, art. 18, protected mukeijo no kenri, rights belonging “exclusively to
the author and constitut[ing] a part of his personality right.” Teruo Doi, Parody, Fair Use, and Moral Rights from the
Japanese Perspective, 24 J. INTL ASSN FOR PROTECTION INDUS. PROP. JAPAN 16, 24 (1999) (internal citation omitted).
35
Copyright Act, S.C. 1921, c 24, s 1, art 12(5) (Can.), amended by the Copyright Amendment Act, 1931, 21 & 22 Geo. 5, c.
8 (UK). One scholar suggests that this is because of Canadas somewhat unique mix of common and civil law
traditions. See Gerald Dworkin, The Moral Right of the Author: Moral Rights and the Common Law Countries, 19 COLUM.-
VLA J.L. & ARTS 229, 232 (1995); see also PAUL GOLDSTEIN & BERNT HUGENHOLTZ, INTERNATIONAL COPYRIGHT: PRINCIPLES,
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
12
included two original 1886 signatories to the Berne Convention: the United Kingdom in 1988
36
and Switzerland in 1992.
37
Even Australia and New Zealand, which both signed the Rome Text in
1928 with its new article 6bis,
38
did not add explicit moral rights protections to their copyright
statutes until 2000
39
and 1994,
40
respectively. Similarly, while Singapore has codified certain
moral rights in its copyright laws, it was not until this year that it proposed the adoption of a
statutory right of attribution after a multi-year public consultation.
41
It bears repeating that the
relatively recent trend towards statutory codification of moral rights does not mean that these
LAW, AND PRACTICE 346 (2d ed. 2010) (“GOLDSTEIN & HUGENHOLTZ”) Emir Aly Crowne Mohammed, Moral Rights and
Mortal Rights in Canada, 4 J. INTELL. PROP. & PRAC. 261, 261 (2009).
36
See Dworkin, 19 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS at 238.
37
See Jacques de Werra, Switzerland, in MORAL RIGHTS 579 (Gillian Davies & Kevin Garnett eds., 2010) (“Werra in MORAL
RIGHTS”).
38
See CONFÉRENCE DE ROME, Acte Adopté par la Conférence Convention de Berne pour la Protection des Œuvrés Littéraires et
Artistiques du 9 Septembre 1886, Revisée a Berlin le 13 Novembre 1908 et a Rome le 2 Juin 1928 at 332–33 (signature of W.
Harrison Moore on behalf of Australia and S. G. Raymond on behalf of New Zealand), available at
http://www.wipo.int/wipolex/en/treaties/text.jsp?file_id=278725.
39
Copyright Amendment (Moral Rights) Act 2000, 2000 No. 159, pt. IX (Austl.).
40
Copyright Act 1994, 1994 No. 143, pt. 4, art. 106 (N.Z.).
41
See MINISTRY OF LAW & INTELLECTUAL PROP. OFFICE OF SING., SINGAPORE COPYRIGHT REVIEW REPORT 19–20 (Jan. 17,
2019), available at https://www.mlaw.gov.sg/content/dam/minlaw/corp/News/Press%20Release/Singapore%20
Copyright%20Review%20Report%202019/Annex%20A%20%20Copyright%20Review%20Report%2016%20Jan%202019.
pdf.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
13
jurisdictions did not previously recognize or protect moral rights,
42
just that such protection
tended to exist either in criminal statutes,
43
case law,
44
or by analogy in economic copyright law.
45
B. Variability in the Protection of Moral Rights Internationally
As the foregoing indicates, there is a significant amount of variation in how moral rights
are recognized around the world, as well as the manner in which they are protected. For
example, in addition to the rights of attribution and integrity, other countries have recognized a
number of additional moral rights, some of which are counterparts to economic rights, including:
the right of withdrawal, or droit de repentir, which allows authors to retract works from
public circulation that they feel no longer represent them or their views;
46
42
See ELIZABETH ADENEY, THE MORAL RIGHTS OF AUTHORS AND PERFORMERS: AN INTERNATIONAL AND COMPARATIVE
ANALYSIS 89–93 (2006) (discussing Romanian, Italian, Polish, Czechoslovakian, Portuguese, Swiss, and Finnish laws that
provided protection of moral interests and led to the development of Article 6bis in the Rome Text).
43
Moral rights were protected in Canada by provisions in the criminal code and by common law principles. See DAVID
VAVER, INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY LAW: COPYRIGHT, PATENTS, TRADE-MARKS 88–89 (1997). In Liberia, plagiarizing anothers
work was a crime. See 2 LIBERIAN CODE OF LAWS OF 1956, TITLES 12–26, at 921 tit. 25, ch. 2, § 35 (Cornell Univ. Press)
(1957).
44
As mentioned earlier, court cases in France recognized some protection for the rights of attribution and integrity in
the nineteenth century. See Liemer, 19 J. INTELL. PROP. L. at 111–22; STINA TEILMANN-LOCK, BRITISH AND FRENCH
COPYRIGHT: A HISTORICAL STUDY OF AESTHETIC IMPLICATIONS 134 (2009); Calvin D. Peeler, From the Providence of Kings to
Copyrighted Things (and French Moral Rights), 9 IND. INTL & COMP. L. REV. 423, 426 (1999). Australia used a smattering of
common law rights and different provisions of their Copyright Act, including a prohibition against false attribution, a
derivative works right, a tort of passing off, the tort of defamation, and contract law. See COPYRIGHT LAW REVIEW
COMM., REPORT ON MORAL RIGHTS 6–10 (1988); COPYRIGHT LAW REVIEW COMM., REPORT OF THE COMMITTEE APPOINTED BY
THE ATTORNEY-GENERAL OF THE COMMONWEALTH TO CONSIDER WHAT ALTERATIONS ARE DESIRABLE IN THE COPYRIGHT LAW OF
THE COMMONWEALTH 90 (1959).
45
The United Kingdoms pre-existing publication and adaptation rights were seen as protecting the rights of disclosure
and integrity, respectively. See Dworkin, 19 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS at232–33.
46
Such a right is recognized in, for example, Belgium, France, Germany, India, Italy, Spain, and the countries of the
Organisation Africaine de la Propriété Intellectuelle (“OAPI”). See GOLDSTEIN & HUGENHOLTZ at 354–55; Dietz, 19
COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS at 203 n.23, 205; Arathi Ashok, Moral Rights—TRIPS and Beyond: The Indian Slant, 59 J.
COPYRIGHT SOCY U.S.A. 697, 708 (2012); Robert Platt, A Comparative Survey of Moral Rights, 57 J. COPYRIGHT SOCY U.S.A.
951, 981–82 (2010). This right has been compared to the U.S. Copyright Act’s sections 203 and 304(c) termination rights.
See GOLDSTEIN & HUGENHOLTZ at 355 (“The U.S. Copyright Act’s termination of transfer provisions roughly approximate
the civil law right of recall by giving authors and their statutory successors a nonwaivable right to terminate copyright
transfers after a specified period.”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
14
the right of divulgation, through which an author can control the public disclosure of
their work, and which supports the economic right of first publication;
47
the right of the author to have access to the original copy of a work in order to
“exercise his author’s rights”;
48
the right to prevent others from associating one’s work with an undesirable “product,
service, cause or institution”;
49
the right to pseudonymity;
50
and
the right of an author to compel the completion of a commissioned work of art.
51
Additionally, not all countries protect the rights of attribution and integrity in the same
manner, and many countries have laws protecting discrete aspects of those rights using different
terminology.
52
As many scholars have noted, civil law and common law countries historically
took different approaches to the protection of authors’ moral rights: while many civil law
countries conceived of moral rights as separate and distinct from an author’s economic rights,
common law countries tended to conceive of moral rights as part and parcel of the general
47
Such a right is recognized in, for example, Egypt, France, Germany, India, and the OAPI countries. See GOLDSTEIN &
HUGENHOLTZ at 353; Ashok, 59 J. COPYRIGHT SOCY U.S.A. at 708; Heba A. Raslan, Shari’a and the Protection of Intellectual
Property―the Example of Egypt, 47 IDEA 497, 542 (2007); Platt, 57 J. COPYRIGHT SOCY U.S.A. at 977, 981–82.
48
Such a right is recognized in, for example, Switzerland. See Werra in MORAL RIGHTS at 591.
49
Such a right is recognized in, for example, Canada. See Lesley Ellen Harris, Moral Rights in Canadian Copyright Law, 34
LAWNOW 14, 15 (2010).
50
Such a right is recognized in, for example, Indonesia and the United Kingdom. See Undang-Undang Republik
Indonesia Nomor 28 Tahun 2014 tentang Hak Cipta [Law of the Republic of Indonesia Number 28 Year 2014 Copyright]
art. 5(1)(b); Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, c. 48, § 77(8) (UK); see also GUIDE TO THE BERNE CONVENTION 41.
51
Such a right is recognized in, for example, France. See Vera Zlatarski, Note, “Moral” Rights and Other Moral Interests:
Public Art Law in France, Russia, and the United States, 23 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS 201, 205–06 (1999) (referring to
recognition of the right by French courts as an extension of moral rights).
52
See, e.g., Yong Wan, Moral Rights of Authors in China, 58 J. COPYRIGHT SOCY U.S.A. 455, 475 (2011) (discussing the right
of alteration in China, which gives the author the right to alter or authorize others to alter a work); Zhiwen Liang,
Between Freedom of Commerce and Protection of Moral Rights: The Chinese Experience and a Comparative Analysis, 57 J.
COPYRIGHT SOCY U.S.A. 107, 111 (2009–10) (noting that moral rights in China include paternity and integrity, as well as
disclosure and revision/alteration rights); Josabeth A. Antonio & Jannette V. Sevilla, The Creator’s Moral Rights Under
Philippine Law, 62 PHIL. L.J. 16, 22 (1987) (discussing the right of alteration in the Philippines as separate from the right of
integrity or the right to control derivative works); Leanne Wiseman, Moral Rights in the Australian Academy: Where to
Now?, 28 U. NEW SOUTH WALES L.J. 98, 108 (2005) (discussing the Australian right to prevent false association, in
addition to the right of attribution).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
15
copyright protections afforded to an author.
53
Although the Berne Convention largely adopted
the civil law approach, conceptualizing moral rights as separate from economic rights,
54
member
states have wide discretion in how they chose to implement the moral rights protections of Article
6bis.
55
For this reason, the contours of the rights of attribution and integrity look quite different,
depending upon the country.
56
One area in which there is significant variance among countries is in how they approach
the concepts of waivability and alienability of moral rights. While moral rights are often
described as “inalienable,” “nonwaivable,” or in other terms that express the inherent
relationship between author and work, moral rights are in fact often waivable and sometimes also
alienable under many countries’ moral rights schemes.
57
In some countries like Canada,
waivability is explicitly spelled out in the statute.
58
Elsewhere, it is inferred by the ability of
authors to authorize certain uses of their works, such as in Nigeria, Germany, France, China, and
53
See, e.g., Robert C. Bird & Lucille M. Ponte, Protecting Moral Rights in the United States and the United Kingdom:
Challenges and Opportunities Under the U.K.’s New Performances Regulations, 24 B.U. INTL L.J. 213, 213–14 (2006). But see
A. G. Matveev, Models of Copyrights System, 8 WORLD ACAD. SCI., ENGINEERING & TECH. INTL J L. & POL. SCI. 2393 (2014);
Emilian Ciongaru, The Monistic and the Dualitstic Theory in European Law, 1 ACTA UNIVERSITATIS GEORGE BACOVIA.
JURIDICA 212 (2012); Özge Akun Mengenli, Does it Make a Difference to Follow Monism or Dualism?, 3 ANKARA B. REV. 85
(July 2010).
54
See Bird & Ponte, 24 B.U. INTL L.J. at 214.
55
1 RICKETSON & GINSBURG 17.81, at 1149.
56
See, e.g., Cyrill P. Rigamonti, Article, Deconstructing Moral Rights, 47 HARV. INTL L.J. 353, 380 (2006) (theorizing that
there are seven decisional rules core to any moral rights regime and that these may be rationalized differently in
different regimes).
57
See, e.g., GOLDSTEIN & HUGENHOLTZ at 355–56 (noting that “[a]though there is a popular tendency to view moral rights
as absolute, legislation in only a few countries even approaches this extreme,” as moral rights in most countries last the
same duration as an author’s economic rights, may be subject to waiver (even if not alienable), and are also subject to
exemptions); Dietz, 19 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS at 221 (1995), (discussing that “a concept of absolute inalienability and
of exclusion of waiver is not compatible with the laws of even the most fundamental moral rights countries”);
Rigamonti, 47 HARV. INTL L.J. at 380 (“[T]he element of inalienability, although absolutely central to Continental moral
rights consciousness, boils down to little more than a handful of rather narrow limitations on the content of copyright
contracts.”).
58
Copyright Act, R.S.C. 1985, c C-42, art 14.1(2)–(4) (Can.).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
16
Switzerland.
59
This ability to waive moral rights is generally tempered by limits designed to
protect authors from unwittingly or unwillingly waiving their rights.
60
Another area of variation in international approaches to moral rights has to do with how
the country’s laws treat situations where a work is “authored” by a corporation or has many
“authors” that all contribute a small piece to a larger whole.
61
In some countries that have
adopted copyright ownership rules similar to the work-for-hire doctrine in the United States,
corporations are allowed to hold and assert moral rights in such works. For example, South
Korea, Japan, and China all designate employers as the default legal author of works created by
employees, including for some moral rights purposes, although they allow the parties to contract
59
See, e.g., BANKOLE SODIPO, COPYRIGHT LAW: PRINCIPLE, PRACTICE & PROCEDURE 159 (2d ed. 2017) (SODIPO”)
(“Notwithstanding the inalienable nature of moral rights under Nigerian law, it follows that where the owner of a
moral right being aware of his right signs an agreement or does an unequivocal act affirming that he will not enforce
his right, he will be estopped from enforcing his moral right.”); Berne Convention Implementation Act of 1987: Hearings on
H.R. 1623 Before the Subcomm. on Courts, Civil Liberties, & the Admin. of Justice of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary, 100th Cong.
92 (1987–88) (1987 BCIA Hearings”) (statement of Dorothy Schrader, General Counsel, U.S. Copyright Office) (“[I]n
Germany it is common to transfer the moral right by contract.”); GOLDSTEIN & HUGENHOLTZ at 356 (“For example, while
moral rights are in civil law deemed unwaivable and nontransferable, it is generally accepted that a license granted to
adapt a work implies a degree of freedom to the adapter.”); 1987 BCIA Hearings at 327 (written statement of Kenneth W.
Dam, Vice President, Law and External Affairs, International Business Machines) (“French courts tend to enforce
contracts permitting reasonable alterations of an authors work”); Liang, 57 J. COPYRIGHT SOCY U.S.A. at 124–26
(pointing out that “[a]lthough the ability to waive moral rights under Chinese copyright law is not clear, it can be
inferred from statutes and also is recognized by judicial opinions”); Werra in MORAL RIGHTS at 595–97 (noting that the
waivability of moral rights in Switzerland often involves analysis of copyright, civil, and contract interpretation).
60
See, e.g., SODIPO at 155–61 (explaining that Nigeria’s law requires any waiver of moral rights to be unequivocal and in
writing); Werra in MORAL RIGHTS at 585 (explaining that Swiss law prohibits blanket waivers).
61
In the United States, many of these types of works are subject to the work-made-for-hire doctrine, which resolves the
issue of multiple authors by substituting a legal fiction of a single authorthe employer. See generally Catherine L. Fisk,
Authors at Work: The Origins of the Work-for-Hire Doctrine, 15 YALE J.L. & HUMAN. 1 (2003) (discussing work made for hire
practices developing early in cartography, then theater, publishing, and collaborative art works; and outlining the
rationale behind the introduction of a statutory work-made-for-hire doctrine in the 1909 Copyright Act).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
17
around this default.
62
Indian courts have also recognized moral rights for corporations.
63
In
contrast, under both Swiss and French law, moral rights can attach only to natural authors and
not corporate entities; employees may maintain or waive their rights, but employing companies
cannot hold them.
64
Several countries, including France and Israel, require that moral rights
remain with the natural author even when the law or a contract transfers economic rights away.
65
Countries have also adopted different approaches regarding how to address potential conflicts
that may arise resulting from the grant of moral rights to different contributors. For example,
Guatemalan authors contributing to newspapers do not have control of their contributions when
combined in a newspaper, but they do have rights in their works when those works stand alone.
66
62
See Copyright Act, Act No. 432, Jan. 28, 1957, amended by Act No. 14634, Mar. 21, 2017, arts. 9–10 (S. Korea);
Chosakuken Hō [Copyright Act], Law No. 48 of 1970, amended by Law No. 35 of 2014, arts. 15, 17 (Japan); Copyright
Law of the People’s Republic of China (promulgated by Order of the President of the People’s Republic of China, Feb.
26, 2010, effective Apr. 1, 2010) No. 26, art. 16, available at http://en.ncac.gov.cn/copyright/contents/10365/329083.shtml;
see also Liang, 57 J. COPYRIGHT SOCY U.S.A. at 118–21 (noting that while the right of attribution remains with the natural
author in China, employers maintain the right of integrity and may set limits on the creators attribution rights). The
Chinese work-made-for-hire situation is particularly interesting given the otherwise complete inalienability of moral
rights under Chinese law. Id. at 111–12 (“Moral rights under the Chinese Copyright Act . . . cannot be transferred to
third parties, including the heirs of an author.”).
63
See Sholay Media & Entm’t Private Ltd. v. Parag Sanghavi, Delhi HC, Aug. 24, 2015, CS (OS) 1892/2006, 20 (India)
(issuing a permanent injunction in favor of plaintiff film corporation that included an injunction “from infringing the
moral rights of the plaintiffs, and from distorting, mutilating, modifying or doing any other act that is prejudicial to the
honour and reputation of the work as well as to the plaintiffs and their work”).
64
See Werra in MORAL RIGHTS at 581 (noting that under Swiss copyright law, an author, defined as the physical person
who created the work, is the beneficiary of moral rights; meaning corporate entities “can never become legal
beneficiaries of moral rights (even if they may benefit from waivers of moral rights obtained from relevant authors”);
Marie-Andrée Weiss, Corporations Have No Moral Rights over Works in France, Even if They Commissioned It, 1709 BLOG
(Nov. 29, 2016), http://the1709blog.blogspot.fr/2016/11/corporations-have-no-moral-rights-over.html (citing Cour de
cassation [Cass.] [supreme court for judicial matters] 1e civ., Nov. 16, 2016, No. 15-22723 (Fr.)) (“[N]either the existence
of a contract of employment nor ownership of the material support of the work are likely to confer on the corporation
employing the author the enjoyment of that [moral] right.”).
65
See Marie-Andrée Weiss, Corporations Have No Moral Rights over Works in France, Even if They Commissioned It, 1709
BLOG (Nov. 29, 2016), http://the1709blog.blogspot.fr/2016/11/corporations-have-no-moral-rights-over.html; Ruth
Levush, Israel: Photographer’s Moral Right over a State-Copyrighted Photograph Recognized, LIBRARY OF CONGRESS GLOBAL
LEGAL MONITOR (Aug. 10, 2015), http://www.loc.gov/lawweb/servlet/lloc_news?disp3_l205404557_text (discussing a
2015 Israeli judicial decision confirming that, pursuant to Israeli copyright law, a state photographer retained the moral
rights in his photograph even though the state was the owner of the copyright).
66
Decreto Cong. No. 33-98, June 21, 1998, Ley de Derecho de Autor y Derechos Conexos [Law on Copyright and
Related Rights] art. 42bis, LA GACETA OFICIAL, May 21, 1998, amended by Decreto Cong. No. 11-2006, May 29, 2006,
Reformas Legales para la Implementación del Tratado de Libre Comercio República Dominicana-Centroamérica-
Estados Unidos de América [Legal Reforms for the Implementation of the Dominican Republic-Central America-United
States of America Free Trade Agreement] LA GACETA OFICIAL, May 29, 2006 (Guat.).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
18
The question of moral rights protection for multi-author works has been particularly acute
in the area of audiovisual works. Some countries have adopted special rules for moral rights in
these works, attempting to balance the interests of the producer, the director, individual
performers, and the authors of incorporated works such as musical scores. For example, while
China recognizes motion pictures as collaborative works with several individual authors, the
various authors are only granted the right of authorship while all other copyrights belong to the
producer.
67
While Guatemala grants moral rights to the producer (who is also holder of the
economic rights), this right includes mandatory attribution for the director, the script author, the
author of any underlying work, and the authors of the musical compositions in the audiovisual
work.
68
In Nigeria, which also grants moral rights to the producer, the law is designed to
encourage performers and others involved in films to execute contracts with the producer in
order to preserve any of their rights.
69
Performers in audiovisual works in France are considered
employees, and thus their rights of attribution and integrity are governed not only by the moral
rights regime, but also by employment law regulations and collective bargaining agreements.
70
In
Germany, although moral rights attach to both filmmakers and performers, a rightsholder may
only prohibit gross distortions of their work and their interests must be balanced with the
legitimate interests of the other film creators and the producer.
71
C. U.S. Accession to the Berne Convention
The United States’ accession to the Berne Convention was the culmination of many
decades of work. Almost as soon as the Berne Convention came into force, Berne member
67
See Copyright Law of the Peoples Republic of China (promulgated by Order of the President of the Peoples Republic
of China, Feb. 26, 2010, effective Apr. 1, 2010) No. 26, art. 15, available at http://en.ncac.gov.cn/copyright/contents/10365/
329083.shtml; see also Liang, 57 J. COPYRIGHT SOCY U.S.A. at 121–22.
68
See Decreto Cong. No. 33-98, June 21, 1998, Ley de Derecho de Autor y Derechos Conexos [Law on Copyright and
Related Rights] arts. 27 & 28, LA GACETA OFICIAL, May 21, 1998, amended by Decreto Cong. No. 11-2006, May 29, 2006,
Reformas Legales para la Implementación del Tratado de Libre Comercio República Dominicana-Centroamérica-
Estados Unidos de América [Legal Reforms for the Implementation of the Dominican Republic-Central America-United
States of America Free Trade Agreement] LA GACETA OFICIAL, May 29, 2006 (Guat.).
69
See Itanyi & Nwamaka, 14 U.S.-CHINA L. REV. at 627–28 (referring to section 9(4) of the Nigerian copyright law).
70
See Marjut Salokannel, Study on Audiovisual Performers’ Contracts and Remuneration Practices in France and Germany,
WIPO DOC. AVP/IM/03/3B, at 3–4, 21 (Mar. 31, 2003). French law regulates the relationship between authors’ rights,
including directors and producers, and related rights, such as the rights of performers. Because related rights cannot
prejudice authors’ rights under French law, performers’ cannot usurp control from film authors, thus addressing
directors concerns with maintain creative control of the end product. Id. at 4.
71
See Dietz, 19 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS at 223 (citing article 93 of the German copyright act); see also GOLDSTEIN &
HUGENHOLTZ at 357 (pointing out how civil law countries, such as France and Germany, accommodate moral rights in
the motion picture realm).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
19
countries were urging the United States to join.
72
The United States had been attending the
conferences related to the Berne Convention since the second conference discussing creation of an
international copyright union in 1885.
73
The United States continued to participate as an observer
at subsequent conferences of the Berne Union Members, including the 1908 Berlin Conference
where the original convention was revised.
74
But while U.S. interest in joining the Berne
Convention was reflected in two major bills introduced in the 1930s, the United States did not
accede to the Berne Convention until 1988.
1. Efforts to Join the Berne Convention
During the 1930s, two major pieces of legislation were proposed to implement the Rome
Text, and enable the United States to accede to the Berne Convention. Both were unsuccessful.
The first bill, introduced by Senator Bronson M. Cutting in 1933, included brief language
explicitly protecting attribution and integrity rights, without any caveats.
75
Several groups
opposed joining the Berne Convention if it required an explicit recognition of moral rights—
including motion-picture producers and distributors, periodical publishers, and radio
broadcasters.
76
The motion picture industry in particular objected to incorporating the right of
72
See Tabl e Talk, LITERARY WORLD, Sept. 27, 1895, reprinted in 52 LITERARY WORLD 220, 222 (James Clarke & Co. JULYDec.
1895) (“It would be a great gain to British authors if the United States Government would announce its adherence to the
‘Berne Convention’[.]”); Hall Caine on Copyright, LITERARY WORLD, Nov. 15, 1895, reprinted in 52 LITERARY WORLD, 395,
395 (James Clarke & Co. JULY–Dec. 1895) (citing a speech of British author Hall Caine gave in Toronto on October 25,
1895, in which he stated that the “one great country which has not yet entered into the Berne Convention . . . is your
neighbour, the United States”).
73
LIBRARY OF CONGRESS COPYRIGHT OFFICE, INTERNATIONAL COPYRIGHT UNION: REPORT OF THE DELEGATE OF THE UNITED
STATES TO THE INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE FOR THE REVISION OF THE BERNE COPYRIGHT CONVENTION, HELD AT BERLIN,
GERMANY, OCTOBER 14 TO NOVEMBER 14, 1908, COPYRIGHT OFF. BULL. NO. 13, at 9 (1908) (indicating that the United States
participated at the second meeting of the International Union for the Protection of Works of Literature and Art as a
“listening delegate”).
74
See id at 10–11 (pointing out that the German government, as hosts of the Berlin conference, invited twenty non-union
countries to attend the conference because “delegates from nonunion countries would at all events contribute to arouse
and increase interest in the Berne Union and its beneficial work”).
75
See A Bill to Enable the United States to Enter the International Copyright Union, S. 1928, 73d Cong. § 4 (1933) (“[T]he
author of any copyrighted work, even after the assignment of the copyright in such work, shall at all times have the
right to claim the authorship of his work, and the right to oppose every distortion, mutilation, or other modification of
the said work which might be prejudicial to his honor or his reputation, as well as the right to restrain the publication
and/or the performance of the mutilated work.”).
76
See Letter from Thorvald Solberg, Register of Copyrights (1897–1930), to Sen. Bronson Cutting (May 30, 1934) (on file
with the Library of Congress in the Bronson M. Cutting Papers);LIBRARY OF CONGRESS COPYRIGHT OFFICE, THIRTY-
SEVENTH ANNUAL REPORT OF THE REGISTER OF COPYRIGHTS FOR THE FISCAL YEAR ENDING JUNE 30, 1934, at 7–9 (1934)
(“THIRTY-SEVENTH ANNUAL REPORT”); Film Men Fight Copyright Bill, L.A. TIMES, May 30, 1934, at 4. In 1934, The Senate
Committee on Foreign Relations held a series of restricted and public hearings on the United States potential joining of
the Berne Convention. They heard from a variety of stakeholders and witnesses who both supported and opposed the
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
20
integrity because “some modification of a work is often necessary to adjust it to the requirements
of screen production.”
77
The second major bill was introduced by Senator F. Ryan Duffy in 1935, and it also
included explicit moral rights protections, this time with carve outs for contractual override,
exceptions to the right of integrity for certain industries, and a proviso protecting existing
common law and equitable remedies.
78
The Dramatists’ Guild and the American Association of
Book Publishers both objected to the moral rights provision.
79
The American Association of Book
Publishers suggested amendments to the bill that would leave any changes required by the moral
rights provisions in Berne to be handled by contracts rather than by statute.
80
Authors, on the
other hand, “desired provisions that would make it less easy for publishers to edit, arrange, or
adapt their works without their express consent.”
81
The exception to the right of integrity for
certain industries was, however, supported by the Motion Picture Producers and Distributors of
America who stated, “Without restriction of the moral rights of authors, our industry is lost.”
82
Music publishers also wished for the exception to be extended to their industry.
83
The Duffy bill
died in 1936.
United States joining Berne. See THIRTY-SEVENTH ANNUAL REPORT at 7–9 (1934); see generally International Copyright
Union: Hearings Before the S. Comm. on Foreign Relations on S. 1928, A Bill to Enable the United States to Enter the
International Copyright Union, 73d Cong. pt. 2, at 23 (1934).
77
THIRTY-SEVENTH ANNUAL REPORT at 8.
78
See An Act to Amend and Consolidate the Acts Respecting Copyright, S. 3047, 74th Cong. § 23 (1935).
79
See LIBRARY OF CONGRESS COPYRIGHT OFFICE, THIRTY-NINTH ANNUAL REPORT OF THE REGISTER OF COPYRIGHTS FOR THE
FISCAL YEAR ENDING JUNE 30, 1936, at 10–11 (1936) (“THIRTY-NINTH ANNUAL REPORT”); see also Revision of Copyright Laws:
Hearings Before the H. Comm. on Patents, 74th Cong. 1417 (1936) (“Revision of Copyright Laws Hearings) (statement of
Edwin P. Kilroe, Attorney, Fox Picture Corporation, Motion Picture Producers’ Association) (noting that “[w]ithout
restriction of the moral rights of authors, our industry is lost. We must, by the very nature of our business, make
changes in stories and plays. We have to meet censorship laws, and we have to meet various laws throughout the
country, and unless we have the right to make those changes, we are completely at the mercy of the authors”); Elmer
Davis, Vice President, Authors League, Letter to the Editor, Case Against the Duffy Bill, SATURDAY REV., Apr. 4, 1936, at 9
(the Authors’ League objected to joining the Berne Convention altogether).
80
THIRTY-NINTH ANNUAL REPORT at 11.
81
Letter from Wallace McClure, Chairman, Inter-Departmental Comm. on Copyright, to Sen. F. Ryan Duffy (May 1,
1937) (on file with the Wisconsin Historical Society).
82
Letter from Wallace McClure, Chairman, Inter-Departmental Comm. on Copyright, to Sen. F. Ryan Duffy (May 18,
1935) (on file with the Wisconsin Historical Society) (quoting a motion picture representatives testimony during an
executive session with the Senate Committee on Patents on May 8, 1935; discussing S. 2465, 74th Cong. (1935), a
precursor to S. 3047).
83
See Letter from Wallace McClure, Chairman, Inter-Departmental Comm. on Copyright, to Sen. F. Ryan Duffy (May 31,
1935) (on file with the Wisconsin Historical Society) (discussing S. 2465, 74th Cong. (1935), a precursor to S. 3047).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
21
Momentum for amending U.S. copyright law and ratifying the Berne Convention was
soon overtaken by World War II.
84
By 1950, focus in the United States had moved away from
joining the Berne Convention to exploring a new copyright agreement being negotiated through
the auspices of the United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization
(“UNESCO”).
85
These negotiations would ultimately lead to the creation of the Universal
Copyright Convention (“UCC”) in 1952, which did not contain any provisions on moral rights.
86
Thereafter, in 1956, Congress and the U.S. Copyright Office initiated an extensive review of the
U.S. copyright law necessary for a planned full revision of the Copyright Act of 1909.
87
With a
full review of domestic copyright laws underway and international copyright protection for U.S.
works secured through a variety of bilateral agreements and the UCC, Congress paid little
attention to the Berne Convention and its moral rights article again until the late 1970s.
No sooner had the brand new Copyright Act of 1976 come into force in 1978 than serious
conversations about the United States joining the Berne Convention were re-started.
88
That year,
Register of Copyrights Barbara Ringer attended a meeting at the World Intellectual Property
Organization (“WIPO”)
89
to analyze whether the new United States copyright law was compatible
with the Berne Convention, where she reported receiving questions about a number of issues,
including “the lack of express protection for the moral rights of authors in the U.S. statute.”
90
By
this time, the Berne Convention had reached its (to date) final revision, in Paris in 1971, and
article 6bis read, in pertinent part:
84
A Committee for the Study of Copyright planned a series of conferences regarding revision of the copyright law and
a draft bill for complete revision of the copyright law was introduced in the Senate in January 1940, but copyright
review halted. Following World War II, the United States did not turn back to domestic copyright revision until 1955.
See U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, EIGHTIETH ANNUAL REPORT OF THE REGISTER OF COPYRIGHTS FOR THE FISCAL YEAR ENDING
SEPTEMBER 30, 1977, at 8 (1978).
85
See U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, FIFTY-FOURTH ANNUAL REPORT OF THE REGISTER OF COPYRIGHTS FOR THE FISCAL YEAR ENDING
JUNE 20, 1951, at 4–5 (1952).
86
See U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, FIFTY-SIXTH ANNUAL REPORT OF THE REGISTER OF COPYRIGHTS FOR THE FISCAL YEAR ENDING
JUNE 30, 1953, at 1 (1954); see generally Universal Copyright Convention, Sept. 6, 1952, 6 U.S.T. 2731, 216 U.N.T.S. 132
(“UCC”).
87
See U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, FIFTY-NINTH ANNUAL REPORT OF THE REGISTER OF COPYRIGHTS FOR THE FISCAL YEAR ENDING
JUNE 30, 1956, at 5 (1956).
88
See LIBRARY OF CONGRESS, ANNUAL REPORT OF THE LIBRARIAN OF CONGRESS FOR THE FISCAL YEAR ENDING SEPTEMBER 30,
1978, at 92 (1979) (“1977–78 ANNUAL REPORT”) (“It seems likely that future copyright historians will mark 1978 as the
year in which concerted efforts to achieve U.S. adherence to the International Convention for the Protection of Literary
and Artistic Property (the Berne Convention) began anew.”).
89
WIPO is “the global forum for intellectual property services, policy, information and cooperation” within the United
Nations. Inside WIPO, WIPO, http://www.wipo.int/about-wipo/en/. It is self-funded and has 191 member states,
including the United States. See id.
90
1977–78 ANNUAL REPORT at 93.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
22
Independently of the author's economic rights, and even after the transfer of the said
rights, the author shall have the right to claim authorship of the work and to object to any
distortion, mutilation or other modification of, or other derogatory action in relation to,
the said work, which would be prejudicial to his honor or reputation.
91
In the late 1980s, members of Congress began to introduce bills to facilitate the United
States joining the Berne Convention. At least one of the proffered bills included express statutory
protections for moral rights.
92
Other bills expressly declared that protections for moral rights
would be unaffected by adherence to the Berne Convention.
93
Familiar discussions on whether
legislative changes were necessary for the United States to join the Berne Convention, including
whether changes were required to implement the moral rights provision, resumed.
94
As part of
these discussions, the U.S. State Department urged the establishment of an Ad Hoc Working
Group to identify and analyze provisions in U.S. law relevant to Berne adherence.
95
The Ad Hoc
Working Group, comprised of copyright professionals working in their private capacity,
determined that, while there were no explicit moral rights provisions in title 17, U.S. law was
91
Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artist Works, art. 6bis(1), Sept. 9, 1886, as revised July 24, 1971,
1161 U.N.T.S. 3 (“Paris Text”).
92
See, e.g., Berne Convention Implementation Act of 1987, H.R. 1623, 100th Cong. § 7(a) (1987):
§106a. Moral rights of the author
Independently of the copyright in a work other than a work made for hire, and even after transfer of copyright
ownership, the author of the work or the authors successor in interest shall the right, during the life of the author
and fifty years after the authors death
(1) to claim authorship of the work; and
(2) to object to any distortion, mutilation, or other alteration of the work that would prejudice the authors
honor or reputation.
The rights conferred by this section shall be referred to in this title as “moral rights.”
93
See, e.g., Berne Convention Implementation Act of 1988, H.R. 4262, 100th Cong. § 4(b) (1988):
(b) Certain Rights Not Affected.—The adherence of the United States to the Berne Convention does not expand or
reduce any right of an author of a work
(1) to claim authorship of the work; or
(2) to object to any distortion, mutilation, or other modification of, or other derogatory action in relation to,
the work, that would prejudice the authors honor or reputation.
94
See, e.g., 1987 BCIA Hearings at 91 (statement of Rep. Carlos Moorhead) (“This is a very important point to us in
California where you can’t get a motion picture studio to buy a play or a book unless they can make a picture that they
can make some money on. And if it’s going to be totally controlled throughout the process by the person that sold their
rights, it could certainly cut down the value to the producer of the picture.”).
95
See AD HOC WORKING GRP. ON U.S. ADHERENCE TO THE BERNE CONVENTION, FINAL REPORT 2 (1986), reprinted in 10
COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS 513, 554 (1986) (“AD HOC WORKING GRP.”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
23
nonetheless compatible with the Berne Convention through the protections afforded by a
combination of existing federal and state laws, as well as various common law principles.
96
The United States acceded to Berne in 1988 after passage of the Berne Convention
Implementation Act (“BCIA”).
97
When considering whether the United States’ legal framework
adequately provided moral rights protections, Congress drew upon the Ad Hoc Working Group’s
analysis of existing moral rights protections, as well as congressional testimony and international
copyright experts’ conclusions.
98
The majority of those who testified before Congress argued
against any change to U.S. law concerning an author’s right to control attribution or the integrity
of a work, stating that current U.S. law was sufficient.
99
For example, a representative of Walt
Disney Productions testified that “developments in the laws of unfair competition, trademark,
privacy, [the section 106 right to prepare derivative works, the law of defamation], and the like”
precluded the need for new statutory moral rights.
100
Additionally, then-Director General of
WIPO, Arpad Bogsch, explained that the United States could become a Member of Berne without
making any changes to U.S. law for the purposes of implementing article 6bis.
101
While many
copyright stakeholders argued that U.S. law provided Berne-compliant moral rights, some
witnesses argued that existing law “simply isn’t [sufficient].”
102
They pointed out that common
law principles such as defamation failed to provide consistent protection of a creator’s right of
integrity, short of “extreme cases of blatant and outrageous misrepresentations.”
103
Similarly,
state moral rights statutes were criticized as being few in number; the Lanham Act was criticized
as providing “insufficient [remedies] to meet the goals of Berne”; and the proponents’ reliance on
96
See id. at 554.
97
Berne Notification No. 121: Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic Works: Accession by the United States
of America, WORLD INTELLECTUAL PROP. ORG. (Nov. 17, 1988), available at
https://www.wipo.int/treaties/en/notifications/berne/treaty_berne_121.html.
98
See H.R. REP. NO. 100-609, at 37–38 (1988).
99
See id. at 33 (noting that “[t]he great majority [of congressional witnesses] testified that the United States should
adhere to Berne, and that no additional law-making was needed to satisfy the standard of Article 6bis”); see also 1987
BCIA Hearings at 692 (written statement of Barbara Ringer, former Director, Copyright Division, UNESCO; former
Register of Copyrights, U.S. Copyright Office (1973–80)) (“[C]urrent U.S. legislation and jurisprudence, especially the
common law, are fully sufficient to meet our obligations under Berne without the need for federal statutory provisions
on the so-called ‘moral right.’”); id. at 244 (statement of Kenneth W. Dam, Vice President, Law and External Relations,
IBM) (“[C]urrent U.S. protection of moral rights is fully compatible with article 6 bis of Berne.”).
100
1987 BCIA Hearings at 230 (statement of Peter Nolan, Vice President and General Counsel, Walt Disney Productions,
on behalf of the Motion Picture Association of America); see also id. at 233.
101
See Letter from Arpad Bogsch, Dir. Gen., World Intellectual Property Organization, to Irwin Karp, Esq. (June 16,
1987), reprinted in 1987 BCIA Hearings at 213–14.
102
1987 BCIA Hearings at 408 (statement of Sydney Pollack, Directors’ Guild of America).
103
Id.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
24
evolving case law was deemed “largely speculative.”
104
The Register of Copyrights, in his
testimony on the BCIA, did not take a position on the question of whether or how to implement
article 6bis, other than to note the importance of the issue.
105
Congress acknowledged both viewpoints, but ultimately concluded that existing U.S. laws
provided protections substantively equivalent to moral rights, and therefore the United States
fully complied with the requirements of article 6bis through a “composite,” “mélange,” or
“patchwork” of laws.
106
2. The Moral Rights Patchwork
Congress’ conclusion that there was “a composite of laws in this country that provides the
kind of protection envisioned by Article 6bis
107
identified a number of legal routes by which an
aggrieved author-plaintiff could pursue moral rights-like claims under federal and state law.
These included:
preventing false attribution under section 43(a) of the Lanham Act;
108
adjusting their moral rights vis-à-vis specific works, through guild agreements or
party-negotiated contracts;
authors’ exclusive right to create and authorize derivative works;
109
restrictions on compulsory licensees’ right to arrange musical works recorded and
distributed under a mechanical license;
110
104
Id. See also 1987 BCIA Hearings at 443 (written statement of William Pierson, Writers Guild of America) (arguing that
the Lanham Act “only allows a disclaimer,” which does not provide adequate integrity rights); id. at 446–49 (statement
of William A. Smith, Academician, National Academy of Design) (noting that after his mural was altered and still
attributed to him, “[n]either our common law, nor U.S. statutory law provide[d] me redress; in any Berne Convention
member nation I would surely have such redress”).
105
See 1987 BCIA Hearings at 48 (written statement of Ralph Oman, Register of Copyrights and Assistant Librarian for
Copyright Services, Library of Congress) (“It should be stressed that careful Congressional examination of moral rights
is essential.”).
106
H.R. REP. NO. 100-609, at 34 (1988). See also Vis ual Artists Ri ghts Act of 1989: Hearing on H.R. 2690 Before the Subcomm.
on Courts, Intellectual Prop., & the Admin. of Justice of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary, 101st Cong. 104 (1989) (“1989 VARA
Hearing) (statement of John B. Koegel, Esq.); Ilhyung Lee, To w a r d a n A m e rican Moral Rights in Copyright, 58 WASH. &
LEE. L. REV. 795, 800 (2001).
107
H.R. REP. NO. 100-609, at 34 (1988).
108
See 15 U.S.C. § 1125(a).
109
See 17 U.S.C. § 106(2).
110
See 17 U.S.C. § 115(a)(2).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
25
terminating or transferring licenses;
111
state statutes protecting authorship and integrity rights in certain works;
112
and
state laws covering privacy and publicity, contracts, fraud and misrepresentation,
unfair competition, and defamation.
113
Since passage of the BCIA, there have been two important additions to the U.S. moral
rights patchwork.
114
The first is the Visual Artists Rights Act of 1990, known as VARA, which
grants authors of certain “work[s] of visual art” the right to claim or disclaim authorship in the
work, as well as a limited right to prevent distortion, mutilation, or modification of a work that is
of recognized stature.
115
The second is section 1202 of title 17—enacted in 1998 as part of the
Digital Millennium Copyright Act—which limits the removal, alteration, or falsification of certain
categories of information regarding a copyrighted work, including the name of the author of the
work.
116
Both VARA and section 1202 are discussed in detail in Section IV of this Study.
D. Post-Berne Developments: New WIPO Treaties
In 1996, WIPO finalized two new treaties which aimed to update international copyright
norms for the digital environment: the WIPO Copyright Treaty (“WCT”) and the WIPO
111
See 17 U.S.C. § 203.
112
See H.R. REP. NO. 100-609, at 34 (1988) (citing California, Louisiana, Maine, Massachusetts, New Jersey, New York,
Pennsylvania, and Rhode Island as examples).
113
See id. at 34.
114
Not included in Congress’ list of provisions that, in combination, provide moral rights-like protections was the
National Film Preservation Act (“NFPA”) of 1988, which required that films added to the National Film Registry must
display a notice during distribution or exhibition if they had been “materially altered” without the director,
screenwriter, or other creators’ participation, a designation that included colorization of black–and-white films. Pub. L.
No. 100-446, § 4, 102 Stat. 1774, 1784–85 (1988) (codified at 2 U.S.C. §§ 178–178l), repealed by Copyright Amendments Act
of 1992, Pub. L. No. 102-307, § 214, 106 Stat. 264, 272 (1992). By requiring a label to warn consumers that a film had
been altered without permission, the NFPA allowed some creators to “disclaim responsibility” and establish a form of
“anti-attribution” for their edited works. 3 MELVILLE B. NIMMER & DAVID NIMMER, NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 8D.02[D][3]
(3d ed. 2017) (“NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT”). This notice requirement did not survive when the NFPA was reauthorized in
1992, and thus lasted a mere four years. See Copyright Amendments Act of 1992, Pub. L. No. 102-307, §§ 201–214, 106
Stat. 264, 267–72 (1992) (codified at 2 U.S.C. §§ 179–179k), repealed by Pub. L. No. 104-285, 110 Stat. 3382 (1996).
115
VARA, Pub. L. No. 101-650, §§ 602–603, 104 Stat. 5128, 5128–30 (1990) (codified at 17 U.S.C. §§ 101, 106A(a)).
116
See DMCA, Pub. L. No. 105-304, § 103, 122 Stat. 2860, 2872–73 (1998) (codified as amended at 17 U.S.C. § 1202(a)–(c)).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
26
Performances and Phonograms Treaty (“WPPT”).
117
The United States signed both treaties in
1997, and ratified the treaties in 1999.
118
Both treaties entered into force in 2002.
119
Of particular interest, article 5 of the WPPT provides for moral rights for performers in
their “live aural performances or performances fixed in phonograms.”
120
The Senate Foreign
Relations Committee, when presenting the treaties to the full Senate for advice and consent,
explained that performers’ moral rights could be covered by the existing patchwork of
protections in the United States, the understanding of which had been pieced together during the
time of Berne implementation.
121
117
WIPO Copyright Treaty, Dec. 20, 1996, S. TREATY DOC. NO. 105-17, 2186 U.N.T.S. 121 (WCT”); WIPO Performances
and Phonograms Treaty, Dec. 20, 1996, S. TREATY DOC. NO. 105-17, 2186 U.N.T.S. 203 (“WPPT”).
118
See S. TREATY DOC. NO. 105-17, at III (1997); WCT Notification No. 10: WIPO Copyright Treaty: Ratification by the United
States of America, WIPO (Sept. 14, 1999), available at https://www.wipo.int/treaties/en/notifications/wct/
treaty_wct_10.html; WPPT Notification No. 8: WIPO Performances and Phonograms Treaty: Ratification by the United States
of America, WIPO (Sept. 14, 1999), available at https://www.wipo.int/treaties/en/notifications/wppt/treaty_wppt_8.html.
119
WCT Notification No. 32: WIPO Copyright Treaty: Entry into Force, WIPO (Dec. 6, 2001), available at
https://www.wipo.int/treaties/en/notifications/wct/ treaty_wct_32.html; WPPT Notification No. 32: WIPO Performances
and Phonograms Treaty: Entry into Force, WIPO (Feb. 20, 2002), available at https://www.wipo.int/treaties/en/
notifications/wct/treaty_wct_32.html.
120
WIPO Performances and Phonograms Treaty, art. 5, Dec. 20, 1996, S. TREATY DOC. NO. 105-17, 2186 U.N.T.S. 203.
Article 5(1) reads as follows:
Independently of a performers economic rights, and even after the transfer of those rights, the
performer shall, as regards his live aural performances or performances fixed in phonograms, have
the right to claim to be identified as the performer of his performances, except where omission is
dictated by the manner of the use of the performance, and to object to any distortion, mutilation or
other modification of his performances that would be prejudicial to his reputation.
121
See S. EXEC. REP. NO. 105-25, at 10 (1998) (“This deference to national law may allow the United States to rely upon a
patchwork of existing state laws and the federal trademark law as the legal basis for satisfying the Treaty obligation,
without enacting new federal legislation.”). Similar discussions about moral rights did not need to occur with the
ratification that same decade of two other treaties involving copyright—both the North America Free Trade Agreement
(“NAFTA”) and the World Trade Organization (“WTO”) Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property
Rights (“TRIPS”) incorporate Berne but not Article 6bisbecause these were trade agreements and moral rights are
non-economic and therefore not related to trade. See U.S. GEN. ACCOUNTING OFFICE, NORTH AMERICAN FREE TRADE
AGREEMENT: ASSESSMENT OF MAJOR ISSUES REPORT TO THE CONGRESS, VOLUME I, at 95 (1993); IFAC-3, REPORT ON THE
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY CHAPTER AND OTHER INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY-RELATED ELEMENTS OF THE NORTH AMERICAN FREE
TRADE AGREEMENT (NAFTA) 9 (1992) (“As in the . . . [draft TRIPS text] the NAFTA copyright obligations do not extend
to moral rights but only to the economic rights provided in the Berne Convention. This exclusion recognizes the
undeveloped nature of what constitutes moral rights violations in Berne countries and that they are not trade-related.”);
Intellectual Property and International Issues: Hearings Before the Subcomm. on Intellectual Prop. & Judicial Admin. of the H.
Comm. on the Judiciary, 102d Cong. 350–51 (1991) (written statement of Eric M. Smith, General Counsel, International
Intellectual Property Alliance) (“Unlike the well-understood economic rights in Berne that must govern the
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
27
Furthermore, both the WCT (article 12) and the WPPT (article 19) also contained
obligations concerning rights management information (“RMI”). Congress added section 1202 to
title 17 to implement these RMI obligations in October of 1998.
122
The Senate gave its advice and
consent to the ratification of both of these treaties in 1998, and they were ratified the following
year.
123
In 2012, after many years of negotiations, WIPO completed the Beijing Treaty on
Audiovisual Performances (“Beijing Treaty”). Article 5 of the Beijing Treaty grants performers
rights of attribution and integrity in their live and fixed audiovisual performances.
124
The United
States is a signatory to the treaty but has not yet ratified it. President Obama’s administration
transmitted the Treaty to the Senate Committee on Foreign Relations for advice and consent in
2016.
125
The Administration also submitted to Congress additional legislation that addressed
“limited statutory changes for the United States to implement the Treaty.”
126
This legislative
proposal did not include any statutory changes that would address issues related to moral
rights.
127
There was no legislative proposal on the Beijing Treaty pending before the 115th
Congress, which ended its session on January 3, 2019, and no such legislative proposal has yet
been introduced in the 116th Congress.
III. GUIDING PRINCIPLES FOR REVIEW OF MORAL RIGHTS REGIME
In its review of the results of the moral rights symposium and the written comments
submitted as part of this Study, the Copyright Office identified three general principles to guide
its analysis of the current U.S. moral rights regime. The first is the need to harmonize any
international trade in protected works, moral rights are non-economic, non-trade related in purpose and in operation
and are inappropriate for inclusion as a mandatory rule in a GATT agreement.).
122
See DMCA, § 103 Pub. L. No. 105-304, 122 Stat. 2860, 2872–74 (1998) (codified as amended at 17 U.S.C. § 1202). Title I
of the DMCA was known as the WIPO Copyright and Performances and Phonograms Treaties Implementation Act of
1998. It amended title 17 to add a new chapter 12, which prohibits circumvention of copyright protection systems and
provides protection for copyright management information.
123
See Resolution of Ratification: Senate Consideration of Treaty Doc. No. 105-17 (1998); WCT Notification No. 10: WIPO
Copyright Treaty: Ratification by the United States of America, WIPO (Sept. 14, 1999), available at
https://www.wipo.int/treaties/en/notifications/wct/treaty_wct_10.html; WPPT Notification No. 8: WIPO Performances and
Phonograms Treaty: Ratification by the United States of America, WIPO (Sept. 14, 1999), available at
https://www.wipo.int/treaties/en/notifications/wppt/treaty_wppt_8.html.
124
Beijing Treaty on Audiovisual Performances, art. 5, June 24, 2012 (not yet in force).
125
See S. TREATY DOC. NO. 114-8 (2016).
126
Letter from John F. Kerry, Sec’y of State, to President Barack Obama (Jan. 22, 2016), in S. TREATY DOC. NO. 114-8, at vi
(2016).
127
Letter from Michelle K. Lee, Under Sec’y of Commerce for Intellectual Prop. & Dir. of the U.S. Patent & Trademark
Office, to Joseph R. Biden, President of the Senate (Feb. 26, 2016), available at http://www.uspto.gov/sites/default/files/
documents/Beijing-treaty-package.pdf.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
28
proposals with certain foundational precepts of U.S. law, namely the First Amendment, fair use,
and respect for the constitutional requirement of limited copyright terms. The second is
acknowledging the critical importance of the attribution and integrity rights to authors. The third
is the importance of recognizing that, due to the diversity among creative industries and
categories of works, one size of moral rights protections cannot fit all industries.
A. Respect for Foundational Principles of U.S. Law
In considering possible changes or additions to the moral rights scheme in the United
States, the Copyright Office believes any modifications must align with other aspects of U.S. law.
In particular, any changes to the law must comport with the First Amendment, fair use, and
constitutional requirement of limited copyright terms.
1. Moral Rights and the First Amendment
The First Amendment is a fundamental constitutional protection guaranteeing the right of
free speech.
128
Copyright law works in concert with the First Amendment to further the goals of
protecting and promoting free speech and original expression. As the Supreme Court said in
1985, “[T]he Framers intended copyright itself to be the engine of free expression.
129
To that end,
copyright law also includes important safeguards to ensure the free speech rights of secondary
users—notably the fair use exception and the idea/expression dichotomy.
130
In response to the Office’s Notice of Inquiry, some commenters raised concerns that
adoption of stronger protections for moral rights in the United States could not be harmonized
with the First Amendment,
131
or that such laws would weaken current First Amendment
protections, particularly with regard to critiques or criticisms of a work. For example,
commenters asked that the Office consider the possibility that a right of integrity would impose
an additional legal chilling effect on those publishers, authors, and scholars who critique the
work of another author in a way that may damage the initial author’s reputation.
132
Another
128
U.S. CONST. amend. I (“Congress shall make no law respecting an establishment of religion, or prohibiting the free
exercise thereof; or abridging the freedom of speech, or of the press; or the right of the people peaceably to assemble,
and to petition the Government for a redress of grievances.”).
129
Harper & Row, Publishers, Inc. v. Nation Enters., 471 U.S. 539, 558 (1985).
130
See Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186, 219–20 (2003) (discussing the idea/expression dichotomy and the fair use doctrine
as free speech safeguards).
131
See Wendy J. Gordon, Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at
2 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“The only way to stop the incursions on free speech is to stop the creation and expansion of new
private rights to control speech. So-called ‘moral rights’ can give authors precisely that dangerous and unwise
power.”).
132
See Association of American Publishers (“AAP”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan.
23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 9 (Mar. 30, 2017) (AAP Initial Comments”) (noting that “moral rights would pose
significant hurdles” to scholars who criticize anothers work); Library Copyright Alliance (“LCA), Comments
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
29
commenter also suggested that a statutory right of attribution could violate the First Amendment
by compelling speech, specifically by requiring a corporate author to identify all of the creative
contributors to a work.
133
Commenters put forth several suggestions for potential means of ensuring free speech
protections under an enhanced moral rights regime. One commenter asserted that “[t]o ensure
free speech protections, the original author should bear the burden of proof when claiming
infringement of the right of integrity.”
134
The same commenter, and others, suggested
establishing a reasonableness standard that would work to prevent frivolous moral rights claims
and protect speech.
135
A number of commenters also discussed how the moral rights of
attribution and integrity can actually work to protect free speech rights of authors. The right of
integrity, and to a lesser extent the right of attribution, can protect an authors right not to speak
by ensuring that creative works are not modified or used in a way that the author fundamentally
disagrees with or disavows.
136
Existing protections for attribution and integrity interests in U.S. law have been
implemented consistent with the First Amendment.
137
And, while the Office recognizes that
Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 3 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“LCA Initial
Comments”) (stating that additional moral rights “would chill criticism“). But see Creators’ Rights Alliance (“CRA),
Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 2 (May 15, 2017)
(“CRA Reply Comments”) (stating that “this is to misread” Article 6bis of the Berne Convention and explaining that
proving a use is “prejudicial to [the author’s] honor or reputation” is a high bar).
133
See Motion Picture Association of America, Inc. (“MPAA”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright
Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 11 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“MPAA Initial Comments”) (citing U.S. Agency for Int’l Dev.
v. All. for Open Soc’y Int’l, Inc., 570 U.S. 205, 213 (2013) (“It is . . . a basic First Amendment principle that ‘freedom of
speech prohibits the government from telling people what they must say.’”). But see Music Creators of North America,
Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 4–5 (Mar. 30, 2017)
(“Music Creators Initial Comments”) (suggesting that moral rights could be used to prevent compelled speech).
134
Future of Music Coalition (“FMC”), Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017,
Notice of Inquiry at 8 (May 15, 2017) (“FMC Reply Comments”).
135
See FMC Reply Comments at 9 (“To further protect free speech, a reasonableness benchmark could be
established[.]”). See Authors Alliance, Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice
of Inquiry at 6 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“Authors Alliance Initial Comments”) (“A robust ‘reasonableness’ limitation on integrity
and attribution rights should also be in place to prevent these rights from stifling onward creativity.); Jani
McCutcheon, Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 3 (Mar. 6,
2017) (“[I]t may be desirable to introduce a reasonableness defense, similar to that existing in Australian moral rights
legislation.”).
136
See, Authors Guild, Inc., Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of
Inquiry at 7-8 (May 15, 2017) (“Authors Guild Reply Comments”) (explaining that writers’ bad experiences with the
editing process” prompts a desire for an integrity right).
137
For example, in cases involving expressive works, courts have formulated tests for reconciling First Amendment
concerns with the application of both state right of publicity claims and false attribution claims under the Lanham Act.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
30
enhanced moral rights protections could potentially create new tensions with the right of free
speech, it does not see these tensions as inevitable or irreparable. At a minimum, for example,
further statutory codification of moral rights could easily be limited by both the fair use exception
and the idea/expression dichotomy.
138
2. Moral Rights and Fair Use
Reconciling the First Amendment with moral rights protections raises the related issue of
how more explicit protections for moral rights could implicate the fair use doctrine, a vital First
Amendment safeguard. The fair use doctrine works to balance the ability of authors to control
the use of their copyrighted works with the free speech interests of secondary users. Fair use also
enables scholarship and criticism of existing works by allowing authors to use not only the facts
and ideas of a work but the expression of that work itself.
139
Even prior to its statutory
codification, the fair use doctrine allowed courts to “avoid rigid application of the copyright
statute when, on occasion, it would stifle the very creativity which that law is designed to
foster.”
140
Fair use furthers the goals of copyright law by simultaneously promoting a robust
marketplace of ideas while also incentivizing authors to create new works that build or comment
upon existing ones. However, more explicit protections for the rights of integrity and attribution
in the United States may create tensions with the fair use doctrine, depending upon how these
protections are implemented.
While fair use allows secondary users to criticize, comment on, or parody an original work
without facing liability for infringement, the moral right of integrity protects an author’s work
against any “derogatory action” that is damaging to the author’s honor or reputation.
Consequently, the Office heard some concern regarding “how a statutory right of integrity. . .
would bode with a court’s ability to make a fair use determination.”
141
At least one commenter
also raised concerns about reconciling the fair use doctrine with the right of attribution,
expressing concern that an attribution right “would conflict with many ordinary practices of
citation, and would threaten standard quotations and fair uses.”
142
Some commenters also raised
See, e.g., Hoffman v. Capital Cities/ABC, Inc., 255 F.3d 1180, 1186 (9th Cir. 2001); Rogers v. Grimaldi, 875 F.2d 994, 998–99 (2d
Cir. 1989).
138
See, e.g., FMC Reply Comments at 8–9; Kernochan Center for Law, Media and the Arts, Comments Submitted in
Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 9 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“Kernochan Center Initial
Comments”); National Writers Union (“NWU”) & Science Fiction and Fantasy Writers of America (“SFWA”), Joint
Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 6 (Mar. 20, 2017)
(“NWU-SFWA Joint Initial Comments”).
139
See Eldred v. Ashcroft, 537 U.S. 186, 197, 219 (2003).
140
Iowa State Univ. Research Found., Inc. v. Am. Broad. Corp., 621 F.2d 57, 60 (2d Cir. 1980).
141
AAP Initial Comments at 8.
142
Organization for Transformative Works (“OTW”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan.
23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 8 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“OTW Initial Comments”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
31
the issue of the difficulties that would result if an attribution right was applied to works with
multiple authors.
143
Many noncommercial, transformative works could be chilled, it was argued,
if attribution were required in such cases, especially when the original work is authored by
several people, or when the original work is being incorporated into a larger work.
144
Other commenters opined that fair use would not be an adequate safeguard to protect
secondary works that follow-on or use elements of prior works if moral rights were to be applied
more strictly. As one commenter stated,[W]e are most concerned about how an extension of the
copyright law to encompass moral rights will affect the rich culture of follow-on creators and fair
use in the United States.”
145
Another commenter stated that implementing statutory rights “could
cause courts to restrict the scope of fair use” in order to give these new rights meaning.
146
Commenters also argued that creators would face uncertainty in trying to apply fair use to
statutory moral rights given the fair use doctrine’s present unpredictability, which could have a
chilling effect on speech.
147
One illustration of a fair use case that implicates moral rights is Campbell v. Acuff-Rose
Music, Inc.
148
That 1994 Supreme Court case concerned an unauthorized parody of Roy Orbison’s
1964 pop hit “Oh, Pretty Woman” recorded by the rap group 2 Live Crew.
149
2 Live Crew had
originally asked permission from Acuff-Rose (the assignee of the song’s copyright) to parody the
song but was refused.
150
When 2 Live Crew released a parody anyway, Acuff-Rose sued. 2 Live
Crew prevailed on its fair use claim in the District Court, but the Court of Appeals found no fair
use, despite recognizing 2 Live Crew’s version as a parody.
151
The Supreme Court reversed the
Court of Appeals and remanded the case, holding that neither the commercial nature of 2 Live
Crew’s recording, nor the amount of content it copied from the Roy Orbison song should be
143
See, e.g., OTW Initial Comments at 8; MPAA Initial Comments at 8.
144
See, e.g., Center for Democracy & Technology (“CDT”), Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright
Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 4 (May 15, 2017) (“CDT Reply Comments”); OTW Initial Comments at 8. Cf.
MPAA Initial Comments at 8 (arguing that a right of attribution could be at odds with the ability to make a fair use of
material incorporated into a larger work because display of the original author’s name “would be impractical or would
detract from the fair users critical or parodic message”).
145
Public Knowledge (“PK”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of
Inquiry at 3 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“PK Initial Comments”).
146
Electronic Frontier Foundation (“EFF”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Offices Jan. 23, 2017,
Notice of Inquiry at 3 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“EFF Initial Comments”).
147
See EFF Initial Comments at 3; Motion Picture Association of America (“MPAA”), Reply Comments Submitted in
Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 9 (May 15, 2017) (“MPAA Reply Comments”).
148
510 U.S. 569 (1994).
149
Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 572 (1994).
150
Id. at 572–73.
151
Id. at 573–74.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
32
factored against the defendant’s fair use claim, considering “the parodic purpose of the use.”
152
Parody, the court found, falls into the favored statutory category of “criticism or comment.”
153
Additionally, the Court held that, because musical parody requires the use of that part of the
original work that “most readily conjures up the song,” the use of the “heart” of the work is not
excessive.
154
Campbell exemplifies the fair use doctrine’s function as a safeguard on secondary
users’ right to free expression, but also illustrates how fair use can allow for a work to be used in
a way that the original author may disavow. Accordingly, any implementation of greater moral
rights protections would need to allow for uses such as 2 Live Crew’s parody as a fair use in
order to maintain the balance between copyright protections and free expression.
Many commenters expressed optimism that fair use as it is currently constituted could be
applied to any additional moral rights protections. Some noted that applying fair use to moral
rights protections, as is the case with the moral rights afforded in VARA,
155
would keep a
statutory right of attribution or integrity from impinging on uses that courts should deem fair.
156
Indeed, the robust fair use jurisprudence developed by the courts can be applied to moral rights
claims with no less uncertainty than it is currently applied to alleged infringement of economic
rights.
157
Additionally, at least one commenter believed it was unlikely that cases where a fair use
was found would have a different result if a statutory right of integrity had existed.
158
The Berne
Convention standard for integrity is much narrower than an author’s mere unhappiness with a
derivative work, and thus “if altering a work is found ‘fair’ because the change gives the work
‘new meaning or message,’ . . . the first author’s ‘honor or reputation’ remains unscathed
precisely because the point is that the new message is not the first author’s message.”
159
Thus, the
Office is of the opinion that, as with the First Amendment, any tensions between potential
statutory moral rights protections and the fair use doctrine can be overcome through proper
calibration of any statutory framework.
152
Id. at 594.
153
See id. at 579.
154
Id. at 588–89.
155
See 17 U.S.C. § 106A(a).
156
See, e.g., American Association of Law Libraries (“AALL”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright
Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 2 (Mar. 29, 2017) (AALL Initial Comments”); Authors Guild Reply Comments
at 7; FMC Reply Comments at 8.
157
See AALL Initial Comments at 2.
158
See Kernochan Center for Law, Media and the Arts, Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright
Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 11 (May 15, 2017) (“Kernochan Center Reply Comments”).
159
Kernochan Center Reply Comments at 11.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
33
3. Moral Rights and Copyright Term Limits
Internationally, jurisdictions vary as to the duration of their moral rights protections.
Berne article 6bis provides that the moral rights of attribution and integrity shall, posthumously,
“be maintained, at least until the expiry of the economic rights.”
160
While some countries
accordingly limit their moral rights duration to be coextensive with economic copyright rights,
161
other countries go further and provide a perpetual duration for the rights.
162
It is one of the most fundamental tenets of U.S. copyright law that the exclusive rights
granted to a copyright holder shall be limited in term. Recognizing the importance of a strong
public domain in promoting the progress of culture and the useful arts, the framers of the
Constitution made sure to include in the Copyright Clause that exclusive rights shall be secured
to authors only for “limited times.”
163
It is not entirely clear to the Office whether this
constitutional requirement would apply to moral rights, as such application would likely depend
upon how those rights were implemented into U.S. law, e.g., as rights deriving from the
Copyright Clause, or deriving from some other authority (such as the Commerce Clause, which
contains no such limitation on duration).
164
Nonetheless were the U.S. to enact a blanket moral
rights statute, the constitutional “limited times” language supports the notion that such rights
should be limited in time.
Duration was also an issue of great importance for several commenters who, in response
to the Copyright Office’s Notice of Inquiry, urged the Office not to adopt a perpetual approach to
moral rights, opining that to do so would be contrary to U.S. copyright law.
165
Additionally, a
160
Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary and Artistic Works art. 6bis (2), Sept. 9, 1886, as revised July 24, 1971,
and as amended Sept. 28, 1979, S. Treaty Doc. 99-27, 1161 U.N.T.S. 3 (“Berne Convention”).
161
See, e.g., Law on Copyright and Neighboring Rights (1999) art. 18 (Andorra); Copyright Act s 18 (2003) (Ant. & Barb.);
Copyright Act 1968 s 195AM (Austl.).
162
See, e.g., Law No. 82 of 2002 (Pertaining to the Protection of Intellectual Property Rights), al-Jarīdah al-Rasmīyah, vol.
2bis, June 2, 2002, art. 143 (Egypt); CODE DE LA PROPRIÉTÉ INTELLECTUELLE [Intellectual Property Code] art. L121-2 (Fr.);
Ley Federal de Derechos de Autor [LFDA] [Authors’ Rights Law] art. 18, Diario Oficial de la Federación [DOF] Dec. 24,
1996, June 15, 2018 (Mex.).
163
U.S. CONST. art. 1, § 8, cl. 8.
164
See Alexander Bussey, Tr a d i t i o nal Cultural Expressions and the U.S. Constitution, 10 BUFF. INTELL. PROP. L.J. 1, 28 (2014)
(“Rights derived from the Commerce Clause are not subject to the ‘limited times’ requirement, however. Therefore, any
trademark-like rights can last perpetually. Furthermore, some limited moral rights resemble trademark rights, so based
on an expansive view of trademark law, some limited moral rights might be able to last perpetually.”). Additionally,
there is some question of whether moral rights, being rights of personhood and not of economic utility, are a good fit
for the “limited times” language. See Ashley Packard, Copyright Term Extensions, the Public Domain and Intertextuality
Intertwined, 10 J. INTELL. PROP. L. 1, 8 (2002).
165
See AALL Initial Comments at 1; AAP Initial Comments at 7; Authors Alliance Initial Comments at 8.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
34
perpetual approach to moral rights would also conflict with the durational limits of some state
statutory and common laws concerning defamation.
166
Moreover, multiple commenters asserted that, since moral rights relate to the personhood
of the author, the policy rationale for statutory protections for the rights of attribution and
integrity is strongest during the life of the author and weakens thereafter.
167
A limited term of
protection for moral rights would “avoid[] the difficulties of trying to evaluate hypothetical
desires of creators after they have passed, and allow[] the public domain to be freely exploited for
the public good.”
168
The Office is of the opinion that there are strong policy reasons for any statutory right of
attribution or integrity incorporated into the Copyright Act to be limitedeither limited to the
lifetime of the author, or, at the outer edge, coextensive with the economic term.
B. Importance of Attribution and Integrity to Creators
Throughout this Study, the Office has heard from many working authorswriters,
musicians, visual artists, filmmakers, and others—and one of their primary messages is the
importance of the moral rights of integrity and attribution for authors everywhere. These
commenters pointed to factors like honor, pride, and recognition as some of the reasons that
attribution and integrity are important to them, as well as the role that these moral rights interests
play in incentivizing new works and in forming the basis for an author’s economic well being.
Authors’ works are, in many cases, a source of honor and pride, and thus authors have a
“deep interest” in having their works correctly attributed to them, and in ensuring that what they
created is made available in an unadulterated manner.
169
To be recognized for one’s work is a
basic human desire, and an author cannot build a reputation without such recognition for both
the fact of their authorship and the ongoing integrity of their work.
170
As one commenter advised,
166
See AAP Initial Comments at 7 (citing Gugliuzza v. K.C.M.C., Inc., 606 So. 2d 790, 791 (La. 1992)) (“Once a person is
dead, there is no extant reputation to injure or for the law to protect. Since the cause of action is intended to redress
injuries flowing from harm to one's reputation, we conclude that to be actionable defamatory words must be ‘of and
concerning’ the plaintiff or, directly or indirectly, cast a personal reflection on the plaintiff.”). However, state rights of
publicity sometimes apply perpetually. See, e.g., TENN. CODE § 47-25-1104 (2014) (allowing for perpetual protection for
the right of publicity so long as the right is commercially exploited by the rightsholder); Martin Luther King, Jr., Ctr. for
Soc. Change, Inc. v. Am. Heritage Prods., Inc., 296 S.E.2d 697 (Ga. 1982) (holding that the right of publicity in Georgia
extends past the death of its owner).
167
See Authors Alliance Initial Comments at 8 n.28; FMC Reply Comments at 4–5; Roberta Kwall, Comments Submitted
in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 4 (Mar. 14, 2017).
168
FMC Reply Comments at 4–5.
169
Authors Guild Reply Comments at 2. See also Authors Alliance Initial Comments at 3.
170
See Authors Alliance Initial Comments at 3.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
35
“[a]lthough it is often difficult to quantify the value to authors of reputation enhancement by
virtue of public dissemination of their works, the value is real and meaningful to authors.”
171
Also real and meaningful to authors is the role that attribution and integrity play in
providing incentives to create new works. This is especially important to academic authors and
authors of user-generated content on the internet—authors for whom monetary incentives are
secondary to recognition as drivers of creation.
172
The knowledge that their works are being
disseminated without reputation-harming mutilation also encourages such authors in their
creations.
173
Finally, several commenters spoke of the economic importance of attribution and integrity
rights. Recognition for one’s unadulterated work leads to a positive reputation, which leads to
more work as well as an increase in valuation of extant works. “Many times,” one commenter
wrote, “it is the reputation of the artist . . . that adds or gives value to her work.”
174
Additionally,
the very act of attributing a work to its author can serve as a form of advertising.
175
Perhaps the most vivid testimony addressing the combined personal and economic
importance of moral rights to authors was this statement from musician/composer Melvin Gibbs
at the Office’s Moral Rights Symposium in 2016:
For us, attribution—that is our currency. I dont exist if people don't know who I
am. I mean that in the most literal sense of “I don't eat.” You know, so every time
something goes out that I’ve participated in that I don’t get attribution for, it affects
my family. And how that affects the community is that the less I am able to create,
the less I am able to help other people create. And the less the community of—it
shrinks the art—community of artists, which will eventually shrink the creativity
of this country as a whole.
176
The Copyright Office takes very seriously the importance of attribution and integrity
interests to authors. This factor was, along with the other guiding principles outlined in this
section, preeminent in our considerations as we drafted this Report. While the Office recognizes
that our decision not to recommend adoption of a new statutory moral right at this time may
disappoint some authors, the Office is not yet prepared to recommend a course that would
171
Id.
172
See id. at 4.
173
See id. at 4.
174
CVA Initial Comments at 2.
175
See Zandra Kubota, Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of
Inquiry (May 13, 2017).
176
Session 4, Symposium Transcript, 8 GEO. MASON J. INTL COM. L. at 89–90 (remarks of Melvin Gibbs,
musician/composer).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
36
represent such a significant change to U.S. law and industry practices. The Office believes that
the existing patchwork, supplemented by the recommended changes to various federal laws
outlined below, should address many of the concerns expressed by authors during the course of
this study, and believes that further study of whether those targeted changes fully address the
primary concerns of artists would be warranted before adoption of a blanket broad new moral
rights provision.
C. Recognize and Respect Diversity Among Creative Industries and Types of Works
The Copyright Office recognizes that any changes to the current U.S. moral rights regime
should respect the fact that the need for moral rights protection varies by creative sector. A one-
size-fits-all solution that fails to account for the differences between sectors and types of works
would serve no creative community well. For example, take the example of a photograph and a
motion picture. A blanket moral rights regime could well protect the individual author of a
photograph in ways that they are not currently protected—such as providing attribution rights
against persons with whom the author is not in contractual privity.
177
However, such a blanket
system would likely produce only an overlay of duplicative attribution protection for directors,
screenwriters, and performers who are already substantially protected by industry-specific
collective bargaining agreements.
178
Conversely, a blanket regime that, in recognition of the role
that private agreements already play in protecting moral rights, waived statutory protection for
all works covered by contracts, would likely under-protect individual artists and authors who lack
the negotiating power of collective bargaining but who frequently work under contract, such as
most freelance journalists
179
or commercial visual artists.
180
Another consideration in thinking about how a U.S. moral rights regime would work
across industries and types of works is those sectors where attribution interests tend to be
177
See Authors Guild, Inc., Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry
at 9 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“Authors Guild Initial Comments”) (“[I]n the case of unauthorized copies, such as un- or
misattributed works in the context of digital piracy, contract law won’t help ensure attribution.”); CVA Initial
Comments at 18–19 (“Even if attribution is part of an artist/client contract, it is very difficult to enforce.”).
178
See, e.g., Session 6: New Ways to Disseminate Content and the Impact on Moral Rights, in Symposium Transcript, Authors,
Attribution, and Integrity: Examining Moral Rights in the United States, 8 GEO. MASON J. INTL COM. L. 125, 133 (2016)
(remarks of Alec French, Directors Guild of America) (And there are things [in collective bargaining] that are facsimiles
of rights of attribution and rights of integrity that you’d find in a moral rights regime.”). But see Directors Guild of
America (“DGA”) & Writers Guild of America, West (“WGAW”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright
Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 3 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“DGA/WGAW Initial Comments”) (“[W]hile the DGA and
WGAs collective bargaining agreements establish certain minimum economic benefits in recognition of their artistic
contributions to the work, the legally recognized author of these works is the copyright holder. As a result, directors
and writers are not recognized as authors of their own artistic works and have no recognized mechanism to enforce
their rights of integrity and attribution under U.S. law.”).
179
See Authors Guild Initial Comments at 7-8).
180
See CVA Initial Comments at 18–19.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
37
governed by sometimes-written, sometimes just generally understood norms, rather than by
contract or statutory law. Like with agreements, these normsparticularly about when to cite the
author of source material or the professional punishment that attaches to plagiarism of another
author—vary across industries and even across mediums, and would not fit easily into a blanket
moral rights regime. For example, in legal writing, attribution norms for academic articles are
quite rigid, whereas practicing lawyers routinely copy without attribution “the form and
language of legal instruments.”
181
Likewise, attribution in historical writing intended for a
popular audience tends not to be as detailed or thorough as writing intended for a scholarly
audience.
182
A one-size-fits-all moral rights regime would risk obliterating these context-specific
and largely self-governing differences between types of works and industries.
IV. DISCUSSION AND FINDINGS
There remains a qualitative issue of whether U.S. moral rights protections are currently
sufficient to the needs of individual authors. Many commenters to this study asserted that the
U.S. moral rights regime offers a robust menu of options for individual authors to protect their
rights of attribution and integrity,
183
with some arguing that the U.S. patchwork style of
protections offers superior protection to that of a statutory scheme.
184
However, other
commenters seeking more comprehensive protections for the rights of attribution and integrity in
the United States identified several holes in the current U.S. moral rights regime, arguing in effect
that the patchwork leaves many areas of the underlying fabric insufficiently or entirely
uncovered.
185
Even when these commenters acknowledge that the United States is in compliance
181
LCA Initial Comments at 3-4.
182
See LCA Initial Comments at 4; see also OTW Initial Comments at 5 (discussing varying attribution norms between
fiction and non-fiction writing as well as between print news and television news).
183
See, e.g., AAP Initial Comments at 5; MPAA Initial Comments at 3; National Music Publishers’ Association
(“NMPA”), Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 4
(May 15, 2017) (“NMPA Reply Comments”).
184
See, e.g., Computer & Communications Industry Association (“CCIA”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S.
Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 2 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“CCIA Initial Comments”) (“In some cases, U.S.
law provides more substantial protection than other Berne Convention adherents.”); LCA Initial Comments at 2
(regarding private institutional punishments for plagiarism); NMPA Reply Comment at 6 (“Songwriters gain much
more through contractual bargaining—either directly or through industry-wide agreements—than they would through
a one size fits all statutory solution.”).
185
See, e.g., Janice T. Pilch, Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry
at 1 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“Pilch Initial Comments”) (“The need to extend moral rights to all categories of works to eliminate
reliance on the ‘patchwork’ of laws that up to now has served to justify moral rights protection in the U.S. has never
been greater.”); International Federation of Journalists (“IFJ”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright
Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 6 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“IFJ Initial Comments”) (“The reputation of the United
States among authors and performers internationally is not enhanced by the absence of moral rights in that country.”);
Music Creators Initial Comments at 3 (“In general, MCNA agrees with those many commentators who believe that the
United States has not yet enacted laws to codify its moral rights treaty obligations under the Berne Convention.”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
38
with its obligations under Berne article 6bis, they point out that “none of the sources of US law,
separately or together, provides adequate protection for authors’ rights of attribution and
integrity.
186
Recommendations: No federal moral rights statute; improvements to the current patchwork
For the reasons discussed below, the Copyright Office does not recommend creating a
broad federal moral right as a new exclusive right at this time. During the enactment of the
BCIA, Congress followed the approach to amend the Copyright Act “only where there is a clear
conflict with the express provisions of the Berne Convention” and “only insofar as it is necessary
to resolve the conflict in a manner compatible with the public interest, respecting the pre-existing
balance of rights and limitations in the Copyright Act as a whole.”
187
As we outline in this Report, many aspects of the patchwork have remained the same
since passage of the BCIA. Those changes that have occurred to the moral rights patchwork have
been a mixed bag: although some aspects of the existing patchwork have frayed, such as the
narrowing of the availability of claims under section 43 of the Lanham Act for violations of the
rights of attribution and integrity, new squares have been added to the patchwork that provide
additional protections, such as the addition of the Visual Artists Rights Act and section 1202 of
title 17. Nonetheless, the Copyright Office believes that the approach taken by Congress thirty
years ago should be respected absent significant, detrimental changes to the patchwork that
would warrant abandoning the current framework in favor of adoption of a new federal moral
right. The Copyright Office does not find that such changes have occurred.
While new technologies have modified the moral rights landscape, new business practices
have also developed, relying in part on the current legal framework.
188
Enacting a federal moral
rights law could adversely impact this carefully developed schema of contracts and industry
186
Kernochan Center Initial Comments at 4.
187
H.R. REP. NO. 100-609, at 20 (1988); S. REP. NO. 100-352, at 10 (1988) (“S. 1301 will not, and should not, change the
current balance of rights between American authors and proprietors, modify current copyright rules and relationships,
or alter the precedential effect of prior decisions.”).
188
See, e.g., MPAA Initial Comments at 2 (“Further statutory recognition of the moral rights of attribution and integrity
risks upsetting this well-functioning system that has made the United States the unrivalled world leader in motion
picture production for over a century.”); Screen Actors Guild-American Federation of Television and Radio Artists
(“SAG-AFTRA”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 2 (Mar.
30, 2017) (“SAG-AFTRA Initial Comments”) (“But to the American performer, there are perhaps no greater rights than
the ability to enforce contracts, and to collectively bargain under federal labor laws.”); Recording Industry Association
of America, Inc. (“RIAA”), Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of
Inquiry at 2 (May 15, 2017) (“RIAA Reply Comments”) (“[R]ecord labels’ agreements with third-parties generally
include attribution requirements. Such contractual provisions are preferable to government mandates that would
presumably apply identical rules to all classes of creative works, rather than treating sound recordings (which typically
involve numerous creative contributors) differently than photographs or novels or videogames (the first two of which
typically involve a single creator).).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
39
norms in a way that would actually be detrimental to the protection of attribution and integrity
interests.
189
For instance, contracts and licenses, which are governed by state law, have been at
the forefront of protecting moral rights in the United States for many years and are commonly
used in creative industries for that purpose. The ability of parties to freely negotiate the inclusion
or exclusion of moral rights in a contract is a flexible way of addressing the interests of both
parties. Likewise, the social and professional norms related to plagiarism, while not legally
enforceable, regulate attribution for many different types of authors across various institutions
and media.
190
Changing the “plagiarism patch” would disrupt the decades of social ordering
established via dependence on these practices. Authors without the benefit of certain
mechanisms for protecting their attribution and integrity interests, such as collective bargaining,
can utilize other features of the framework, such as plagiarism norms and contract law, to protect
their interests.
191
Further, depending upon how it would be implemented, and what exceptions and
limitations it would admit, a new moral rights statute could also present tensions with well-
established legal principles, such as the First Amendment, on which the copyright ecosystem
depends.
192
Thus, the Office concludes that a blanket statutory moral right for authors of all types
of copyrightable subject matter would disproportionately disrupt current economic transactions
as well as the legal structure that guides them.
Nonetheless, as in the 1980s, a “minimalist” approach towards reform does not entail
ignoring deficiencies within the current moral rights framework. For this reason, the Office
believes that updates to individual pieces of the patchwork may be advisable to account for the
evolution of technology and the corresponding changes within certain business practices.
Specifically, we note that the gaps in Lanham Act protection caused by the Dastar decision, while
not as large as some suggest, could be filled by a narrowly crafted amendment expanding the
Act’s unfair competition protections to include false representations regarding authorship.
Additionally, the Office suggests three minor changes to VARA: clarifying the definition of
“work of visual art” with regard to commercial works; amending VARA’s “recognized stature”
requirement in order to more firmly guide courts in interpreting that phrase; and amending
VARA’s waiver provision to require all authors to consent to a VARA waiver. The Office’s
analysis of the section 1202 provisions limiting CMI removal or alteration concludes that
189
See, e.g., NMPA Reply Comment at 2 (“The existing U.S. legal framework is in fact preferable to the adoption of a
European-style moral rights regime which would only stand to bring uncertainty and disruption to the music
marketplace and will provide a serious disincentive to the use of musical works by prospective licensees.”).
190
See infra Section IV.B.6.a.
191
See NMPA Reply Comment at 4 (“Together the combination of statutory and common law rights, and contracts forms
a healthy moral rights jurisprudence that provides songwriters, their music publisher partners, and other authors, with
the protections they need. This brings certainty and efficiency to enforcement of these rights in the marketplace.”).
192
See, e.g., MPAA Initial Comments at 10 (“New, as-yet-unspecified, statutory protections for either the rights of
integrity or attribution could indeed implicate the First Amendment.”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
40
Congress may want to consider adding a new section 1202A that would better protect authors
and copyright owners against removal or alteration of CMI when intended to conceal attribution.
Finally, the Office proposes that Congress consider a narrowly tailored federal right of publicity,
to address the uncertainty and ambiguity caused by conflicting state laws in this area.
A. Federal Law
1. Misappropriation and Unfair Competition: The Lanham Act
When the BCIA was passed in 1989, the Lanham Act (the federal trademark and unfair
competition statute) was a major component of the U.S. patchwork providing moral rights
protections. Specifically, district and circuit courts had repeatedly held that certain violations of
the rights of attribution and integrity, such as failure to properly credit an author
193
or editing an
author’s work without permission “into a form that departs substantially from the original
work,”
194
could give rise to a claim under section 43(a) of the Lanham Act.
195
The continued
viability of section 43(a) as a vehicle for protecting authors’ attribution and integrity interests has
been called into question, however, following the Supreme Court’s 2003 decision in Dastar Corp.
v. Twentieth Century Fox Film Corp. (“Dastar”),
196
which some courts and commenters have
interpreted as precluding any such claims under the Lanham Act. As discussed below, however,
the Court’s opinion in Dastar is susceptible to more than one interpretation, a situation that has
implications for the continued usefulness of the Lanham Act as part of the moral rights
patchwork.
a) Pre-BCIA Case Law
Section 43(a) provides a remedy for certain “false designation[s] of origin, false or
misleading description[s] of fact, or false or misleading representation[s] of fact” in connection
193
See, e.g., F. E . L . Publ’ns, Ltd. v. Catholic Bishop of Chi., No. 81-1333, 1982 WL 19198, at *10 (7th Cir. Mar. 25, 1982); Smith
v. Montoro, 648 F.2d 602, 607–08 (9th Cir. 1981); Follett v. New Am. Library, Inc., 497 F. Supp. 304, 311–12 (S.D.N.Y. 1980).
As the Ninth Circuit noted when holding that an actor who alleged his name had been replaced on all film credits and
advertising with another actor’s name properly stated a valid claim under section 43(a), an actors name can be of
critical importance to a film’s “power at the box office” and to the actors ability to become recognized as a box office
star. Montoro, 648 F.2d at 607.
194
Gilliam v. Am. Broad. Cos., 538 F.2d 14, 24–25 (2d Cir. 1976).
195
Despite this pre-BCIA case law, some study commenters questioned the effectiveness of the Lanham Act for
protecting authors’ moral rights even pre-Dastar. See, e.g., OTW Initial Comments at 12 (“At the very least, pre-Dastar
trademark law is a poor way to serve authors’ interests in attribution.”); cf. NWU-SFWA Joint Initial Comments at 8
(“[R]egardless of the Dastar decision, the Lanham Act neither protects nor provides effective remedies for violations of
authors moral rights.”).
196
Dastar Corp. v. Twentieth Century Fox Film Corp., 539 U.S. 23 (2003).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
41
with “any goods or services.”
197
A number of different claims are cognizable under section 43(a),
including claims for infringement of an unregistered trademark, claims for false implications of
sponsorship or endorsement, and claims for “passing off” or “reverse passing off.”
198
Claims
arising from violations of the rights of attribution and integrity typically fall into the last category:
either a claim for “passing off,” whereby a plaintiff/author asserts that the defendant is
attributing to the plaintiff a work that either was not authored by the plaintiff or that has been
modified in a way to make it no longer the plaintiff’s work, thereby “passing off” the defendant’s
work as being that of the plaintiff; or a claim for “reverse passing off,” whereby a plaintiff/author
asserts that the defendant is representing himself as the source of the plaintiff’s work by
removing attribution to the plaintiff, thus passing off plaintiff’s goods as his own.
One of the seminal pre-BCIA “passing off” cases implicating authors’ moral rights (in that
instance, the right of integrity) was 1976’s Gilliam v. American Broadcasting Cos. In Gilliam, the
British comedy troupe Monty Python brought a passing off claim against the television network
ABC after ABC “substantially” edited certain Monty Python sketches without permission and
then broadcast them.
199
The edits omitted 27 percent of the original program and included
removing crucial elements of several skits, so that they became unintelligible.
200
The comedy
troupe members sued ABC and alleged that ABC had violated section 43(a) of the Lanham Act by
using their name in connection with a mutilated” version of their work that did not accurately
represent their authorship.
201
The Second Circuit concluded “that the truncated version at times
omitted the climax of the skits to which appellantsrare brand of humor was leading and at other
197
Section 43(a) states:
(1) Any person who, on or in connection with any goods or services, or any container for goods, uses in
commerce any word, term, name, symbol, or device, or any combination thereof, or any false designation
of origin, false or misleading description of fact, or false or misleading representation of fact, which—
(A) is likely to cause confusion, or to cause mistake, or to deceive as to the affiliation, connection, or
association of such person with another person, or as to the origin, sponsorship, or approval of his or
her goods, services, or commercial activities by another person, or
(B) in commercial advertising or promotion, misrepresents the nature, characteristics, qualities, or
geographic origin of his or her or another person's goods, services, or commercial activities,
shall be liable in a civil action by any person who believes that he or she is or is likely to be damaged by
such act.
15 U.S.C. § 1125(a).
198
2 ANNE GILSON LALONDE, GILSON ON TRADEMARKS § 7.02[5] (Matthew Bender 2018) (“GILSON ON TRADEMARKS”).
199
Gilliam, 538 F.2d at 24.
200
Gilliam, 538 F.2d at 25 (describing one of ABC’s edits).
201
Gilliam, 538 F.2d at 24.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
42
times deleted essential elements in the schematic development of a story line.”
202
Significantly,
the court stated thatthe edited version broadcast by ABC impaired the integrity of appellants’
work and represented to the public as the product of appellants what was actually a mere
caricature of their talents.”
203
Following passage of the BCIA, several courts followed Gilliam,
permitting a right of action under the Lanham Act for instances where an author’s work was
mutilated, garbled, or mangled but their name remained attached to it.
204
b) The Supreme Court’s decision in Dastar
In 2003, the U.S. Supreme Court issued an opinion in Dastar that many have viewed as
having the effect of narrowing, if not eliminating, the availability of the Lanham Act as a proxy
for moral rights.
205
Dastar involved the sale and distribution by Dastar Corp. of edited videotapes
of a television series first created by an affiliate on behalf of Twentieth Century Fox. Twentieth
Century Fox asserted a “reverse passing off” claim against Dastar under section 43(a) of the
Lanham Act, based on Dastar’s failure to attribute the footage used in its videotapes.
Titled “Crusade in Europe” and based on a book by the same name, the series at issue was
produced on behalf of Twentieth Century Fox and aired by it in 1949.
206
Fox did not renew the
copyright in the television series, and in 1977 the series entered the public domain.
207
But in 1988,
Fox reacquired the television rights to the underlying book and licensed the exclusive rights to
distribute the “Crusade” video set to SFM Entertainment and New Line Home Video.
Subsequently, in 1995, Dastar Corp. purchased eight beta cam tapes of the original 1949
202
Gilliam, 538 F.2d at 25. As one court later put it, “[t]he edited version simply made no sense.” Choe v. Fordham Univ.
Sch. of Law, 920 F. Supp. 44, 49 (S.D.N.Y. 1995). See also Gilliam, 538 F.2d at 25 n.12 (“In one skit, an upper class English
family is engaged in a discussion of the tonal quality of certain words as ‘woody’ or ‘tinny.’ The father soon begins to
suggest certain words with sexual connotations as either ‘woody’ or ‘tinny, whereupon the mother fetches a bucket of
water and pours it over his head. The skit continues from this point. The ABC edit eliminates this middle sequence so
that the father is comfortably dressed at one moment and, in the next moment, is shown in a soaked condition without
any explanation for the change in his appearance.”).
203
Gilliam, 538 F.2d at 25 (emphasis added).
204
See, e.g., Choe, 920 F. Supp. at 47–49 (student brought a section 43(a) claim against law school journal for publishing
his comment with typographical and substantive errors); Playboy Enters., Inc. v. Dumas, 831 F. Supp. 295, 315–17
(S.D.N.Y. 1993) (artist brought a section 43(a) counterclaim against Playboy for publishing a collection of his works that
were altered and attributing them to the artist); Wojnarowicz v. Am. Family Assn, 745 F. Supp. 130, 141–42 (S.D.N.Y. 1990)
(artist brought a section 43(a) claim against a non-profit organization for publishing a pamphlet that incorporated his
attributed images for criticism purposes).
205
Dastar, 539 U.S. 23.
206
The book contained General Eisenhowers written account of the European theatre of World War II, and was first
published by Doubleday. Doubleday granted the exclusive television adaptation and broadcast rights to an affiliate of
the plaintiff. Dastar, 539 U.S. at 25–26.
207
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 26.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
43
“Crusade” series, copied and edited that footage, and released it as a new video set entitled
“World War II Campaigns in Europe.” The “Campaigns in Europe” video set was a little more
than half the length of the original “Crusade” series and featured a new opening sequence, credit
page, and closing, as well as new chapter-title sequences and narrated chapter introductions,
among other revisions.
208
Dastar Corp. then manufactured and sold copies of the “Campaigns”
video set, with all markings identifying itself as the producer and distributor; the videos, sold at
major retailers and online for significantly less than the “Crusade” set, also made no reference to
the “Crusade” series.
209
Twentieth Century Fox, SFM Entertainment, and New Line Home Video sued Dastar
Corp. asserting, among other claims, reverse passing off in violation of section 43(a) of the
Lanham Act based on Dastar Corp.’s failure to identify and credit the creators of the original
“Crusade” television series as the origin of the footage in its “Campaigns” series. The U.S.
District Court for the Central District of California granted summary judgment for the plaintiffs,
noting that Dastar Corp. copied the entire television series, made only “minor changes,” and
packaged the edited product as its own.
210
In a short opinion, the Ninth Circuit affirmed,
concluding that Dastar Corp. committed “a ‘bodily appropriation’ of Fox’s series” by copying the
series and marketing the edited product without attribution.
211
The question before the Supreme Court was whether “the Lanham Act protect[s] creative
works from uncredited copying, even without a likelihood of consumer confusion.”
212
Section
43(a)(1)(A), which was at issue in Dastar, prohibits a “false designation of origin, false or
misleading description of fact, or false or misleading representation of fact, which . . . is likely to
cause confusion . . . as to the origin . . . of [the defendant’s] goods.”
213
In interpreting the
applicability of the Lanham Act, the Court focused on the statute’s use of the terms “origin” and
“goods.”
214
208
Id. at 26–27.
209
Id. at 27.
210
Twentieth Century Fox Film Corp. v. Dastar Corp., No. CV 98-7189, 2000 WL 35503105, at *11–12 (C.D. Cal. Jan. 4, 2000).
211
Twentieth Century Fox Film Corp. v. Entm’t Distrib., 34 Fed. App’x. 312, 314 (9th Cir. 2002) (quoting Cleary v. News Corp.,
30 F.3d 1255, 1261 (9th Cir. 1994)).
212
Brief for Petitioner at i, Dastar Corp. v. Twentieth Century Fox Film Corp., No. 02-428, 2003 WL 367729, at *I (Feb. 13,
2003). The Court also granted cert on a second, related question: “May a court applying the Lanham Act award twice
the defendant’s profits for purely deterrent purposes?” Id. The Court ultimately did not address this question, which it
said was mooted by its conclusion on the first question. See Dastar, 539 U.S. at 38.
213
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 31 (quoting 15 U.S.C. § 1125(a)(1)(A)).
214
See id. at 29–37.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
44
The Court on an 8–0 vote rejected “[r]eading ‘origin’ in § 43(a) to require attribution of
uncopyrighted materials.”
215
It began its analysis with the dictionary definitions of “origin” and
“goods,” which the Court interpreted as referring to “the producer of the tangible product sold in
the marketplace.”
216
The Court next discussed the purpose of section 43(a), which the Court
characterized as guarding consumers against deception and protecting a producer’s goodwill,
and concluded that a “consumer who buys a branded product does not automatically assume
that the brand-name company is the same entity that came up with the idea for the product, or
designed the product.”
217
In other words, the Court thought that consumers are not confused
when a manufacturer’s name appears on a product and that name differs from the name of the
creator of the underlying content, because consumers are only worried about who manufactured
the tangible product.
While the Court acknowledged the possibility that consumer interests might be different
for “a communicative product” such as a novel, for which “[t]he purchaser . . . is interested not
merely, if at all, in the identity of the producer of the physical tome (the publisher), but also, and
indeed primarily, in the identity of the creator of the story it conveys (the author),”
218
the Court
ultimately found that “[t]he right to copy, and to copy without attribution, once a copyright has
expired, like the right to make (an article whose patent has expired)—including the right to make
it in precisely the shape it carried when patented—passes to the public.”
219
The Court reasoned
that to hold otherwise would result in the creation of “a species of mutant copyright law that
limits the public’s federal right to copy and to use’ expired copyrights.
220
Further, citing the
Visual Artists Rights Act of 1990, the Court stated that Congress had previously added an
attribution right to copyright law “with much more specificity than the Lanham Act’s ambiguous
use of ‘origin.’”
221
In the end, the Court “conclude[d] that the phrase refers to the producer of the
tangible goods that are offered for sale, and not to the author of any idea, concept, or
communication embodied in those goods.”
222
c) Post-Dastar Case Law
The Court’s opinion in Dastar has been interpreted by many commenters as undermining
the continued viability of the Lanham Act as a vehicle for an author seeking to vindicate their
215
Id. at 35.
216
Id. at 31.
217
Id. at 32. It is worth noting that this conclusion was not based on consumer surveys or evidence from the record.
218
Id. at 33.
219
Id. at 33 (quoting Sears, Roebuck & Co. v. Stiffel Co., 376 U.S. 225, 230 (1964)).
220
Id. at 34 (quoting Bonito Boats, Inc. v. Thunder Craft Boats, Inc., 489 U.S. 141, 165 (1989) (cleaned up).
221
Id. at 34.
222
Id. at 37.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
45
rights of attribution and integrity.
223
The exact extent to which such claims are precluded by
Dastar remains up for debate, however. Lower court opinions applying Dastar have fallen into
two primary camps: a broad reading that precludes most claims under the Lanham Act for
violation of the rights of attribution or integrity interests in expressive works,
224
and several more
narrow readings that limit Dastar more closely to its facts and leave open the possibility of certain
claims based on violation of these interests.
Most of the courts that read Dastar broadly have held that it forecloses claims “premised
on the false designation of the origin of ideas, concepts, or communications embodied in tangible
goods,”
225
rejecting claims for lack of attribution in connection with movies,
226
video footage,
227
223
See Artists Rights Society (ARS”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice
of Inquiry at 3 (Mar. 27, 2017) (“ARS Initial Comments”) (“The ability of artists or estates to rely on Section 43(a) may be
limited as a result of the Supreme Courts decision in Dastar.”); Authors Guild Initial Comments at 2 (stating that Dastar
is a main factor in “the result that our law no longer provides a full right of attribution for authors of books and other
literary works”); FMC Reply Comments at 3 (“[A]ny resemblance to moral rights protections from section 43(a) were
lost by Dastar.”); Kernochan Center Initial Comments at 3 (“Dastar has, accordingly, undermined much of the law under
section 43(a) on which the United States’ claimed right of attribution rested at the time of Berne adherence.”); SAG-
AFTRA Initial Comments at 7 (“We are concerned that the 2003 Supreme Court decision, Dastar v. Twentieth Century
Fox, will one day undermine our SAG-AFTRA members’ ability to use the Lanham Act to address attribution or
misattribution to intangible entertainment products.”). But see, Broadcast Music, Inc. (“BMI”), Reply Comments
Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 2 (May 15, 2017) (“BMI Reply
Comments”) (discussing composers objecting to political candidates’ use of songs, “the Lanham Act helps to fill gaps in
the United States’ compliance with Berne”); CCIA Initial Comments at 4–5 (explaining that Dastar has not affected the
moral rights paradigm in the United States); University of Michigan Library, Reply Comments Submitted in Response
to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 1 (May 15, 2017) (“[W]e remain unconvinced that the
patchwork of laws, which were viewed as sufficient when the United States acceded to Berne, has unraveled following
Dastar. The excessive focus on Dastar does a disservice to a patchwork that has always been far more extensive than the
Lanham Act.”). Some commentators see such preclusion as a good thing. See, e.g., CDT Reply Comments at 4 (“To the
extent that the Dastar decision has limited the legal avenues for pursuing attribution claims, it was correct to do so.”).
224
See, e.g., Kent v. Universal Studios, Inc., No. CV 08–2704, 2008 WL 11338293, at *10 (C.D. Cal. Aug. 15, 2008) (holding
that the term “origin” in section 43(a) “exclude[s] the identification of the authors of communicative works”); Atrium
Grp. de Ediciones y Publicaciones, S.L. v. Harry N. Abrams, Inc., 565 F. Supp. 2d 505, 512–13 (S.D.N.Y. 2008); Weidner v.
Carroll, No. 06-CV-782, 2007 WL 2893637, at *4 (S.D. Ill. Sept. 28, 2007).
225
Narrative Ark Entm’t v. Archie Comic Publ’ns, Inc., No. 16 CV 6109, 2017 WL 3917040, at *12 (S.D.N.Y. Sept. 5, 2017)
(finding Dastar preemption of Lanham Act claim based on defendants’ failure to attribute authorship to plaintiff of
stories, artwork, and characters first created by plaintiff under a freelance agreement for defendants); see also Gary
Friedrich Enters. v. Marvel Enters., 713 F. Supp. 2d 215, 234 (S.D.N.Y. 2009) (finding Dastar preemption of Lanham Act
claims because § 43(a) “does not . . . cover misrepresentation about the author of an idea, concept, or communication
embodied in . . . goods”).
226
See, e.g., Williams v. UMG Recordings, Inc., 281 F. Supp. 2d 1177, 1185 (C.D. Cal. 2003) (rejecting claims based on failure
to provide attribution for plaintiff’s contributions to motion picture, including narration, editing, and musical scoring).
227
See Fioranelli v. CBS Broad. Inc., 232 F. Supp. 3d 531, 539 (S.D.N.Y. 2017).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
46
web designs,
228
textbooks,
229
poetry collections,
230
and photographs,
231
to name a few. In adopting
a broader reading of Dastar, these courts have often focused on Justice Scalia’s expressed fear that
the availability of Lanham Act claims for mis- or non-attribution of expressive works might create
a form of “mutant copyright,”
232
and have sought to clearly police what they view as the
boundaries between trademark and copyright law.
233
A smaller minority of courts have extended
this reading of Dastar even further to prohibit any Lanham Act claim related to works that are
potentially covered by copyright, such as precluding claims even for misattribution of the
tangible goods embodying works of authorship
234
or for false representation of “affiliation”
between an author and a publisher of a novel.
235
In contrast, courts adhering to a narrower interpretation of Dastar have been less
concerned with maintaining a bright line between copyright and trademark law, and have been
willing to entertain some claims for mis- or non-attribution of expressive works under certain
theories. The courts that have allowed such Lanham Act claims to proceed have generally done
so on one of four grounds:
228
See Mays & Assocs., Inc. v. Euler, 370 F. Supp. 2d 362, 371 (D. Md. 2005).
229
See Zyla v. Wadsworth, 360 F.3d 243, 251–52 (1st Cir. 2004); Vogel v. Wo lters Kluwer Health, Inc., 630 F. Supp. 2d 585, 589–
92 (M.D.N.C. 2008).
230
See Silverstein v. Penguin Putnam, Inc., 522 F. Supp. 2d 579, 601–02 (S.D.N.Y. 2007).
231
See Agence Fr. Presse v. Morel, 769 F. Supp. 2d 295 (S.D.N.Y. 2011).
232
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 34.
233
See, e.g., Friedman v. Zimmer, No. CV 15-502, 2015 WL 6164787, at *4 (C.D. Cal. July 10, 2015) (“[G]iven the [Dastar]
Court’s concerns about creating overlap between the Lanham Act and other intellectual property regimes, it would
have made little sense for the Supreme Court to reject the Dastar plaintiffs claims under 15 U.S.C. § 1125(a)(1)(A) but
permit the same sort of claim to be asserted under a different prong of the same statute.”); Morel, 769 F. Supp. 2d at 307
(“In Dastar, the Supreme Court admonished that section 43(a) of the Lanham Act—which governs trademarks—cannot
be invoked as an end run around the copyright laws or to add another layer of protection to copyright holders.”); Maule
v. Phila. Media Holdings, LLC, 710 F. Supp. 2d 511, 518 (E.D. Pa. 2008). Other courts have extended this concern to
preclude claims under the Lanham Act that might overlap with other intellectual property laws. See, e.g., Baden Sports,
Inc. v. Molten USA, Inc., 556 F.3d 1300, 1307 (Fed. Cir. 2009) (holding that Dastar also sought to prevent “overlap
between the Lanham and Patent Acts”); United Servs. Auto. Ass’n v. Mitek Sys., Inc., No. SA12–CV–282, 2013 WL
781900, at *3–5 (W.D. Tex. Feb. 15, 2013) (following Baden Sports to extend Dastar to trade secrets); Tao of Sys. Integration,
Inc. v. Analytical Servs. & Materials, Inc., 299 F. Supp. 2d 565, 571–72 (E.D. Va. 2004) (extending Dastar to trade secrets).
234
See Weidner, 2007 WL 2893637, at *4.
235
Antidote Int'l Films, Inc. v. Bloomsbury Publ'g, PLC, 467 F. Supp. 2d 394, 398–99 (S.D.N.Y. 2006).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
47
(i) Dastar precludes only claims for non-attribution or “reverse passing off,” but
leaves available claims for misattribution or “passing off”;
236
(ii) Dastar precludes only claims under section 43(a)(1)(A),
237
but leaves open claims
under section 43(a)(1)(B), which prohibits “misrepresenting the nature,
characteristics, [or] qualities” of goods or services in advertising;
238
(iii) Unattributed copying of works that are themselves the goods, as opposed to works
embodied in separate, tangible goods, constitutes “repackaging” of the sort
cognizable under Dastar;
239
(iv) Dastar only applies to works that are in the public domain, and does not prohibit
claims under section 43(a) for either passing off or reverse passing off in
connection with works that are still under copyright protection.
240
Availability of claims for misattribution or passing off
As mentioned above, prior to the Supreme Court’s decision in Dastar, the Second Circuit
found that the act of making prejudicial, material alterations to a work could support a claim for
passing off under section 43(a) under the theory that “[t]o deform [plaintiff’s] work is to present
him to the public as the creator of a work not his own, and thus makes him subject to criticism for
236
Auscape Int’l v. Nat’l Geographic Soc’y, 409 F. Supp. 2d 235, 250–51 (S.D.N.Y. 2004) (citing Gilliam). Cf. Craigslist Inc. v.
3Taps Inc., 942 F. Supp. 2d 962, 978 (N.D. Cal. 2013) (“The Copyright Act provides no recourse for Craigslist to prevent
others from trading on Craigslists name and mark, and thus does not overlap with the present Lanham Act claim.”).
237
Prohibiting the use of a “name, . . . false designation of origin, false or misleading description of fact, or false or
misleading representation of fact” in connection with “goods, services, or commercial activities” in a manner that is
likely to cause confusion. 15 U.S.C. § 1125(a)(1).
238
See, e.g., Pearson Educ., Inc. v. Boundless Learning, Inc., 919 F. Supp. 2d 434, 438 (S.D.N.Y. 2013) (“Dastar explicitly left
open the possibility that some false authorship claims could be vindicated under the auspices of section 43(a)(1)(B)s
prohibition on false advertising.”); Clauson v. Eslinger, 455 F. Supp. 2d 256, 261 (S.D.N.Y. 2006) (“The Dastar Court
explicitly left open the possibility that some false authorship claims could be vindicated under the auspices of this
sections prohibition on false advertising.”); cf. Zyla, 360 F.3d at 252 n.8 (noting in dicta thatDastar left open the
possibility that some false authorship claims could be vindicated under the auspices of § 43(a)(1)(B)’s prohibition on
false advertising”); Defined Space, Inc. v. Lakeshore E., LLC, 797 F. Supp. 2d 896, 901 (N.D. Ill. 2011) (agreeing with the
plaintiffs interpretation that “Dastar explicitly left open a claim under § 43(a)(1)(B) under the Lanham Act”).
239
See, e.g., Defined Space, 797 F. Supp. 2d at 901 (permitting a section 43(a) claim brought by a photographer against the
defendants who failed to provide proper accreditation); Levine v. Landy, 832 F. Supp. 2d 176, 189, 191 (N.D.N.Y. 2011)
(permitting a section 43(a) claim brought by photographer whose photos were used by a publisher without attribution);
Cable v. Agence Fr. Presse, 728 F. Supp. 2d 977, 981 (N.D. Ill. 2010).
240
See, e.g., Defined Space, 797 F. Supp. 2d at 901; Do It Best Corp. v. Passport Software, Inc., No. 01 C 7674, 2004 WL
1660814, at *17–18 (N.D. Ill. July 23, 2004).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
48
work he has not done.”
241
Post-Dastar, at least two courts have reasoned that certain acts of
misattribution may still present cognizable claims under section 43(a). The Southern District of
New York has stated, albeit in dicta, that a claim for passing off under section 43(a) could proceed
when an “author’s name [is used] to suggest authorship or approval of a work substantially
modified without the author’s consent.”
242
Similarly, the Northern District of California found
that Dastar does not preclude claims for “regular ‘passing off,’” noting that such a claim “does not
raise the ‘perpetual patent and copyright’ concerns that the Supreme Court identified in Dastar
and that, in that case, “[t]he Copyright Act provides no recourse for [plaintiff] to prevent others
from trading on [its] name and mark, and thus does not overlap with the present Lanham Act
claim.
243
Scholars and commenters have likewise argued that misattribution claims such as those
at issue in Gilliam should survive Dastar.
244
Only one court has directly considered Dastar’s application to a passing off claim
premised on material alterations to a plaintiff’s work.
245
In Dankovich v. Keller, the pro se plaintiff
asserted a claim for passing off under section 43(a) based on allegations that defendants
published his article with an unapproved headline and with additional unapproved changes to
the substance of the article, which resulted in “[d]efendants falsely misreprent[ing] that [plaintiff]
241
Gilliam, 538 F.2d at 24 (citing Martin A. Roeder, The Doctrine of Moral Right: A Study in the Law of Artists, Authors and
Creators, 53 HARV. L. REV. 554, 569 (1940)).
242
Auscape, 409 F. Supp. 2d at 251 (citing Gilliam). See also Cyber Websmith, Inc. v. Am. Dental Ass’n, No. 09-CV-6198, 2010
WL 3075726, at *3 (N.D. Ill. Aug. 4, 2010) (stating, in dicta, that passing off claims avoid Dastar preemption).
243
Craigslist, 942 F. Supp. 2d at 978.
244
See, e.g., Justin Hughes, American Moral Rights and Fixing the Dastar “Gap,” 2007 UTAH L. REV. 659, 695 (2007) (arguing
that reading Dastar to preclude misattribution claims would dramatically undermine the Lanham Acts ability to protect
consumers against false facts, such as the author “market[ing] my new high-energy drink as ‘formulated by the people
at Coca-Cola’ or my new line of clothing as ‘designed by Karl Lagerfeld’”); International Trademark Association
(“INTA”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 4 (Mar. 27,
2017) (“INTA Initial Comments”) (arguing that “removing misattribution from the scope of trademark law can only
harm consumers and producers and frustrate the goals of trademark law”); SAG-AFTRA Initial Comments at 7
(“Incorrectly billing a film is analogous to but worse than a toy manufacturer selling an unauthorized action figure,
because inaccurate billing decreases a performers chances of finding gainful employment. It also potentially calls his
or her integrity into question if she or he has claimed to have appeared in a work in which they have not been correctly
billed. In addition, such inaccurate billing misleads a consumer into paying for a movie that the performer had no
creative or professional involvement in.”). Cf. A.V.E.L.A., Inc. v. Estate of Marilyn Monroe, LLC, No. 12 Civ. 4828, 2019 WL
367842. at *17–9 (S.D.N.Y. Jan. 30, 2019) (allowing a claim for false endorsement under section 43(a) to proceed based on
the licensing and distribution of products bearing the name and likeness of a dead celebrity).
245
Separately, the Central District of California has called into question the continued viability of Gilliam, stating in dicta
that “Dastar . . . effectively overrules Gilliam.” Kent, 2008 WL 11338293, at *4. It is worth noting, however, that the
claims at issue in Kent were for reverse passing off based on non-attribution, similar to the claims directly at issue in
Dastar, rather than claims for passing off or false attribution of the type at issue in Gilliam.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
49
authored the piece he now claims he ‘did not write.’
246
The court, citing several post-Dastar
reverse passing off cases, rejected the Lanham Act claim, stating that plaintiff’s claim “is exactly
the type of false authorship claim barred by Dastar, regardless of how [plaintiff] attempts to
characterize it.”
247
The Office was unable to locate any cases where a court rejected a claim under
section 43(a) based on defendant’s attribution of his own work to the plaintiff.
Availability of claims under section 43(a)(1)(B)
Another theory that has been employed by courts to limit the scope of Dastar preemption
is that the Supreme Court’s holding applies only to claims under section 43(a)(1)(A) of the
Lanham Act, leaving available claims for non-attribution under section 43(a)(1)(B). In finding the
claims before it to be preempted by the Copyright Act, the Dastar Court noted that “[i]f,
moreover, the producer of a video that substantially copied [plaintiffs’ series] were, in advertising
or promotion, to give purchasers the impression that the video was quite different from that
series, then one or more [plaintiffs] might have a cause of action . . . for misrepresentation
under . . . § 43(a)(1)(B).”
248
Several lower courts have seized upon this language to hold that
Dastar explicitly left open the possibility that some false authorship claims could be vindicated
under the auspices of section 43(a)(1)(B)’s prohibition on false advertising.”
249
In reaching such a
conclusion, the Southern District of New York noted that the Dastar court “grounded its holding
in what it ruled was the ‘natural understanding’ of section 43(a)(1)(A)’s phraseorigin of goods,’”
but that “Congress did not incorporate any such reference into section 43(a)(1)(B).”
250
Other courts have rejected this line of reasoning. The Federal Circuit found that similar
reliance on the Dastar dicta quoted above was misplaced, noting that “[w]hile the dictum in
Dastar might suggest that the Supreme Court left open the possibility of a claim arising from a
misrepresentation concerning the qualities of certain goods, it does not necessarily suggest that
claims based on false designation of authorship are actionable under Section 43(a)(1)(B),”
expressing the concern that allowing such claims “could create overlap” between the Lanham Act
and other intellectual property laws.
251
The Sixth Circuit similarly rejected claims under section
43(a)(1)(B), stating that “a misrepresentation about the source of the ideas embodied in a tangible
object (such as misrepresentation about the author of a book or the designer of a widget) is not a
mischaracterization about the nature, characteristics, or qualities of the object,” and that “a
misrepresentation is actionable under § 43(a)(1)(B) only if it misrepresents the ‘characteristics of
246
Dankovich v. Keller, No. 16-13395, 2017 WL 5571354 (E.D. Mich. July 27, 2017).
247
Id. at *8.
248
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 38.
249
Pearson, 919 F. Supp. 2d at 438. See also Clauso, 455 F. Supp. 2d at 262 (stating that a “film’s credits and promotional
materials wrongly credit defendant as being producer” state a claim under section 43(a)(1)(B)).
250
Pearson, 919 F. Supp. 2d 438.
251
Baden Sports, 556 F.3d at 1307.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
50
the good itself.’”
252
The Southern District of New York likewise found that authorship was not a
characteristic or quality of a work, because to find otherwise would result in allowing under
section 43(a)(1)(B) “the very claim Dastar rejected under § 43(a)(1)(A).”
253
A number of courts in the Ninth Circuit have similarly read into the Ninth Circuit’s
opinion in Sybersound Records, Inc. v. UAV Corp.
254
a blanket prohibition against claims based on
false designation of authorship under section 43(a)(1)(B).
255
In Sybersound, the Ninth Circuit
rejected a claim under section 43(a)(1)(B) premised on allegations that defendant misrepresented
its pirated karaoke recordings as being licensed by the copyright owner, which in turn put
plaintiffs, who licensed (and paid royalties for) the recordings, at a competitive disadvantage. In
finding that such misrepresentations were not actionable, the Court stated that “the licensing
status of each work” was not part of the nature, characteristics, or qualities of the karaoke
products.”
256
Complicating this analysis, however, is the fact that the Sybersound court stated that
“the nature, characteristics, and qualities of karaoke recordings under the Lanham Act are more
properly construed to mean characteristics of the good itself, such as the original song and artist of
252
Kehoe Component Sales, Inc. v. Best Lighting Prods., Inc., 796 F.3d 576, 590 (6th Cir. 2015) (rejecting claims under section
43(a)(1)(B) based on counterclaim defendant’s advertising of products identical to products it produced on behalf of
counterclaim plaintiff, without attribution to counterclaim plaintiff for originating the design). It is worth noting that
neither Kehoe nor Baden Sports involved copyrighted or expressive works. Baden Sports involved a false advertising
claim based on defendants marketing of its product as “proprietary,” “exclusive,” and “innovative, when plaintiff
alleged that defendant copied features of plaintiffs product, infringing a utility patent that plaintiff had obtained for
those features. Baden Sports, 556 F.3d at 1303. Similarly, in Kehoe a seller brought various claims, including a false
advertising claim, against its former supplier after the latter used molds and tooling designed for manufacture of the
sellers products to create identical lighting products that the supplier then marketed directly to the sellers customers.
Kehoe, 796 F.3d at 580.
253
Antidote Int’l Films, 467 F. Supp. 2d at 399–400; see also Morel, 769 F. Supp. 2d at 308 (citing Antidote); LaPine v. Seinfeld,
No. 08 Civ. 128, 2009 WL 2902584, at *15 (S.D.N.Y. Sept. 10, 2009) (same); Gurvey v. Cowan, Liebowitz & Latman, PC, No.
06 Civ. 1202, 2009 WL 1117278, at *4 (S.D.N.Y. Apr. 24, 2009) (“A failure to attribute the authorship of an idea simply
does not amount to the misrepresentation of the ‘nature, characteristics, qualities, or geographic origin of . . . goods,
services, or commercial activities’ as required under section 43(a) of the Lanham Act.”), rev’d in part on other grounds, 462
Fed. App’x. 26 (2d Cir. 2012); Thomas Publ’g Co., LLC v. Tech. Evaluation Centers, Inc., No. 06 Civ. 14212, 2007 WL 2193964,
at *3 (S.D.N.Y. July 27, 2007).
254
517 F.3d 1137 (9th Cir. 2008).
255
See, e.g., Friedman, 2015 WL 6164787, at *4 (citing Sybersound for the proposition that a claim of false designation of
authorship is not viable under section 43(a)(1)(B) under the Lanham Act); A.H. Lundberg Assocs., Inc. v. TSI, Inc., No.
C14-1160, 2014 WL 5365514, at *4 (W.D. Wash. Oct. 21, 2014) (citing Sybersound for the proposition that “claims of false
designations of authorship as false advertisement are not actionable under § 1125(a)(1)(B) in the Ninth Circuit”); cf.
Baden Sports, 556 F.3d at 1307 (“Following Sybersounds reasoning, we conclude that authorship, like licensing status, is
not a nature, characteristic, or quality, as those terms are used in Section 43(a)(1)(B) of the Lanham Act.”).
256
Sybersound, 517 F.3d at 1144.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
51
the karaoke recording.”
257
This statement seems to recognize that the identity of the artist can be a
material characteristic of the good, and thus misattribution of the artist could support a claim
under section 43(a)(1)(B).
258
Availability of claims for repackaging of works
Some courts have read Justice Scalia’s discussion of the meaning of “origin” in section
43(a)(1)(A) as being limited to situations where the copyrighted works at issue are embodied in
tangible goods (such as an audiovisual work embodied in a videotape or a novel embodied in a
physical book), and thus inapplicable to situations where the work and the goods are merged
(such as a digital photograph).
259
In reaching such a conclusion, these courts often analogize to
the Dastar court’s hypothetical regarding the repackaging of goods, wherein the Court stated that
a section 43(a) claim “would undoubtedly be sustained if Dastar [Corp.] had bought some of New
Line's Crusade videotapes and merely repackaged them as its own.”
260
In several cases finding no
Dastar preemption, the courts found it notable that the defendant copied the plaintiff’s expressive
work without modification or addition.
261
This approach is exemplified by the Northern District of Illinoisopinion in Cable v. Agence
France Presse.
262
In that case, the plaintiff photographer sued the defendant news agency alleging
violations of the Copyright Act and the Lanham Act for displaying, disseminating, and
distributing copies of his photos without permission or attribution. Defendant argued that the
Lanham Act claim was precluded by Dastar because the photographs were not a tangible good,
but rather embodied the photographer’s communication. The court disagreed, and held that
plaintiff’s claim—“that AFP took the plaintiff’s photos and repackaged them as their own without
revision”—was permitted by Dastar.
263
The Northern District of New York used similar reasoning
257
Sybersound, 517 F.3d at 1144 (emphasis added).
258
But see Friedman, 2015 WL 6164787, at *4 (rejecting this reading of Sybersound).
259
See, e.g., Defined Space, 797 F. Supp. 2d at 901 (holding that facts alleging that a defendant took the plaintiffs
“photographs and passed them off as their own photographs without revision or proper accreditation . . . cleanly fit
within the exception enunciated by Dastar”); Victor Stanley, Inc. v. Creative Pipe, Inc., No. 06-2662, 2011 WL 4596043, at
*11–12 (D. Md. Sept. 30, 2011); Gen. Sci. Corp. v. SheerVision, Inc., No. 10-cv-13582, 2011 WL 3880489, at *3 (E.D. Mich.
Sept. 2, 2011); Cable, 728 F. Supp. 2d at 981; Cvent, Inc. v. Eventbrite, Inc., 739 F. Supp. 2d 927, 936 (E.D. Va. 2010); Michael
Grecco Photography, Inc. v. Everett Collection, Inc., 589 F. Supp. 2d 375, 387 (S.D.N.Y. 2008), vacated in part on other grounds,
No. 07 Civ. 8171, 2009 WL 969928 (S.D.N.Y. Apr. 7, 2009).
260
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 31.
261
See, e.g., Cisco Tech., Inc. v. Certification Trendz, Ltd., 177 F. Supp. 3d. 732, 737–38 (D. Conn. 2016); Defined Space, 797 F.
Supp. 2d at 901; Do It Best, 2004 WL 1660814, at *17–18. Cf. Flaherty v. Filardi, No. 03 Civ. 2167, 2009 WL 749570, at *9
(S.D.N.Y. Mar. 20, 2009) (stating in dicta that had the defendant “merely changed the cover page of the script to list
himself as author and provide a new title, Plaintiff might have had a Lanham Act claim”).
262
Cable, 728 F. Supp. 2d 977.
263
Cable, 728 F. Supp. 2d at 981.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
52
in Levine v. Landy.
264
Distinguishing an earlier Southern District of New York case that found
Dastar preemption of a claim for failure to identify the plaintiff as the creator of a comic book
character, the Levine court noted that the comic book character at issue in the previous case was
“embodied” in a film and merchandise, while in the case before it, plaintiff “alleges defendants
misrepresented the origin of the photographs themselves; not the ideas, concepts, or
communications embodied in the photographs.”
265
The District of Connecticut likewise found
that a claim under section 43(a) might be available were the defendant to sell works consisting
solely of questions and answers from plaintiff’s certification exams, but that “[i]f . . . it can be
shown at summary judgement that Defendants have added content to these exams in the form of
answer explanations, Plaintiff’s false designation of origin claim would likely fail under Dastar
and its progeny.
266
In contrast, other courts have rejected such a distinction, even on similar facts.
267
The
Southern District of New York, evaluating claims that a news agency and its licensees distributed
and reproduced plaintiff’s photographs without authorization and with improper attribution to a
third party, found that the photographs were “communicative products” as described by the
Dastar Court, and thus “false designation of their authorship is not cognizable under section
43(a)(1)(A).”
268
Similarly, the Southern District of Illinois rejected the idea that the defendants
merely repackaged the plaintiffs’ goods despite “[t]he fact that the ‘product’ (i.e., the manuscript)
in this case is nothing more tangible than an idea or communication that it embodies,and
accordingly found that plaintiffs’ Lanham Act claim for false designation of origin was precluded
under Dastar.
269
Public Domain
At least one court has nominally distinguished Dastar by noting that “Dastar rested
heavily on the fact that the materials at issue were in the public domain,” finding that Lanham
Act claims relating to works that are not in the public domain do not pose “the fear of a perpetual
copyright regime such as the Supreme Court faced in Dastar.”
270
The majority of courts have
264
Levine, 832 F. Supp. 2d 176.
265
Id. at 191 (emphasis added).
266
Certification Trendz, 177 F. Supp. 3d. at 737–38.
267
See, e.g., Tech. Evaluation Ctrs., 2007 WL 2193964, at *2–3 (holding that Dastars prohibition on protection for “the
author of any idea, concept or communication embodied in those goods” extends to services embodied in non-tangible
goods like websites); Morel, 769 F. Supp. 2d at 307 (rejecting claim for reverse passing off based on reproduction of
photograph); cf. Fioranelli, 232 F. Supp. 3d at 541 (finding that footage incorporated into defendants’ media products
was not a tangible good, and that failure to credit plaintiff as the author of the footage did not support a claim under
section 43(a)(1)(A)).
268
Morel, 769 F. Supp. 2d at 307.
269
Weidner, 2007 WL 2893637, at *4.
270
Defined Space, 797 F. Supp. 2d at 901.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
53
rejected limiting Dastar to works in the public domain, however.
271
For example, the Southern
District of New York noted that “the Supreme Court did not articulate any distinction between
copyrighted and uncopyrighted material,” but rather “the Court was clearly concerned that
applying Lanham Act protection to otherwise unprotected material would result in an extension
of copyright law through the back door of the Lanham Act,” and thus would have “declined to
extend Lanham Act protection to the [video], whether it was under copyright or not.”
272
The
Middle District of Tennessee likewise rejected this distinction, stating that the result of such an
interpretation would be that “‘origin of goods’ in § 1125(a)(1) [would] mean one thing when
addressing copyrighted works, and mean something quite different when addressing works
whose copyrights had expired.”
273
Despite the weight of authority rejecting such a limitation of Dastar to works in the public
domain, some scholars and commentators have expressed support for this theory as a basis for a
narrow reading of Dastar.
274
As one copyright scholar stated at the Office’s moral rights
symposium, Dastar “was mostly about . . . content no longer protected by copyright.”
275
271
See, e.g., Narrative Ark, 2017 WL 3917040, at *5; Fioranelli, 232 F. Supp. 3d at 539; Personal Keepsakes, Inc. v.
Personalizationmall.com, Inc., No. 11 C 5177, 2012 WL 414803, at *4 (N.D. Ill. Feb. 8, 2012); Kinney v. Oppenheim, No. CV-
10-6287, 2011 WL 13217573, at *10 (C.D. Cal. Mar. 3, 2011); Contractual Obligation Prods., LLC v. AMC Networks, Inc., 546
F. Supp. 2d 120, 130 (S.D.N.Y. 2008); Vogel, 630 F. Supp. 2d at 591; Brainard v. Vassar, 561 F. Supp. 2d 922, 934 (M.D. Tenn.
2008); A Slice of Pie Prods., LLC v. Wayans Bros. Entm’t, 392 F. Supp. 2d 297, 313 (D. Conn. 2005); UMG, 281 F. Supp. 2d at
1185.
272
Atrium Grp., 565 F. Supp. 2d at 512. In fact, the Southern District of New York has found in at least one instance that
an attempt to distinguish Dastar on this grounds in order to pursue a Lanham Act claim for failure to credit the plaintiff
as the producer rises to the level of bad faith required to support an award of attorneys’ fees to the defendant. See
Contractual Obligation, 546 F. Supp. 2d at 130–31.
273
Brainard, 561 F. Supp. 2d at 934.
274
See, e.g., Hughes, 2007 UTAH L. REV. at 697; AAP Initial Comments at 6 (“the decision is arguably limited to works in
the public domain.”); Authors Alliance Initial Comments at 7–8 (”The Dastar decision articulated a strong U.S.
commitment to a robust public domain and the publics right to freely use works that have entered into it. Attempts by
those who would interfere with the public domain by attaching non-economic author rights to public domain works
should be rejected.”). Cf. Jane C. Ginsburg, The Right to Claim Authorship in U.S. Copyright and Trademarks Law, 41 HOUS.
L. REV. 263, 269 (2004) (“The Court placed great emphasis on the unconstrained ability of the public to copy and
distribute public domain works. Requiring accurate attribution of creative origin, according to the Court, improperly
impedes the public's entitlement. Where, by contrast, the work is still subject to the author's exclusive right to make the
work available in copies or by transmission, the requirements as to how the copies or transmissions are labeled take
nothing from the public.”).
275
Session 2: The U.S. Perspective, in Symposium Transcript, Authors, Attribution, and Integrity: Examining Moral Rights in
the United States, 8 GEO. MASON J. INTL COM. L. 26, 33 (2016) (hereinafter “Session 2, Symposium Transcript”) (remarks of
Peter K. Yu, Professor of Law, Texas A&M University School of Law).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
54
d) The Implication of Dastar for the Moral Rights Patchwork
It is indisputable that the Supreme Court’s holding in Dastar has narrowed the
applicability of the Lanham Act to claims for violations of the rights of attribution and integrity,
and thus has resulted in the fraying of one square of the moral rights patchwork as originally
envisioned by Congress. It would nevertheless be inappropriate to write off the Lanham Act
entirely. Based on the Office’s review of lower court decisions interpreting Dastar, the Office
believes that, when Dastar is properly interpreted, the Lanham Act remains a viable square of the
moral rights patchwork.
276
Though limited in its availability―as individual squares in the
patchwork tend to be―the Lanham Act provides a vehicle for authors to protect both their
attribution and integrity interests under certain facts. The question that must be answered,
however, is what types of section 43(a) claims remain, and what level of protection do such
surviving claims provide for authors who have seen their work mis- or non-attributed, or
distorted in a manner that they find prejudicial?
The Office acknowledges that the majority of courts considering claims under section
43(a) arising from either mis- or non-attribution of creative works or prejudicial distortions of
those works have rejected such claims post-Dastar. It does not follow, however, that all potential
claims under section 43(a) for violations of the rights of attribution or integrity are foreclosed.
Further, while a small minority of such courts have stretched Dastar’s expressed concern
regarding the creation of “a species of mutant copyright law that limits the public’s federal right
to copy and to use expired copyrights’’
277
to preclude any claims under section 43(a) related to
works potentially covered by copyright, such a result does not appear to be consistent with either
the purpose of the Lanham Act or the wording of the Dastar opinion itself.
278
As the Dastar Court noted, the Lanham Act is at its heart a consumer protection statute.
279
For it to fulfill this purpose, courts must acknowledge that, at least with respect to certain
products, a consumer’s purchasing decision is likely to be influenced “not merely, if at all, [by]
the identity of the producer of the physical tome (the publisher), but also, and indeed primarily,
[by] the identity of the creator of the story it conveys (the author).”
280
276
To the extent that state trademark statutes and common law are consistent with the Lanham Act, most states have
found that analysis of the state principles are to be interpreted under the same analysis as the federal law. See 1
MCCARTHY ON TRADEMARKS AND UNFAIR COMPETITION § 22:1.50 (5th ed. 2017) (“MCCARTHY ON TRADEMARKS”); see also
Grupo Gigante SA De CV v. Dallo & Co., Inc., 391 F.3d 1008, 1100 (9th Cir. 2004); Donchez v. Coors Brewing Co., 392 F.3d
1211, 1219 (10th Cir. 2004); Rolls-Royce Motors Ltd. v. A & A Fiberglass, Inc., 428 F. Supp. 689, 694 (N.D. Ga. 1976).
277
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 34 (cleaned up).
278
See supra discussion on pages 47–54, and cases cited therein.
279
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 32 (“Section 43(a) of the Lanham Act prohibits actions like trademark infringement that deceive
consumers and impair a producer's goodwill.”).
280
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 33.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
55
Nor has there ever been a bright line separating copyright and trademark protection in all
instances,
281
and a reading of Dastar that requires such a result would upend decades of copyright
and trademark jurisprudence. The language of the Dastar opinion itself recognized that a
cognizable section 43(a) claim may still exist under certain circumstances with respect to works
covered by copyright, such as if a defendant “substantially copied” a plaintiff’s work and “in
advertising or promotion, [gives] purchasers the impression that [defendant’s product] was quite
different from” the plaintiff’s product,
282
or if a defendant purchases plaintiff’s work “and merely
repackage[s it] as its own.”
283
Still, a full reckoning with the consequence of Dastar for the moral
rights patchwork has to recognize and take into consideration the Court’s concerns, as expressed
in Dastar and other cases, regarding the proper scope of any overlap between intellectual
property rights regimes.
284
The Office believes that both the wording of and the public policy behind the Lanham Act
counsel in favor of permitting claims under section 43(a) to proceed for certain violations of the
attribution and integrity interests. While the Office perceives at least four different judicial
theories under which courts have allowed such claims to move forward post-Dastar,
285
the Office
finds some of these theories to be better reasoned than others.
The Office finds persuasive the argument, as articulated by the Northern District of
California
286
and the Southern District of New York,
287
that instances of passing off, such as
through misattribution of a work to an author or the prejudicial distortion of the content of the
author’s work, are rightly the subject of a claim under section 43(a).
288
To date, no court has
articulated an argument that the Office finds persuasive for why such claims should be
considered preempted under Dastar.
289
Such cases do not raise the specter of “perpetual
281
Indeed, as courts have long recognized, “[d]ual protection under copyright and trademark laws is particularly
appropriate for graphic representations of characters.” Frederick Warne & Co., Inc. v. Book Sales Inc., 481 F. Supp. 1191,
1196 (S.D.N.Y. 1979). See also Walt Disney Prods. v. Air Pirates, 581 F.2d 751 (9th Cir. 1978); Patten v. Superior Talking
Pictures, 8 F. Supp. 196 (S.D.N.Y. 1934).
282
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 38.
283
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 31.
284
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 34 (“[In] construing the Lanham Act, we have beencareful to caution against misuse or over-
extension’ of trademark and related protections into areas traditionally occupied by patent or copyright.”) (quoting
TrafFix Devices, Inc. v. Marketing Displays, Inc., 532 U.S. 23, 29 (2001)).
285
See supra notes 236–275 and accompanying discussion.
286
See Craigslist, 942 F. Supp. 2d 962.
287
See Auscape, 409 F. Supp. 2d 235.
288
It remains an open question as to whether such claims are properly brought under section 43(a)(1)(A) or 43(a)(1)(B).
289
Looking at the legislative history of section 43(a), particularly as it was revised by the Trademark Law Revision Act
of 1988, and within the context of the closely related BCIA and VARA statutes, one scholar has argued that “Dastar’s
conclusion may be precisely the opposite of what Congress intended.” Mary LaFrance, When You Wish upon Dastar:
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
56
copyright” feared by Justice Scalia, as permissible acts of copying could still be accomplished
without misattributing the resulting work to the original author. Nor is it clear that the
Copyright Act provides a vehicle for vindication of an author’s interest in avoiding the
reputational harm that comes from having her or his name associated with a work produced by a
third party.
290
Allowing such claims to move forward would also further the Lanham Act’s
purpose of preventing consumer confusion, so that consumers do not purchase the resulting
work under the false impression that it represents the output of the author. While this approach
does not provide the bright-line separation between copyright and trademark law that some
courts may wish, it is in keeping with the historical development of copyright and trademark
jurisprudence, where such a bright line has long been notably absent.
The Office likewise finds persuasive the reasoning employed by those lower courts that
have found Dastar to leave open the possibility of asserting claims for mis- or non-attribution in
advertising under section 43(a)(1)(B). As several lower courts, including the First Circuit,
291
have
noted, the Dastar opinion explicitly leaves open the possibility of claims under section 43(a)(1)(B)
in certain circumstances.
292
This conclusion is supported by the text of the Lanham Act itself. As noted by the
Southern District of New York, the Dastar holding was premised chiefly on a textual reading of
the term “origin of goods” in section 43(a)(1)(A).
293
In contrast, the ordinary meaning of the terms
“nature,”
294
“characteristics,”
295
and qualities”
296
are far broader than the term “origin.” Even
giving credence to Justice Scalia’s intuition that the “entity that came up with the idea for the
Creative Provenance and the Lanham Act, 23 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 197, 219 (2005). Rather, LaFrance argues, the
legislative history indicates that if Congress wanted section 43(a) to protect any types of goods against reverse passing
off, it was intangible, expressive works. Id. at 219–33. “This history received no attention whatsoever in the Dastar
opinion.” Id. at 201.
290
Admittedly, the Copyright Act may provide a vehicle for an author to challenge prejudicial distortions of her or his
work, provided that such distortions both result in the creation of a derivative work and are not excused by fair use.
See 17 U.S.C. § 106(2).
291
See Zyla, 360 F.3d at 252 n.8 (noting in dicta thatDastar left open the possibility that some false authorship claims
could be vindicated under the auspices of § 43(a)(1)(B)’s prohibition on false advertising”).
292
See Dastar, 539 U.S. at 38.
293
See Pearson, 919 F. Supp. 2d at 438.
294
Defined as “the inherent character or basic constitution of a person or thing: essence.” Nature, WEBSTERS NINTH
NEW COLLEGIATE DICTIONARY 789 (1987).
295
Defined as a “distinguishing trait, quality, or property. Characteristics, WEBSTERS NINTH NEW COLLEGIATE
DICTIONARY 227 (1987).
296
Defined as a “peculiar and essential character: nature” or “an inherent feature: property.” Qualities, WEBSTERS
NINTH NEW COLLEGIATE DICTIONARY 963 (1987).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
57
product” is “typically of no consequence to purchasers,”
297
it may be that a not insignificant
number of customers would find the actual author of a book, song, or movie to be a nature,
characteristic, or quality of the goods that is relevant to their purchase decision.
298
Allowing a
company to distribute a video of a 10-year-old child’s scene-by-scene illustrations of Hamlet while
advertising it as the Kenneth Branagh motion picture version, merely because the advertisement
relates to authorship of the content rather than the manufacturer of the DVD, is a result that
would appear to be in conflict with both the literal wording of and the purpose behind section
43(a)(1)(B) of the Lanham Act. While such an approach—as with allowing claims for
misattribution or prejudicial distortion of a workdoes not neatly separate copyright and
trademark protections, a court’s policy preference for a bright line demarcation should not
displace clear statutory language.
299
Although three post-Dastar Circuit Court decisions have been cited by lower courts as
precluding claims for mis- or non-attribution of expressive works under section 43(a)(1)(B), each
of these cases is readily distinguishable. Both the Federal Circuit’s decision in Baden Sports
300
and
the Sixth Circuit’s decision in Kehoe
301
address claims for non-attribution of the concept behind
physical products, as opposed to non- or misattribution of the content of communicative
products. Such claims are more similar to the Dastar Court’s cola hypothetical,
302
and the identity
of the originator of the concept is less likely to be considered by consumers to be relevant aspects
of the nature, characteristics, or quality of the goods. Likewise, the Ninth Circuit’s decision in
Sybersound addressed a claim under section 43(a)(1)(B) related to purportedly false assertions that
the karaoke products at issue were licensed, as opposed to infringing.
303
A representation that the
products were licensed is not a representation regarding the nature, characteristic, or quality of
297
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 32–33.
298
Of course, the Office’s intuition regarding the relevance of such information to consumer purchasing decisions
would properly be the subject of a consumer survey, as are other topics of relevance in Lanham Act litigations.
299
See Dawson Chem. Co. v. Rohm & Haas Co., 448 U.S. 176, 220–21 (1980) (“Since our present task is one of statutory
construction, questions of public policy cannot be determinative of the outcome unless specific policy choices fairly can
be attributed to Congress itself.”).
300
Baden Sports, 556 F.3d 1300.
301
Kehoe, 796 F.3d 576.
302
“[T]he brand-loyal consumer who prefers the drink that the Coca-Cola Company or PepsiCo sells, while he believes
that that company produced (or at least stands behind the production of) that product, surely does not necessarily
believe that that company was the ‘origin of the drink in the sense that it was the very first to devise the formula.
The consumer who buys a branded product does not automatically assume that the brand-name company is the
same entity that came up with the idea for the product, or designed the product—and typically does not care
whether it is.”
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 32.
303
See Sybersound, Inc. v. UAV Corp., 517 F.3d 1137 (9th Cir. 2008).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
58
the goods themselves, however, but instead is a representation regarding the economic
arrangements related to the goods.
304
The Office similarly believes that a strong argument can be made for allowing claims
under section 43(a) for certain instances of unattributed copying of communicative works that are
not otherwise embodied in tangible goods. The Office sees no textual support in the Lanham Act
for a reading of “origin of goods” that allows a defendant to obtain an electronic copy of an Ansel
Adams photograph and resell it as its own, while prohibiting the same defendant from
purchasing a videotape and repackaging it as his own. Treating the author of a communicative
work that is not otherwise embedded in tangible goods as the “origin” of those goods would thus
give meaning to the term “origin” in section 43(a) with respect to such goods.
305
It also serves the
consumer-protection purposes of the Lanham Act since, as Justice Scalia acknowledged, the
purchaser of a communicative product is likely to have a greater interest in the origin of the
content of such communicative product than the origin of a design for a widget.
306
For much the same reason, however, the Office is not persuaded by the arguments made
by some commentators and at least one court that the copyright status of a work provides a
meaningful basis of distinction when determining whether a claim for non-attribution can go
forward under section 43(a) after Dastar. While such a reading may address the public policy
concern regarding creation of a “mutant copyright” that was articulated by the Dastar Court, the
Office does not see any textual support in the Lanham Act for such a finding. The nature of the
goods, and thus the meaning of the term “origin” as a modifier of the goods, simply does not
magically change at the point a work passes from within the copyright term into the public
domain.
e) Potential Lanham Act Changes
While the Office finds persuasive certain courts that more narrowly interpret the Supreme
Court’s holding in Dastar to allow certain claims for violations of integrity and attribution
interests to proceed under section 43(a), case law on this issue will likely continue to develop after
issuance of this Report. Should Congress determine at any point that these remaining section
43(a) protections are insufficient to vindicate either, on the one hand, authors’ legitimate interests
in protecting their attribution and integrity interests, or, on the other hand, consumers’ legitimate
interest in knowing the authorship of the cultural products they consume, Congress may consider
adopting an amendment to section 43(a) that would expand the unfair competition protections to
304
The Sybersound court itself noted such a distinction, stating, “the nature, characteristics, and qualities of karaoke
recordings under the Lanham Act are more properly construed to mean characteristics of the good itself, such as the
original song and artist of the karaoke recording.” Sybersound, 517 F.3d at 1144.
305
To the extent that courts have read Dastar “to suggest that electronic products are not covered by the Lanham Act,”
such an interpretation does not seem to find any textual support in the actual language of the Lanham Act. Cvent, 739
F. Supp. 2d at 936.
306
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 33.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
59
include false representations regarding authorship of communicative works. The Office believes
further study of the issue is warranted before drafting specific statutory language to accomplish
this goal, and for this reason is not providing draft legislation at this time. Nonetheless, in the
Office’s view, any such an amendment should be narrowly crafted to focus on the purpose of the
Lanham Act, and thus protect only against consumer confusion or mistake as to authorship or
attribution, and not to provide expanded copyright protection, or afford the author any
additional control over permissible uses of the underlying work. Such a limitation would
mitigate against the Dastar court’s policy concerns about overlapping IP doctrines generally, and
limitations on public domain uses specifically.
2. Visual Artists Rights Act (“VARA”)
The Visual Artists Rights Act (“VARA”), which added section 106A to title 17, provides
limited moral rights of attribution and integrity for authors of qualifying “works of visual art.”
307
Specifically, section 106A protects a qualifying artist’s right to claim or disclaim authorship in a
work, and provides a limited right to prevent the distortion, mutilation, or modification of a
work, as well as to prevent the destruction of a “work of recognized stature.”
308
VARA permits
the author to waive these moral rights, which are not absolute, via a signed, written agreement
that specifies the work and the particular uses of the work to which the waiver applies.
309
However, rights under VARA are non-transferrable.
310
Because these rights are personal to the
author, the rights under VARA for works created after it took effect are not coextensive with the
term of copyright but expire upon the death of the author.
311
Congress took up the question of moral rights protection for visual artists two years after
the BCIA. In the Report accompanying H.R. 2690 (Visual Artists Rights Act of 1990), the House
Committee on the Judiciary noted that the 100th Congress, at the time of the BCIA debate, agreed
that “both Federal and State [laws], statutory and common, were sufficient to comply with the
307
Pub. L. No. 101-650, 104 Stat. 5128, 5128 (1990).
308
17 U.S.C. § 106A(a). A “work of visual art” is defined as:
(1) a painting, drawing, print, or sculpture, existing in a single copy, in a limited edition of
200 copies or fewer that are signed and consecutively numbered by the author, or, in the case of a
sculpture, in multiple cast, carved, or fabricated sculptures of 200 or fewer that are consecutively
numbered by the author and bear the signature or other identifying mark of the author; or (2) a still
photographic image produced for exhibition purposes only, existing in a single copy that is signed
by the author, or in a limited edition of 200 copies or fewer that are signed and consecutively
numbered by the author.”
17 U.S.C. § 101.
309
17 U.S.C. § 106A(e)(1).
310
Id.
311
See 17 U.S.C. § 106A(d). For works created before VARA took effect, the duration is coextensive with the term for
economic rights: life of the author plus 70 years. See 17 U.S.C. § 106A(d)(2).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
60
requirements of the [Berne] Convention[]” and “therefore enacted legislation to implement the
Convention’s requirements without also enacting additional moral rights laws.”
312
The Report
continued that the 100th Congress, however, believed that “adherence to the Berne Convention
did not end the debate about whether the United States should adopt artists’ rights laws,” and
thus pursued further consideration of moral rights protections in the United States, in the context
of visual art and artists.
313
In enacting VARA, Congress was responding to “[v]isual artists, such as painters and
sculptors, [who] have complained that their works are being mutilated and destroyed, that
authorship of their works is being misattributed, and that the American copyright system does
not enable them to share in any profits upon resale of their works.”
314
Congress intended the
rights outlined in VARA to be “analogous to those protected by Article 6bis of the Berne
Convention.”
315
While several states at that time offered limited rights for visual artists, Congress
expected VARA to establish a “uniform Federal system of rights for certain visual artists.”
316
The narrowness of the statute, both as drafted and as interpreted by the courts, has,
according to many, undermined the effectiveness of the moral rights afforded under VARA. The
study comments, in addition to the case law, highlight four areas of concern with the
interpretation and application of VARA’s rights: (1) the statutory definition of a work of visual
art as a threshold for VARA claims; (2) the effect of this limited definition of a work of visual art
on exercising the rights of attribution and integrity, coupled with the difficulty of extracting a
workable standard from the statute for these rights; (3) drafting inconsistencies with the duration
provision; and (4) limited public awareness of the waiver provision.
a) Limitations of VARA
VARA protections apply only to a “work of visual art,” as defined by section 101 of the
Copyright Act.
317
Under this statutory definition, a work of visual art is a (i) painting, drawing,
print, or sculpture, (ii) existing in a single copy or in a limited edition of 200 copies or fewer that
are signed and consecutively numbered by the author.
318
A still photographic image produced
for exhibition purposes also qualifies as a “work of visual art” as long as it exists in a single copy
312
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 7–8 (1990).
313
Id. at 8.
314
Id.
315
Id. at 5.
316
Id. at 9.
317
Pub. L. No. 101-650, § 602, 104 Stat. 5128, 5128 (codified at 17 U.S.C. § 101).
318
17 U.S.C. § 101. Limited editions of sculptures may contain a “signature or other identifying mark of the author.” Id.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
61
signed by the author or in a limited edition of 200 copies or fewer that are signed and
consecutively numbered by the author.
319
The case law, as well as the comments received in response to this Study, illustrate the
significance of the statutory definition of a “work of visual art” as a threshold for the rights under
VARA. The statutory definition excludes two large categories of works, the first being
obviously—works that are not visual in nature. The second exclusion is those visual artworks
that do not qualify as “works of visual art” under the section 101 definition, such as posters,
advertising material, and works made for hire.
320
Many commenters, both in and out of the NOI
process, argue that this second exclusion limits the usefulness of VARA in enforcing the
attribution and integrity rights of many authors of visual works.
321
(1) VARA Applies Only to “Visual” Works
VARA does not apply to copyrightable works that are not “visual” in subject matter, such
as literary and musical works. Congress, when enacting VARA, specifically chose to limit the
scope of the moral rights ascribed in the legislation to “works of visual art” only, and not to
works belonging to other categories of copyrightable subject matter. To justify this limited scope,
Congress explained that, unlike a motion picture or a literary work, which are susceptible to
reproduction without any diminution in their value, when an original work of visual art is
modified or destroyed, “it cannot be replaced.”
322
According to one witness before the House
Judiciary Subcommittee on Courts, Intellectual Property, and the Administration of Justice during
a hearing on the VARA bill, while section 106 exclusive rights ensure that creators of literary and
audiovisual works retain exclusive control over their works, they do not necessarily reflect the
needs of visual artists to protect and control the uses of their works, which tend to exist in single
copies (or very limited quantities) and not multiple reproductions like literary or musical
works.
323
Further justifying the limited scope of VARA, one academic that testified during hearings
before the House contended that an artist imparts his or her personality into a single- or limited-
copy work of visual art more than into a mass-produced work, and thus visual art that exists
solely in a single original or in very limited copies is particularly deserving of moral rights
319
Id. The statute does not specify at what point in the creative process the author must express the intent to exhibit, or
whether the author can use the photograph for any other purpose. See Lilley v. Stout, 384 F. Supp. 2d 83, 87–89 (D.D.C.
2005) (holding that photographs taken as part of a collaborative project were not for exhibition purposes only).
320
See 17 U.S.C. § 101.
321
See infra discussion on pages 64–70.
322
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 9 (1990).
323
See 1989 VARA Hearing at 100–01 (written statement of John B. Koegel, Esq.).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
62
protections.
324
The House Report for VARA quotes testimony before the House Judiciary
Subcommittee on Courts, Intellectual Property, and the Administration of Justice on this point,
emphasizing the unique value of the original work of art:
The original or few copies with which the artist was most in contact embody the
artist’s “personality” far more closely than subsequent mass produced images.
Accordingly, the physical existence of the original itself possesses an importance
independent from any communication of its contents by means of copies.
325
At the time of VARA’s enactment, Congress and stakeholders both noted the important
relationship between a single copy of a work that embodies an artist’s personality and
moral rights protection.
With these differences in mind, Congress drafted VARA to apply only to visual art and
not to other copyrightable works. Interpreting the statute strictly, courts have immediately
dismissed VARA claims when the work at issue is not a work of visual art subject matter. For
example, the district court in Hijrahannah v. Def Jam Recordings dismissed the plaintiff’s VARA
claims because the work at issue was sheet music.
326
Similarly, the district court in Kettenburg v.
University of Louisville dismissed a VARA claim because it was for a literary work.
327
At least two commenters have proposed that the protections outlined in VARA should be
extended to musical works and sound recordings. The Society of Composers & Lyricists
explained that music made to accompany audio-visual works is typically produced under work-
made-for-hire contracts, and urged that such musical works be “afforded the same protection” as
VARA works.
328
Likewise, the Recording Academy advocated that VARA-type protections for
324
See 1989 VARA Hearing at 84 (statement of Jane C. Ginsburg, Associate Professor of Law, Columbia University
School of Law).
325
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 12 (1990) (quoting 1989 VARA Hearing at 84 (statement of Jane C. Ginsburg, Associate
Professor of Law, Columbia University School of Law)). Notably, this argument better supports the moral right of
integrity than that of attribution. The right of attribution, Professor Ginsburg maintained, should be afforded to visual
art of all stripes, regardless of multiplicity of copies. See 1989 VARA Hearing at 85 (statement of Jane C. Ginsburg,
Associate Professor of Law, Columbia University School of Law).
326
Hijrahannah v. Def Jam Recordings, No. 14 C 0872, 2014 WL 3586055, at *2 (N.D. Ill. July 21, 2014) (dismissing for failure
to state a claim upon which relief can be granted, plaintiffs VARA claims regarding the use of his sheet music by other
artists).
327
Kettenburg v. Univ. of Louisville, No. CIVA 3:06CV79, 2005 WL 4444092, at *2 (W.D. Ky. June 16, 2005) (dismissing the
plaintiffs VARA claim concerning proper attribution for his creative writing class assignment).
328
Society of Composers & Lyricists (“SCL”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017,
Notice of Inquiry at 3 (Mar. 30, 2017) (“SCL Initial Comments”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
63
attribution should be accorded creators of musical works and sound recordings, specifically so
“songwriters, producers, engineers and non-featured artists” are given credit for their work.
329
Whether musical works or sound recordings should be protected by federal rights of
attribution and integrity is part of the fundamental question of whether there should be a blanket
statutory federal moral rights regime, and the Office has addressed that question above.
330
However, on the narrower question of whether VARA in particular should be expanded to
encompass musical works and sound recordings, the Office believes that such an approach would
contradict the purpose of VARA as explained in the legislative history. First, musical works and
sound recordings are made available to the public in mass-produced editions, not the single or
limited editions that make certain works of visual art so suitable for moral rights protection.
Second, as explained by the Society of Composers & Lyricists, musical works created to
accompany audio-visual works tend to be made-for-hire.
331
Works-made-for-hire are explicitly
excluded from VARA even if they are original visual art works.
332
Third, musical works and
sound recordings can benefit from contractual protections for attribution and integrity interests of
the sort not available to visual artists, who typically work without such contracts.
333
(2) Not All Visual Art Works are Covered by VARA
Although VARA covers visual art works, not all works of visual art qualify under the
statutory definition of a “work of visual art.”
334
Case law and the study comments highlight the
narrow scope of VARA resulting from this limited definition. According to the House Report for
VARA, “courts should use common sense and generally accepted standards of the artistic
community in determining whether a particular work falls within the scope of the definition.”
335
The following discussion outlines the various types of visual works of art that the courts have
interpreted as excluded from the statutory definition of a “work of visual art” for which the artist
can exercise his or her moral rights under VARA: (a) works made for hire, (b) commercial art, (c)
applied art, (d) non-copyrightable art, (e) preparatory works, and (f) site-specific works.
329
Recording Academy, Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of
Inquiry at 2 (May 15, 2017) (“Recording Academy Reply Comments”).
330
See supra pages 38–39.
331
SCL Initial Comments at 3.
332
See 17 U.S.C. § 101 (definition of “work of visual art”).
333
See American Association of Independent Music (A2IM”), Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S.
Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 5 (May 15, 2017) (“A2IM Reply Comments”) (“There is no
compelling reason for this expansion [VARA to sound recordings], and in fact, would negatively impact the
independent music community. Contractual provisions incorporating protections for attribution and integrity are
already part of many recording agreements.”).
334
See supra notes 317–320 and accompanying discussion.
335
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 11 (1990).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
64
(a) Works Made for Hire
Section 101’s definition of a “work of visual art” specifically excludes works made for
hire.
336
The House Report for VARA does not explain this exclusion, but in its comments on the
1989 VARA bill the U.S. Copyright Office noted that, “[a]s a practical matter, most works
described in the bill [e.g., works of visual art in single or limited editions] are not usually created
for hire.
337
Even witnesses in 1989 opposed to the work-made-for-hire exclusion pointed out that
a work created as a commissioned work-made-for-hire would typically be a mass-produced
work, and thus not covered by VARA.
338
These two pieces of testimony bolster the supposition
that VARA’s authors did not perceive a significant relationship between the visual art works they
were seeking to protect and the types of visual art that tend to be made for hire; thus they
excluded works made for hire from the definition of “work of visual art.” Recall that to qualify as
a work made for hire, a work must be either “prepared by an employee within the scope of his or
her employment,” or
specially ordered or commissioned for use as a contribution to a collective work,
as a part of a motion picture or other audiovisual work, as a translation, as a
supplementary work, as a compilation, as an instructional text, as a test, as
answer material for a test, or as an atlas, if the parties expressly agree in a written
instrument signed by them that the work shall be considered a work made for
hire.
339
Commissioned works in most, if not all, of these categories tend not to be works of visual art in
single or limited editions, hence the arguments above that the universes of works made for hire and
works intended to be protected by VARA seldom intersect.
There have been, however, cases that found that single-edition works which would
otherwise be covered by VARA were ultimately not protected by the statute because of the
employee status of the artist. For example, the Second Circuit in Carter v. Helmsley-Spear found the
plaintiffs’ sculpture to be a work made for hire as the plaintiffs were directed under contract to
336
17 U.S.C. § 101 (“A work of visual art does not include . . . (B) any work made for hire”). A work made for hire, as
defined by the Copyright Act, is a “work prepared by an employee within the scope of his employment” or “a work
specially ordered or commissioned for use as [nine categories of works] if the parties expressly agree in a written
instrument signed by them that the work shall be considered a work made for hire. Id.
337
See 1989 VARA Hearing at 65 (1989) (written statement of Ralph Oman, Register of Copyrights).
338
See id. at 86 (written statement of Jane C. Ginsburg, Associate Professor of Law, Columbia University School of Law)
(“Nor, I believe, is a works made for hire exception needed. The exception would essentially benefit proprietors of the
kinds of works listed in Section 101, for example, encyclopedias, atlases and periodicals. These are mass-produced
works, to which the right of integrity would not in any event apply.).
339
17 U.S.C § 101 (definition of “work made for hire”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
65
design, create, and install the sculpture while receiving employee benefits, such as a weekly
salary.
340
Thus, the court dismissed the plaintiffs’ VARA claims.
341
Some commenters suggested amending the statute and extending VARA protections
specifically to works made for hire.
342
One of these commenters stressed that the focus should be
on granting the right of attribution to commissioned works of visual art, and expressed concern
about whether artists are generally sufficiently informed of the details of contract law to negotiate
for attribution rights within work-made-for-hire contracts.
343
The other commenter argued for
both attribution and integrity rights for works-made-for-hire, which the commenter argued will
primarily apply to employee-created works.
344
With the aim of continuing to honor the integrity
of contracts, the Office at this time does not recommend extending VARA protections to visual
works made for hire.
The Office remains in agreement with its 1989 observation that, because of the limitations
of the statutory definition of “work made for hire,” the worlds of single- or limited-edition visual
art works and visual art works made for hire seldom intersect,
345
and further, that this argues for
excluding works made for hire from the section 101 definition of “works of visual art.” In its
comments for the current study, the Kernochan Center pointed out that “the number of works for
hire that would otherwise qualify as ‘works of visual art’ is likely to be relatively small,” both in
terms of specially ordered or commissioned works and works created by employees.
346
While this
comment was intended to bolster the argument for including works made for hire in the
definition of “work[s] of visual art,” it can just as easily cut in the other direction. Specifically, if
the universe of works made for hire contain relatively few otherwise VARA-eligible works, then
removing the work made for hire exclusion won’t make much of a difference to the majority of
340
Referring to the work-made-for-hire test articulated by the Supreme Court in Community for Creative Non-Vi olence v.
Reid, 490 U.S. 730 (1989), the Second Circuit held that the artwork was a work made for hire under the same standard.
Carter v. Helmsley-Spear, Inc. (“Carter II”), 71 F.3d 77, 87–88 (2d Cir. 1995).
341
See Carter II, 71 F.3d at 88. See also MG Design Assocs., Corp. v. Costar Realty Info. Inc., 224 F. Supp. 3d 621, 634–35 (N.D.
Ill. 2016) (dismissing plaintiffs VARA claim because the designs at issue were done as a work made for hire).
342
See CVA Initial Comments at 5–9; Kernochan Center Initial Comments at 7; see also David E. Shipley, The Empty
Promise of VARA: The Restrictive Application of a Narrow Statute, 83 MISS. L.J. 985, 1010 (2014) (“[T]he idea that the
employee-artist does not have moral rights in the creations done for an employer is antithetical to moral rights
theory.”).
343
See CVA Initial Comments at 5–7, 9 (“There is no reason why the moral right of attribution should be stripped from
an independent creator and assigned to someone else who is not their employer in a work made for hire contract . . . .”).
344
See Kernochan Center Initial Comments at 7 n.19.
345
See 1989 VARA Hearing at 65 (written statement of Ralph Oman, Register of Copyrights).
346
Kernochan Center Initial Comments at 7 n.19. See also id. (“Most commissioned artworks do not fit within the nine
statutory categories of ‘specially ordered or commissioned works’ that are capable of being works made for hire. . . .
Moreover, most employee-created artworks (such as greeting cards and comic books) are not likely to be produced as
single originals or only as limited editions of under 200 copies signed and numbered.”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
66
working artists. On the contrary, the Office believes that it would negatively alter the very nature
of a work made for hire relationship by undercutting the claim of the employer to “authorship”
status.
(b) Commercial Art
Section 101’s definition of a “work of visual art” also excludes “any merchandising item or
advertising, promotional, descriptive, covering, or packaging material or container,” preventing
authors from exercising their moral rights for these works under VARA.
347
The House Report on
VARA does not explain or give examples of what is meant by this limiting language.
Contemporaneous hearings have but one reference, in written testimony to a Senate Judiciary
Committee hearing by the National Newspaper Association (“NNA”), illustrating several
complications that could result from granting moral rights to artists who create images used in
advertising.
348
While there is no way to know if the NNA’s testimony influenced Congress, it is at
least one indication of what Congress might have been considering. Of course, this does not help
in understanding the other exclusions in the definition, such as promotional or descriptive
material that are not used in advertising.
A number of cases have denied an artist protection under VARA because the work was
considered promotional or advertising material.
349
For example, the court in Pollara v. Seymour
found that the “objective and evident purpose” of a banner created as part of a lobbying effort to
promote a specific message rendered the banner as promotional and advertising material and not
an eligible work of visual art, despite the artistic ability and creativity inherent in the work.
350
The
concurrence, however, disagreed with the majority’s test for commercial or promotional material
and explained that excluding from the definition of visual art all works that “promote” is
unworkable, because, under that formulation, any painting or sculpture commissioned to
347
17 U.S.C. § 101.
348
See Moral Rights in Our Copyright Laws: Hearings on S. 1198 and S. 1253 Before the Subcomm. on Patents, Copyrights and
Trademarks of the S. Comm. on the Judiciary, 101st Cong. 689 (1989) (written statement of Jack Fishman, National
Newspaper Association) (“Would the newspaper have to receive permission to reduce the size of a drawing, or to
augment a simple drawing, or combine several? Would permission have to be obtained before a black and white ad
was run in color, or a color ad run in black and white? What would we do when our ad department received camera-
ready copy which had no attribution on it? Refuse the ad? Track down the artist?”).
349
See, e.g., MG Design, 224 F. Supp. 3d at 634–35 (finding that renderings of trade show designs were not visual art in
part because they “were a design for a client's commercial promotion and intended to profit MG and attract more
business for MG and its client”); Benke v. Departure Agency, Inc., No. CV 11-397, 2011 WL 13129964, at *4 (C.D. Cal. Aug.
11, 2011) (finding that photographs commissioned by a hotel were not visual art because they were produced solely to
advertise the hotel services”).
350
Pollara v. Seymour, 344 F.3d 265, 269–71 (2d Cir. 2003).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
67
promote a specific idea such as the Olympics or AIDS awareness “could never receive protection
under VARA.
351
In its comments, the Coalition of Visual Artists objected to VARA’s exclusion of
commercial art as sending the message that certain types of commercial art, specifically design,
illustration, and photography, are “unworthy of moral rights.
352
According to the Coalition,
these types of artworks do not have different artistic merit than fine art — the art typically
associated with VARA. Instead, the Coalition argued that the distinction between fine art and
commercial art is not as clear in the digital age as it might have been when VARA was enacted,
and commercial art should not be excluded in this manner from moral rights protection.
353
The Office does not believe that Congress excluded commercial and promotional works
from the definition of “work of visual art” because it believed such images to be somehow
artistically less worthy than so-called “fine art.” Instead, it appears more likely that, following
the sort of arguments put forth by the NNA, that Congress wanted to avoid interfering with
works of art that were controlled or influenced by an entity other than the artist—and hence
presumably are less attached to the artist’s reputation—as well as avoid interfering with
contractual freedoms. The Office accepts this apparent reasoning, but does believe that the
commercial/”fine art” distinction can be drawn more narrowly than the current statute has it.
Regarding Pollara, the Office agrees with both the majority and the concurrence: The majority is
correct in its finding that the exclusion of a banner “created for the purpose of promoting and
advertising” is required by the statute, regardless of the content of its message or skill of its
design.
354
The concurrence, also, is correct in pointing out the logical conclusion of this broad
exclusion—that artwork that merely promotes an idea or a cause, without commercial intent,
would be excluded from VARA protection.
355
Pollara indicates, then, the need for re-visiting VARA’s exclusions from the term “work of
visual art.” Despite the clear message of the statutory language, Congress in 1989 betrayed no
intent to exclude artworks that independently promote ideas or causes.
356
It did, however, as
shown in the 1989 hearing transcripts, take testimony regarding the necessity of excluding
351
Id. at 271 (Gleeson, J., concurring).
352
CVA Initial Comments at 3.
353
Id. at 13.
354
Pollara, 344 F.3d at 270.
355
Pollara, 344 F.3d at 271–72 (Gleeson, J., concurring).
356
For discussions of some examples of such artwork, see, e.g., Margaret Carrigan, What Happens When Social Practice
Art Meets the Market?, ARTSY (Aug. 30, 2017, 6:44 PM), https://www.artsy.net/article/artsy-editorial-social-practice-art-
meets-market (discussing the impact of social practice art); Maria D. Leake, Art as Social Practice: Exploring the
Contemporary, ART EDUC., Mar. 2012, at 25, 26–32; M.H. Miller, Protest Art in the Era of Trump, N.Y. TIMES STYLE MAG.
(Feb. 20, 2017), available at http://www.nytimes.com/2017/02/20/t-magazine/protest-art-betty-tompkins-postcommodity-
rirkrit-tiravanija.html.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
68
artworks created on the basis of a contract.
357
Hence, barring VARA protection for some
commercial art may be appropriate for moral rights protection, but barring art that independently
promotes a social or political message absent of any commercial intent seems to the Office to be a
step too far.
Based on its analysis in the discussion above, the Office recommends that Congress
consider a statutory amendment concerning the definition of a “work of visual art” to enable
more artists to claim moral rights protection for visual art that promotes a particular cause or
viewpoint, and to clarify the scope of “commercial art” excluded from VARA protections.
Specifically, the Office recommends adopting the definition of an eligible work similar to that
used by the California Art Preservation Act, adding the phrase “prepared under contract for
commercial use by its purchaser” to the definition in section 101.
358
A proposed section 101
would thus read:
a work of visual art does not include (A) . . . (ii) any merchandising item or
advertising, promotional, descriptive, covering, or packaging material or
container, any of which are prepared under contract for commercial use by its
purchaser.
This proposed standard specifically excludes art created to call attention to a particular
product or service in the commercial context. However, art that may promote a particular
social/non-commercial message carries the same concerns for attribution and integrity as other
visual art. Therefore, “protest art” or art created for a political purpose or social cause that
promotes a particular message would not be excluded based on the particular use of the work
under the proposed section 101 work of visual art definition.
359
The content and meaning of the
work should not serve as a barrier to these important moral rights protections.
(c) Applied Art
VARA’s standard for a “work of visual art” also specifically excludes “applied art,”
360
which the statute does not define. While Congress in the VARA legislative history referred to the
exclusions, including applied art, as “self-explanatory,”
361
courts have struggled to find a
workable standard for when a work qualifies as applied art in the context of VARA. In Carter v.
Helmsley-Spear, Inc., the Second Circuit held that a sculpture consisting of pieces of a school bus,
automobile parts, and a number of interactive components affixed to a wall and ceiling and
357
See 1989 VARA Hearing at 65 (written statement of Ralph Oman, Register of Copyrights) (addressing potential VARA
protection of works made for hire).
358
CAL. CIV. CODE § 987(b)(2).
359
For example, the banner created to lobby a social cause (legal aid for prisoners) in Pollara would qualify as a work of
visual art under the proposed standard. See supra notes infra [x]-[xxx] and accompanying text.
360
17 U.S.C. § 101 (“A work of visual art does not include(A)(i) . . . applied art[.]”).
361
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 13 (1990).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
69
embedded in the floor and wall of a building lobby was not applied art.
362
The appellate court
reiterated the district court’s explanation that “applied art” encompassed “two- and three-
dimensional ornamentation or decoration that is affixed to otherwise utilitarian objects.”
363
The
appellate court further held that the sculpture in this particular case was not applied art even
though it was affixed to “the lobby’s floor, walls, and ceiling, because “[i]nterpreting applied art
to include such works would render meaningless VARA’s protection for works of visual art
installed in buildings.”
364
Attempting to create a workable standard for “applied art,” the Ninth Circuit in Cheffins v.
Stewart considered whether La Contessa, a school bus adorned in the trappings of a 16th-century
Spanish galleon, was applied art—that is, the object of the art “initially served a utilitarian
function and . . . continues to serve such a function after the artist made embellishments or
alterations to it.
365
While the concurrence contended that this standard would frustrate the
purpose of VARA by “unduly narrowing the protections of artists,”
366
the majority defended this
standard by focusing on the object’s “practical utility” instead of its “artistic merit.”
367
While
acknowledging the artistic qualities of La Contessa, the court concluded that La Contessa was
applied art as it began as a rudimentary object and continued to be used for transportation and as
an entertainment stage after its transformation.
368
While commenters in this study did not specifically discuss applied art in this context, the
concurrence in Cheffins criticized the lack of appropriate definitions in VARA and the absence of
any guidance developing in the case law.
369
The concurrence further emphasized that a more
nuanced test was necessary that would “evaluate the work as a whole” and serve the greater
purpose of VARA.
370
The Office finds persuasive the Cheffins concurrence’s assessment of the
362
Carter II, 71 F.3d at 80, 85.
363
Id. at 84–85 (2d Cir. 1995) (quoting Carter v. Helmsley-Spear, Inc. (“Carter I”), 861 F. Supp. 303, 315 (S.D.N.Y. 1994)).
364
Carter II, 71 F.3d at 85.
365
Cheffins v. Stewart, 825 F.3d 588, 594 (9th Cir. 2016).
366
Id. at 597–98 (McKeown, J., concurring). More specifically, the concurrence argued that the definition fails to
consider the work as a whole and “fails to clarify when the product of artistic creation has crossed the threshold of
functionality that transforms it form visual to applied art.” Id. at 599. The concurrence proposed that the standard
should consider the primary purpose of the work instead and whether the artistic features are subservient to a useful
function. Id. at 602.
367
Cheffins, 825 F.3d at 594.
368
Cheffins, 825 F.3d at 595.
369
See id. at 600 (McKeown, J., concurring) (“The difficulty of our job is compounded because VARA provides no
definitions of applied art. Leaders of the art community warned Congress that VARAdoes not offer firm definitions’ of
applied and visual art, leaving ‘open for conjecture the kinds of art and artists eligible for protection. [But] Congress
was unmoved.”) (internal citation omitted).
370
Id. at 602 (McKeown, J., concurring).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
70
inadequacy of current judicial standards. The absence of any applicable statutory or legislative
guidance has led to an imprecise judicial standard and uncertainty, at the very least, in the art
world.
371
The Office suggests that Congress re-evaluate VARA’s lack of guidance as to the
exclusion of applied art and consider whether an amendment making its intent clear is
warranted, to ensure the exclusion is not overly broad and that courts can apply a uniform
standard. Specifically, the Office recommends further study of how working artists understand
the term and how courts have interpreted it.
(d) Non-copyrightable Art
Works ineligible for copyright protection also do not qualify as works of visual art under
VARA.
372
In Kelley v. Chicago Park District, the Seventh Circuit Court of Appeals dismissed
Chapman Kelley’s claim that the park district violated his right of integrity under VARA for
modifying his Chicago Wildflower Works (1984–2004), a wildflower display planted in a public
park.
373
The Seventh Circuit found that because Kelley’s garden was “neither ‘authored’ nor
fixedin the senses required for copyright,” the work could not qualify for moral rights
protection under VARA.
374
Chapman Kelley, in his comment for this study, argued that VARA’s
definition of a “work of visual art” should be amended to include works similar to his Chicago
Wildflower Works.
375
Kelley contended not only that his work satisfies the fixation requirement for
copyright, but also that “it is unwise to set ‘art’ guidelines . . . and to make legal constraints for
it.
376
The Office disagrees that including non-copyrightable art within the VARA framework is
appropriate. Providing moral rights protection to art that does not qualify for copyright
protection would improperly extend the scope of copyright law. Recall that VARA protects only
a “work of visual art, which definitionally excludes “any work not subject to copyright
371
See Lena Saltos, Cheffins v. Stewart: Burning Man; Burning Ships, HHR ART LAW (July 5, 2016),
http://www.hhrartlaw.com/2016/07/cheffins-v-stewart-burning-man-burning-ships (“[T]he test the majority adopted
may not provide the clarity and objectivity for which it hoped. . . . This will significantly narrow the reach of VARA and
deter artists from bringing claims with respect to destruction of works that may incorporate utilitarian elements, thusly
undermining one of VARAs main goals.”).
372
See 17 U.S.C. § 101 (“A work of visual art does not include— . . . (C) any work not subject to copyright protection
under this title.”).
373
Kelley v. Chi. Park Dist., 635 F.3d 290, 306 (7th Cir. 2011).
374
Id.
375
See Chapman Kelley, Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 3
(Mar. 27, 2017) (“Chapman Kelley Initial Comments”); see also Jenny Keller, Comments Submitted in Response to U.S.
Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 1 (Apr. 4, 2017) (“Pleases [sic] amend VARA to include works of
art, especially Chicago Wildflower Work (CWW) by Chapman Kelley. This original work is important to art history
and to the arts community, but especially to the viewing public.”).
376
Chapman Kelley Initial Comments at 3.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
71
protection under this title.”
377
Extending VARA to non-copyrightable works could require a
statutory amendment and would threaten the creation of the very kind of “mutant copyright”
warned against by the Supreme Court in the Dastar case.
378
Moreover, it would be unreasonable
to grant moral rights—rights that are personal to the author—to art that does not qualify as
having sufficient original, human expression for copyright protection.
379
(e) Preparatory Works
The text of VARA specifically excludes “models” from the definition of a work of visual
art. Nevertheless, artists have attempted to bring VARA claims regarding preparatory works
made in the process of creating the final product. While the House Report accompanying H.R.
2690 advises that “courts should use common sense and generally accepted standards of the
artistic community in determining whether a particular work falls within the scope of the
definition,”
380
VARA’s legislative history does not specifically discuss the relationship between
barring “models” and the question of preparatory works in general.
With this limited guidance, the courts have not consistently held whether preparatory
works qualify as a work of visual art or as an ineligible “model. In Flack v. Friends of Queen
Catherine, Inc., the court for the Southern District of New York considered whether a clay head
that was used to cast a bronze statue was a work of visual art or amodelexcluded from VARA
protection.
381
The court observed that neither the statute nor the legislative history of VARA
provides much guidance with determining the meaning of the word “model.”
382
Relying on the
art community’s acceptance and exhibition of clay sculptures as works of art in their own right,
the court found that the preparatory clay head in this case was a work of visual art independent
of the final bronze statute.
383
The Third Circuit in NASCAR v. Scharle, however, did not refer to
the standards of the artistic community when determining whether drawings for the two-
dimensional design of a trophy fell into the purview of VARA.
384
Instead, the court interpreted
these particular drawings as “technical drawings, diagrams, or models for the trophy,” and not
377
17 U.S.C. § 101 (definition of “work of visual art”).
378
Dastar, 539 U.S. at 34.
379
See Naruto v. Slater, 888 F.3d 418, 420 (9th Cir. 2018) (finding that animals lack statutory standing under the Copyright
Act).
380
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 11 (1990).
381
Flack v. Friends of Queen Catherine Inc., 139 F. Supp. 2d 526, 532 (S.D.N.Y. 2001).
382
Id. at 533 (“The legislative history is completely devoid, however, of any indication of the meaning of the word
‘model.’ Indeed, when the exclusionary portion of the definition of ‘a work of visual art’ is discussed at all, the
distinction emphasized is that between fine art, on the one hand, and movies, books, newspapers, magazines, and other
creative works on the other.”).
383
Id. at 533–34.
384
See Nat’l Ass’n for Stock Car Auto Racing, Inc. (“NASCAR”) v. Scharle, 184 Fed. App’x. 270 (3d Cir. 2006).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
72
works of visual art, as the drawings only “represented multiple attempts to arrive at the optimal
design for the trophy,” the final product.
385
The Study comments did not specifically discuss models or preparatory works in the
context of VARA’s definition of a “work of visual art,” and the Copyright Office has no cause to
make a recommendation on this topic beyond a suggestion that courts take seriously the House
Report’s admonition to “use . . . generally accepted standards of the artistic community” when
evaluating a work’s status as a “work of visual art.”
386
So far, the courts have inconsistently
applied this instruction when evaluating preparatory works. The Office, however, finds a useful
model in the court’s application of community standards in Flack v. Friends of Queen Catherine, Inc.
In different areas of copyright law, the courts tend to avoid any analysis of the artistic merits of
the work and defer to the expertise of those in the community.
387
Adopting this approach for
interpreting preparatory works in the VARA context more appropriately responds to the
particular goals of the statute.
(f) Site-specific Art
VARA does not specifically mention site-specific works”works that are fundamentally
integrated with their setting and are considered incomplete when perceived in isolation. The
nature of site-specific art signifies that removing the work from its original site ultimately
destroys the work, rendering this category of art particularly relevant in the VARA context.
With the absence of any mention of site-specific works in the statute, courts have again
inconsistently interpreted whether site-specific works fall under the definition of “work of visual
art.” For example, the First Circuit in Phillips v. Pembroke Real Estate, found that VARA does not
apply to site-specific art, in this case a multi-element sculpture designed for a specific park.
388
The
court relied upon the public presentation exception under section 106A(c)(2), which states that a
“modification of a work of visual art which is the result of . . . public presentation . . . is not a
destruction, distortion, mutilation, or other modification.”
389
According to the court, allowing
VARA to protect site-specific works would ultimately create two different regimes: “one for free-
standing works of art . . . and one for site-specific art that can never be moved and must always
385
Id. at 276 (internal citations omitted).
386
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 11 (1990).
387
See, e.g., Bleistein v. Donaldson Lithographing Co., 188 U.S. 239, 251 (1903) (“It would be a dangerous undertaking for
persons trained only to the law to constitute themselves final judges of the worth of pictorial illustrations, outside of the
narrowest and most obvious limits.”); Esquire, Inc. v. Ringer, 591 F.2d 796, 805 (D.C. Cir. 1978) (“Neither the Constitution
nor the Copyright Act authorizes the Copyright Office or the federal judiciary to serve as arbiters of national taste.”);
Christine Haight Farley, Judging Art, 79 TUL. L. REV. 805, 810–19 (2005) (examining arguments about why judges should
not judge art).
388
See Phillips v. Pembroke Real Estate, Inc., 459 F.3d 128, 140–43 (1st Cir. 2006).
389
Id. at 133 (quoting 17 U.S.C. § 106A(c)(2)).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
73
be displayed.”
390
The court held that “the plain language of VARA does not protect site-specific
art,” but “[i]f such protection is necessary, Congress should do the job.”
391
The Seventh Circuit in Kelley v. Chicago Park District offered a different perspective on the
relationship between VARA and site-specific art and warned against the strict interpretation
adopted by the Phillips court.
392
In doing so, it raised three counterarguments, namely: (1) “site-
specific art” is not mentioned at all in the statute as being excluded or otherwise, leaving the
courts with more flexibility concerning this question; (2) the section 106A(c)(2) public
presentation exception does not waive all VARA rights for site-specific art, including the right of
attribution, and thus the argument in Phillips that the public presentation exception is an
indication that site-specific art should not be protected does not hold; and (3) the building
exception in section 113(d) seems to indicate that the statute acknowledges potential protection
for site-specific art.
393
One commenter called for expanding VARA to explicitly include site-specific works. She
argued that the “artist’s ability to articulate the nature and importance of the site-specificity of an
artwork” justifies VARA protection.
394
She further explained that this proposed expansion of
VARA “seems barely more burdensome to property owners, and, appropriately, a good deal
more respectful to artists.”
395
At this time, the Office agrees with the Kelley court that courts have
flexibility in applying VARA to works of site-specific art, but finds that the ancillary legal issues
relating to site-specific art, such as the rules in section 113(d) regarding a work of visual art that
has been incorporated in a building, and the obligations thereto of the building’s owner,
396
disfavor a one-size-fits-all statutory change to ensure any meaningful and appropriate expansion
of moral rights to these works. Moreover, the overlap between site-specific works and other
390
Id. at 143.
391
Id.
392
Kelley v. Chi. Park Dist. 635 F.3d 290, 306–07 (7th Cir. 2011) (analyzing Phillips v. Pembroke Real Estate, Inc., 459 F.3d 128
(1st Cir. 2006)).
393
Id. Section 113(d), known as “the building exception” states that works “incorporated in or made part of a building
in such a way that removing the work from the building will cause the destruction, distortion, mutilation, or other
modification of the work” do not qualify for moral rights protection if the artist (1) consented to the installation of the
work in the building (if pre-VARA enactment) or (2) executed a written acknowledgement that removal of the work
may subject it to destruction, distortion, mutilation, or modification (if post-VA RA e n act men t) . See 17 U.S.C. § 113(d).
394
Sarah Conley Odenkirk, Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry
at 2 (Mar. 19, 2017) (“Odenkirk Initial Comments”).
395
Id. at 2.
396
See 17 U.S.C. § 113(d).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
74
categories of visual art may overcome these challenges prompted by the ancillary legal issues and
provide sufficient moral rights protection when appropriate.
397
b) Actionable Conduct: VARA Rights of Attribution & Integrity
Generally, the courts resolve most VARA cases on the threshold question whether the
plaintiff’s work is a work of visual art as defined by the statute. Thus, scant case law exists
discussing the specific standards, especially for the appropriate remedies, for violations of the
right of attribution and right of integrity under VARA.
398
The few cases in which the courts
substantively discuss the rights of attribution and integrity highlight specific problems in the
interpretation and application of the statutory standards relating to both rights.
(1) Right of Attribution
Under VARA, an artist exercising the right of attribution may claim authorship of his or
her work of visual art and prevent another party from using the artist’s name on works not
created by the artist.
399
This provision upholds the artist’s right to be associated with works that
reflect only his or her artistic vision.
400
VARA also provides the artist with the right to prevent the use of his or her name as
author of a work of visual art that has been distorted, mutilated, or modified in a way that would
be “prejudicial to his or her honor or reputation.”
401
This right blends the objectives of both the
attribution and integrity rights as it forbids the combination of alteration of a work together with
inaccurate attribution of the altered work to the particular artist.
402
According to the legislative
history, the standard for determining whether an action is “prejudicial” to an artist’s reputation is
397
See Cohen v. G & M Realty L.P. (“5Pointz”), No. 15-CV-3230, 2018 WL 851374 (E.D.N.Y. Feb. 12, 2018) (awarding
damages to the artists for the destruction of site-specific graffiti art).
398
See Mass. Museum of Contemporary Art Found., Inc. (“MASS MoCA”) v. Büchel, 593 F.3d 38, 53 (1st Cir. 2010) (“[C]ourts
avoid construing the extent of VARA protection by finding that works do not meet the threshold requirements for
‘visual art’ protected by VARA. Unsurprisingly, therefore, we have found no case law discussing a possible difference
in the showing required for injunctive relief and damages for right-of-integrity claims.”) (cleaned up).
399
17 U.S.C. § 106A(a)(1)(A)–(B).
400
See H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 5 (1990) (stating that the attribution right “ensures that artists are correctly identified
with the works of art they create, and that they are not identified with works created by others”).
401
17 U.S.C. § 106A(a)(2).
402
See Mass. Museum of Contemporary Art Found., Inc. (“MASS MoCA”) v. Büchel, 565 F. Supp. 2d 245, 256–57 (D. Mass.
2008) (“This aspect of VARA protection would prevent a third party from taking Artist As finished sculpture, for
example, and chopping pieces off it, or painting it blue, and then exhibiting it as As work.”), aff’d in part, vacated in part,
remanded, 593 F.3d 38 (1st Cir. 2010).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
75
“flexible” and should “focus on the artistic or professional honor or reputation of the
individual.”
403
Section 106A(c)(3) provides an exception to the attribution right by immunizing
defendants from liability for “any reproduction, depiction, portrayal, or other use of the work” in
connection with the types of works listed under subparagraphs (A) and (B) of the definition of a
work of visual art, which includes posters, technical drawings, models, books, magazines,
newspapers, periodicals, advertising, promotional material, or works made for hire.
404
Under this
exception, a reproduction of an artist’s visual work on a poster or in a magazine need not be
accompanied by the artist’s name. Many of the attribution claims brought under VARA focus on
a reproduction, not the original, work of visual art. Courts have consistently dismissed these
claims under this exception.
405
Neither the courts nor the study comments have dealt with the substance of VARAs right
of attribution. Any study comments that mentioned the right of attribution under VARA
generally advocated for Congress to extend this right to other types of copyrighted works or
works of visual art that do not fit under the statutory definition.
406
As discussed above, extending
the right of attribution under VARA to other types of copyrighted works would certainly involve
amending the definition of a “work of visual art,”
407
as well as generally expanding VARA well
beyond its current limits. The Office awaits future court decisions that may further illuminate the
issue of the attribution right under VARA.
403
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 15 (1990).
404
17 U.S.C. § 106A(c)(3). According to the legislative history, the actions that fall under this exception “do not affect
the single or limited edition copy,” and thus “imposing liability in these situations would not further the paramount
goal of the legislation: to preserve and protect certain categories of original works of art.” H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 18
(1990).
405
See, e.g., Wilson v. New Palace Casino, L.L.C., No. 1:11cv447, 2013 WL 870350, at *3–4 (S.D. Miss. Mar. 7, 2013)
(dismissing the artist’s attribution claim in relation to reproductions of a feature of his original painting); Martin v. Walt
Disney Internet Grp., No. 09CV1601, 2010 WL 2634695, at *5 (S.D. Cal. June 30, 2010) (dismissing the plaintiffs
attribution claim regarding reproductions of her photograph); Silberman v. Innovation Luggage, Inc., No. 01 Civ. 7109,
2003 WL 1787123, at *4–5 (S.D.N.Y. Apr. 3, 2003) (holding that the artist could not assert an attribution claim under
VARA in relation to unsigned reproductions of the artist’s original photograph).
406
See, e.g., American Society of Journalists and Authors (“ASJA”), Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright
Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 5 (Mar. 30, 2017) (ASJA Initial Comments”) (“It is our understanding that the
United States recognizes moral rights (although only attribution and integrity) for visual artists through VARA . . . but
not for authors. So we ask, why should one sort of creative work get moral rights protections, but not others?”); CVA
Initial Comments at 5 (“The moral right of attribution should include works created by independent creators created
under work made for hire contracts.”); Recording Academy Reply Comments at 2 (“The Academy believes that similar
protections, with respect to the right of attribution, should be extended to the creators of musical works and sound
recordings to ensure that credit is also granted to songwriters, producers, engineers and non-featured artists . . . .”).
407
See supra discussion on pages 64–70.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
76
(2) Right of Integrity
The right of integrity under VARA consists of two parts: (a) the right to prevent any
intentional distortion, mutilation, or other modification that would be prejudicial to the artist’s
honor or reputation;
408
and (b) the right to prevent any destruction of a work of recognized
stature.
409
Congress intended the right of integrity to further the public interest in preserving and
protecting works of visual art and thereby preserving the integrity of our shared culture.
410
The
case law and the study comments have highlighted several issues regarding the interpretation
and scope of these two rights of integrity.
(a) Prejudicial to Artist’s Reputation
As stated above, VARA extends to artists of works of visual art the right to prevent any
intentional distortion, mutilation, or other modification of their work that would be prejudicial to
the artist’s honor or reputation.
411
However, VARA limits this right with three exceptions. A
work is not distorted, mutilated or otherwise modified for these purposes if the modification is
the result of the passage of time or the inherent nature of the materials.
412
Similarly, the
modification of a work of visual art resulting from conservation or public presentation (including
lighting and placement) does not qualify as destruction, distortion, mutilation, or other
modification in this context unless the modification is caused by gross negligence.
413
Conservation by a person without sufficient training may qualify as gross negligence, but it is not
clear whether it would constitute a violation of the VARA right of integrity.
414
In its study
comments, the Artists Rights Society argued that gross negligence “is extremely difficult to
establish,” and poor restoration or conservation may leave the artist “without recourse.
415
While the statute itself does not provide any guidance on the scope of the right of integrity
relating to prejudicial harm, the VARA House Report recommended that the courts “focus on the
artistic or professional honor or reputation of the individual as embodied in the work that is
408
17 U.S.C. § 106A(a)(3)(A).
409
17 U.S.C. § 106A(a)(3)(B).
410
See H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 5–6 (1990); see also John H. Merryman, The Refrigerator of Bernard Buffet, 27 HASTINGS L.J.
1023, 1042 (1976) (arguing that the pre-VARA copyright “law provides no way to protect the public interest in
preservation of our culture against revision of works of art by unilateral unauthorized action”). But see Amy M. Adler,
Against Moral Rights, 97 CALIF. L. REV. 263, 290–93 (2009) (arguing that the preservation emphasis of VARA is
inappropriate for contemporary art—the only type of art that VARA protects).
411
17 U.S.C. § 106A(a)(3)(A).
412
17 U.S.C. § 106A(c)(1).
413
17 U.S.C. § 106A(c)(2).
414
See Flack v. Friends of Queen Catherine Inc., 139 F. Supp. 2d 526, 535 (S.D.N.Y. 2001).
415
ARS Initial Comments at 2.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
77
protected” and “examine the way in which a work has been modified and the professional
reputation of the author of the work.”
416
The appellate court in MASS MoCA v. Büchel interpreted
this standard to require a showing of prejudicial harm to the artist’s reputation in relation to the
alteration of the specific work of art at issue in the case in order for the plaintiff to receive
damages.
417
In this case, the court considered the prejudicial harm to the plaintiff’s reputation
associated with a particular unfinished installation that the museum had modified.
418
The Office
agrees with the interpretation of this right by the court in MASS MoCA, specifically that the harm
to the artist’s reputation should be assessed in the context of the particular work at issue and not
the artist’s reputation concerning his or her entire oeuvre. Such an interpretation is consistent
with VARA’s general focus on particular works.
419
(b) Definition of ”Work of Recognized Stature
As stated above, VARA grants the artist the right to “prevent any destruction of a work of
recognized stature.”
420
Despite its legal significance, the term “recognized stature” is not defined
in the statute. However, the VARA bill as introduced in the House in 1989 addressed the concept
of protecting against the destruction of works of recognized stature and included the following
language:
In determining whether a work is of recognized stature, a court or other trier of
fact may take into account the opinions of artists, art dealers, collectors of fine
art, curators of art museums, conservators, and other persons involved with the
creation, appreciation, history, or marketing of works of visual art. Evidence of
commercial exploitation of a work as a whole, or of particular copies, does not
preclude a finding that the work is a work of recognized stature.
421
This language was omitted from the bill during markup, as the House Committee on the
Judiciary sought to avoid “a battle of expert witnesses” and increased litigation that they
predicted would have resulted from this definition.
422
Thus, absent statutory text or direct
416
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 15–16 (1990).
417
See Mass. Museum of Contemporary Art Found., Inc. (“MASS MoCA”) v. Büchel, 593 F.3d 38, 53–54 (1st Cir. 2010). See
also 3 NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 8D.06[C][1][c] (noting that “an intentional and prejudicial mutilation is an integrity
violation, remediable through not only an injunction, but damages as well”).
418
See MASS MoCA, 593 F.3d at 42–46.
419
See H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 15 (1990) (quoting 1989 VARA Hearing at 106 (written statement of John B. Koegel, Esq.)
(“An artists professional and personal identity is embodied in each work created by that artist. Each work is a part of
his/her reputation. Each work is a form of personal expression . . . .”)).
420
17 U.S.C. § 106A(a)(3)(B).
421
H.R. 2690, 101st Cong. § 3 (as introduced in the House, Jun. 20, 1989).
422
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 15 (1990).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
78
legislative history, courts were left to develop a workable standard on their own, and despite
Congress’ intentions, such battles have occurred.
The district court in Carter v. Helmsley-Spear, Inc. formulated a test that the art must be
(1) meritorious and (2) recognized by art experts and other members of the artistic community as
such.
423
The Seventh Circuit in Martin v. City of Indianapolis accepted letters, articles, and awards
as evidence of recognized stature.
424
More recently, in Cohen v. G & M Realty L.P. (“5Pointz II),
425
a jury found 45 out of 49 graffiti works to be works of recognized stature based on the artistic
recognition of the works outside of the graffiti site, the art world’s academic and professional
interest in the works, and the skill and craftsmanship inherent in the works.
426
The 5Pointz II
court found that the testimony of the defendants’ expert was flawed as an “unduly restrictive
interpretation of recognized stature that was more akin to a masterpiece standard.”
427
Generally, the courts have focused their inquiries on whether the work itself, not the artist,
has achieved recognized stature.
428
In Scott v. Dixon, the court found that while the artist had
“achieved some level of local notoriety, the work, a swan sculpture installed in the backyard of a
property, had not achieved “recognized stature” as it had never been publicly exhibited but only
privately displayed.
429
Questioning this judicially developed standard, one commenter in the
Office study pointed out that the statute does not explicitly require public display in order to
achieve “recognized stature.”
430
One commenter suggested that the “judicial application of the [recognized stature
requirement 17 U.S.C. 106A(a)(3)(A)] has been overly restrictive and has thwarted fulfillment of
423
Carter I, 861 F. Supp. at 325 (considering VARA claim for a sculpture installed in the lobby of a commercial building),
aff’d in part, vacated in part, reversed in part on other grounds, 71 F.3d 77 (2d Cir. 1995).
424
Martin v. City of Indianapolis, 982 F. Supp. 625, 630–31 (S.D. Ind. 1997) (considering VARA claims in response to the
city destroying a large outdoor stainless steel sculpture).
425
Cohen v. G & M Realty L.P. (“5Pointz”), 320 F. Supp. 3d 421 (E.D.N.Y. 2018) (“5Pointz II”) (holding that aerosol artwork
on long-standing walls qualified as works of recognized stature subject to VARA protection).
426
Id.
427
Id. at 439 (referring to the defendants’ expert testimony relying heavily on academic databases and her narrow search
on social media that did not include the films, television, newspaper articles, blogs, online videos, and “social media
buzz” that featured the 5Pointz works).
428
See, e.g., Scott v. Dixon, 309 F. Supp. 2d 395, 400 (E.D.N.Y. 2004) (“[I]t is the artwork that is the subject of the litigation
that must have acquired this stature.”). But see Cohen v. G & M Realty L.P. (“5Pointz), No. 13-CV-5612, 2017 WL
1208416, at *3 (E.D.N.Y. Mar. 31, 2017) (noting a legal basis for focusing on the “recognized stature” of the artist rather
than the work itself).
429
Scott, 309 F. Supp. 2d at 400–01.
430
See Art Law Committee of the New York City Bar Association, Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright
Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 5 (Mar. 27, 2017) (“NY Bar Association Initial Comments”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
79
the statute’s objectives.”
431
Specifically, this commenter maintained that the recognized stature
standard is too narrow, especially in the context of public art (e.g., murals, large-scale sculptures)
where the value of the art is rooted in the community where the art resides.
432
According to this
argument, the less established the artist and less relevant their work is to scholarly research, the
more attention should be given to the community’s opinion and not necessarily the expert’s as “the
preservative aims of the recognized stature provision should not be undercut by an inflexible
dependence on a scholarly consensus of aesthetic importance.”
433
The Copyright Office finds that the recent interpretation of “recognized stature” by the
court in 5Pointz II potentially addresses some of these concerns regarding the exclusion of certain
types of art.
434
Instead of focusing solely on the scholarly merits of the work, the 5Pointz II court
considered the graffiti works at 5Pointz within the appropriate community and context for that
particular medium.
435
Moreover, the Office finds persuasive the assessment that the prevailing
judicial interpretation of “recognized stature” is too narrow. For example, the court’s test for
“recognized stature” in Carter v. Helmsley-Spear, Inc., that the art must be “meritorious,” appears
to contradict the long-standing policy shared by the courts and the Copyright Office to avoid
assessing the aesthetic merits of art.
436
The Carter standard is also susceptible to excluding types
of art that may not qualify as traditional fine art or may not have received sufficient scholarly
attention and analysis. Similarly, the Office also has concerns with the tendency of some courts to
rely solely on scholarly consensus to assess a work’s status. The Office, instead, agrees with the
proposed standard that the courts should also consider the local community’s relationship with
the artwork as a determination of the work’s “recognized stature.” Other factors besides the
aesthetic merits or scholarly treatment may be more indicative of a work’s “recognized stature,”
depending on the type of work at issue and the particular community in which it is present. This
interpretation reflects the justification the House Committee on the Judiciary provided in the
431
Id. at 1.
432
See id. at 5 (“The recognized stature of such a localized work may not be primarily aesthetic in nature at all; the work
may have become iconic for non-aesthetic reasons, or it may reflect the social concerns of the community in a way that
an acknowledged masterpiece may not.”).
433
Id. at 5.
434
The Office recognizes that the precedential value of this opinion is unclear at this early stage, based on the particular
“insolence” of the defendants and whether the recent opinion actually clarifies the statutorily undefined term of
“recognized stature” for other types of art. 5Pointz II, 320 F. Supp. 3d at 447 (“If not for Wolkoll’s insolence, these
damages would not have been assessed.”).
435
See 5Pointz II, 320 F. Supp. 3d at 438–39 (referring to the folios of the plaintiffs highlighting their career
accomplishments and the placement of works in various media).
436
See, e.g., Bleistein, 188 U.S. at 251–52 (“It would be a dangerous undertaking for persons trained only to the law to
constitute themselves final judges of the worth of pictorial illustrations, outside of the narrowest and most obvious
limits.”); Esquire, 591 F.2d at 805 (“Neither the Constitution nor the Copyright Act authorizes the Copyright Office or
the federal judiciary to serve as arbiters of national taste.”); U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, COMPENDIUM OF U.S. COPYRIGHT
OFFICE PRACTICES § 310.2 (3d ed. 2017), available at http://www.copyright.gov/comp3/docs/compendium.pdf.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
80
VARA report for not including the definition of “recognized stature” in the final version of the
bill. According to the report, the House Committee did not intend to require the artist to “prove a
pre-existing standing in the artistic community” as it “appreciate[d] that less well-known or
appreciated artists also have honor and reputations worthy of protection.”
437
The Copyright
Office thus finds that a broader interpretation of “recognized stature” that accounts for the
opinions of those beyond the academic community coincides with congressional intent to extend
VARA protection to a greater range of artistic works.
The Office recommends that Congress consider a statutory amendment to ensure that the
recognized stature provision in section 106A(a)(3)(B) supports the overall goals of VARA of
protecting the moral rights of visual artists and in turn, preserving their contributions to culture.
Consistent with these goals, the standard of recognized stature should reflect that the recognition
of a work of art can originate from outside the “fine arts” academy and instead from the local
community where the art resides. The recent case regarding the graffiti art at 5Pointz highlights
the significance of assessing the recognition of a work of art within the relevant community for
that particular medium.
438
Specifically, the Office recommends adding to subsection 106A(3)(B) the following
language from the California Art Preservation Act, modified to add reference to the opinions of
the relevant community:
437
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 15 (1990). See also id. (“The deletion of this language is consistent with the fact that,
throughout history, many works now universally acknowledged as masterpieces have been rejected and often
misunderstood by the general public at the time they were created.).
438
See, e.g., Peter A. Berry, Graffiti Artists Awarded $6.7 Million for Destruction of 5Pointz Murals in Queens, XXL (Feb. 14,
2018), http://www.xxlmag.com/news/2018/02/graffiti-artists-6-7-million-dollars-destruction-of-5pointz-murals-queens/
(“A group of New York City-based Graffiti artists have just secured a huge W for the culture.”); Alan Feuer, Brooklyn
Jury Finds 5Pointz Developer Illegally Destroyed Graffiti, N.Y. TIMES (Nov. 7, 2017),
http://www.nytimes.com/2017/11/07/nyregion/5pointz-graffiti-jury.html (explaining that the trial “explored the
question of whether graffiti, despite its transient nature, should be recognized as art”); Amanda Holpuch, 5 Pointz: New
York Graffiti Mecca Calls on Banksy for Help in Fight to Stay Alive, GUARDIAN (Oct. 18, 2017) (quoting 5Pointz curator Marie
Cecile Flageul at the start of the case as saying, “Either way, whatever happens, we’ve given talented artists a platform.
We’ve made history.”); Eileen Kinsella, Decrying Real Estate Developer’s ‘Insolence,’ Judge Awards Street Artists $6.7 Million
in Landmark 5Pointz Case, ARTNET NEWS (Feb. 12, 2018), http://news.artnet.com/art-world/judge-awards-6-million-
5pointz-lawsuit-1222394 (quoting 5Pointz attorney Eric Baum as saying,Aerosol art has been recognized as fine art.”);
Lastplak Streetart (@lastplak), TWITTER (Feb. 15, 2018, 12:06 PM), http://twitter.com/lastplak/status/964229447766413314
(Graffiti and street art painters expressing congratulations to the artists in the 5Pointz case for the case outcome); Street
Art NYC, The Institute of Higher Burning, GOOGLE ARTS & CULTURE (2013), http://artsandculture.google.com/exhibit/
wRU6hVET (explaining the importance of 5Pointz in the culture of its neighborhood and the street art community).
But see Cathy Gellis, Court Destroys Future Public Art Installations by Holding Building Owner Liable for Destroying This
One, TECHDIRT (Feb. 22, 2018, 1:47 PM), http://www.techdirt.com/articles/20180219/11142039268/court-destroys-future-
public-art-installations-holding-building-owner-liable-destroying-this-one.shtml (arguing that the case is actually not a
win for graffiti artists as it may force them to change practices with respect to covering over each other’s’ work).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
81
In determining whether a work a work of visual art is of recognized stature, the
trier of fact shall rely on the opinions of artists, art dealers, collectors of fine art,
curators of art museums, and other persons involved with the creation or
marketing of art, as well as the opinion of the relevant community”
439
Such language may enable artists of public art or non-traditional art to show that their particular
work, which may not have qualified under a more academic focus, is of recognized stature within
the particular community related to that specific style of art. With this clarifying language, non-
traditional art and public art may qualify more easily as a work of “recognized stature.”
c) Duration
The rights granted by VARA belong to the author of the work and not the copyright
owner or the owner of the physical art object.
440
For works made after the effective date of VARA
(June 1, 1991), the integrity and attribution rights under VARA endure for the life of the artist.
441
For works created before June 1, 1991, the duration of VARA rights depends upon whether the
artist transferred title to the work. If the artist parted with title prior to June 1, 1991, then the
author does not have any rights under VARA.
442
If the artist created the work before June 1, 1991
but did not transfer title to the work prior to that date, then the artist’s VARA rights endure for a
term of life plus 70 years.
443
This particular provision has created certain inconsistencies regarding duration of
rights.
444
If an artist created a painting in 1985 (for which he did not transfer title before 1991) and
dies in 2005, then the copyright term and the artist’s rights of integrity and attribution for that
painting will last until 2075. However, if the artist created a painting in 1995 and died in 2005,
then the copyright term will last until 2075 but the rights of integrity and attribution would have
lasted for a shorter time, until 2005. The legislative history explains that the term of protection for
both works created before or after the enactment date “is consistent with current copyright terms
for economic rights.”
445
The drafters of VARA may have configured this inconsistent duration
provision in order to render the term for current works coextensive with the term for economic
439
See CAL. CIV. CODE § 987(f).
440
17 U.S.C. § 106A(e)(2).
441
17 U.S.C. § 106A(d)(1).
442
17 U.S.C. § 106A(d)(2). See Roberta Rosenthal Kwall, How Fine Art Fares Post VARA, 1 MARQ. INTELL. PROP. L. REV. 1,
24–26 (1997) (arguing that not applying VARA to previously created works whose titles had been transferred was the
result of Congress’ interest in avoiding frustrating the property interests and expectations of those who had bought
copies of VARA works prior to the effective date of the statute).
443
17 U.S.C. § 106A(d)(2) (stating that “the rights conferred by . . . shall be coextensive with, and shall expire at the same
time as, the rights conferred by section 106”).
444
See 3 NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 8D.06[E].
445
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 18 (1990).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
82
rights at that time, while maintaining for future works that the moral rights under VARA are
personal to the author and thus should endure only for the life of that particular author. It is
unclear to the Office why Congress devised this particular inconsistency in duration that favors
the estates of artists who created works prior to VARA over the estates of artists who created
works since the enactment of VARA. Should Congress decide to take up the substantive VARA
recommendations in this Report, the Office also recommends that it address this apparent
inconsistency by adopting a uniform term.
d) Waiver
As the rights under VARA are personal rights of the artist, the artist may assert the
attribution and integrity rights even after transferring ownership of the copyright or the object.
While these rights are not subject to transfer, the artist may waive these rights in a written
instrument signed by the author. The instrument must identify the work and the uses of that
work to which the waiver applies.
446
The waiver applies only to the particular work and uses
outlined in the instrument. In the case of a joint work prepared by two or more authors, a waiver
of rights made by one author waives such rights for all authors.
447
But one joint author cannot
waive the other joint author’s VARA rights and thereby take sole credit for their joint work.
448
VARA directed the Copyright Office to conduct a study on the waiver of rights provision
and submit a report to Congress on the findings of the study and any recommendations, no later
than five years after the date of enactment.
449
In 1996, the Copyright Office submitted its final
report on the Office’s assessment of the impact of the waiver of moral rights provisions as
outlined in VARA.
450
The Copyright Office concluded that, because artists and art consumers are
generally unaware of moral rights, it could not make an accurate prediction on the impact of
VARA’s waiver provisions at that time.
451
However, the 1996 Report did make a number of
observations on the language and probable effect of VARA on a range of issues. The Office found
that VARA inappropriately permits one joint author to waive the moral rights of coauthors in a
joint work;
452
that VARA should be clarified regarding the specific uses to which waiver might
446
17 U.S.C. § 106A(e)(1).
447
Id.
448
See Grauer v. Deutsch, No. 01 CIV. 8672, 2002 WL 31288937, at *1 (S.D.N.Y. Oct. 11, 2002) (holding that an artist’s
display of copyrighted photographs with a claim of sole authorship did not amount to a waiver of the alleged co-
author’s right of attribution under VARA).
449
See Pub. L. No. 101-650, § 608, 104 Stat. 5128, 5132 (1990).
450
U. S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, WAIVER OF MORAL RIGHTS IN VISUAL ARTWORKS (1996) (“WAIVER REPORT”). The Copyright
Office also submitted to Congress an Interim Report in 1992 that summarized responses to a Notice of Inquiry.
See id. at i.
451
WAIVER REPORT at xiii.
452
WAIVER REPORT at xvii, 192.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
83
apply,
453
especially since waiver language tends to be quite broad;
454
and that the public, artists,
and art purchasers need further education on VARA.
455
The study comments in response to the 2017 Notice of Inquiry addressed familiar issues
highlighted by the Office’s 1996 Report. Some commenters remarked on the general sense of
unfairness of one artist impacting the rights of another, particularly in the context of joint
authorship.
456
Specifically, the Kernochan Center stated that “it is unfair for artists of works of
visual art to be subject to waiver of their rights by a co-author. Any waiver of moral rights should
be effective only with respect to the particular author who signed the waiver.”
457
The Copyright Office finds persuasive the concerns raised in the comments concerning the
ability of one author to waive the rights of another joint author. Such a provision contradicts the
purpose of VARA to protect personal rights and is inconsistent with the statutory prohibition
against the transfer of those rights. As in the 1996 Report, the Copyright Office again
recommends that Congress amend this provision to provide that no joint author may waive
another’s statutory moral rights under VARA without the written consent of each joint author
whose rights would be affected by the waiver.
458
3. Section 1202 of Title 17
Section 1202 of title 17―enacted as part of the DMCA―prohibits the removal, alteration,
or falsification of certain categories of information regarding a copyrighted work.
459
Such
“copyright management information” (“CMI”) is defined in section 1202 to include a work’s title,
author, copyright owner, and terms and conditions of use; performers in non-audiovisual works;
453
WAIVER REPORT at xviii.
454
WAIVER REPORT at 180.
455
WAIVER REPORT at 186.
456
See Kernochan Center Initial Comments at 7; FMC Reply Comments at 6 (“Authors should be able to opt out of their
right of integrity, but not strip other authors of the same right.”).
457
Kernochan Center Initial Comments at 7.
458
See WAIVER REPORT at 192 (“The Office suggests that Congress amend this provision to provide that no joint author
may waive another’s statutory moral rights without the written consent of each joint author whose rights would be
affected.”).
459
This includes information relating to “[t]he title and other information identifying the work,” “[t]he name of, and
other identifying information about, the author of a work,” “[t]he name of, and other identifying information about, the
copyright owner of the work,” “the name of, and other identifying information about, a performer whose performance
is fixed in a work other than an audiovisual work,” “the name of, and other identifying information about, a writer,
performer, or director who is credited in the audiovisual work,” “[t]erms and conditions for use of the work,
“[i]dentifying numbers or symbols referring to such information or links to such information,” and “[s]uch other
information as the Register of Copyrights may prescribe by regulation.” 17 U.S.C. § 1202(c).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
84
and writers, performers, and directors credited in an audiovisual work.
460
To qualify as CMI
under the statute, the information must be “conveyed in connection with” copies or displays of
the work, “including in digital form”; information in a copyright notice can constitute CMI.
461
The Register of Copyrights is authorized to expand section 1202’s CMI definition by regulation.
462
The statute prohibits the attachment of false CMI, as well as the removal or alteration of CMI.
463
Both prohibitions require knowledge and intent in order to constitute a violation.
464
Specifically,
to be liable for providing false CMI or for the distribution or importation for distribution of false
CMI, a person must do so “knowingly and with the intent to induce, enable, facilitate, or conceal
infringement.”
465
Similarly, the removal or alteration of CMI and the distribution of works where
the CMI has been removed or altered violates section 1202 only if done with knowledge that such
action will “induce, enable, facilitate, or conceal” copyright infringement.
466
Congress noted that CMI aids in “indicating attribution, creation and ownership” of a
work, and that CMI plays an important role in “establishing an efficient Internet marketplace” by
tracking and monitoring copyright uses and facilitating licensing agreements.
467
These provisions
460
Id. The categories for performers, writers, and directors do not apply to public performances of works by radio and
television broadcast stations. CMI also includes “other information identifying” all categories as well as identifying
numbers or symbols that refer to such information. Id.
461
Id.
462
17 U.S.C. § 1202(c)(8). At least one commenter recommended that the Office “prescribe by regulation the inclusion of
names of creators―whether or not statutory authors―as CMI that can be protected under section 1202 if conveyed in
connection with copies of the work.” Kernochan Center Initial Comments at 8. Cf. Recording Academy Reply
Comments at 2–3 (suggesting that “[t]he definition of CMI could be expanded in a way that allows for the inclusion of
information about additional individuals involved in the making of a sound recording . . . including the songwriters,
the non-featured performers, and the producers and engineers”). The Copyright Office agrees that this regulatory path
could play an important role in the discussion and use of CMI. The Office may consider its legal authority to initiate
and adopt further regulations at a future date.
463
17 U.S.C. § 1202(a), (b).
464
Section 1202’s knowledge and intent requirements mirror those in the WCT and the WPPT. Both treaties require
member states to “provide adequate and effective legal remedies against any person knowingly performing any of the
following acts knowing, or with respect to civil remedies having reasonable grounds to know, that it will induce,
enable, facilitate or conceal an infringement of any right covered by this Treaty.” WCT art. 12(1); WPPT art. 19(1). The
knowledge conditions ensure that “mere inadvertent acts” are not prohibited. MIHÁLY FISCOR, THE LAW OF COPYRIGHT
AND THE INTERNET: THE 1996 WIPO TREATIES, THEIR INTERPRETATION AND IMPLEMENTATION 564 (2002). Congress enacted
section 1202 to implement the United States’ WCT and WPPT obligations, including the conditions that prohibited
activities are intentional, deliberate, and with the intent to induce, enable, facilitate, or conceal infringement. See S. REP.
NO. 105-190, at 34 (1998); H. REP. NO. 105-551, pt. 1, at 10–11 (1998).
465
17 U.S.C. § 1202(a).
466
17 U.S.C. § 1202(b).
467
S. REP. NO. 105-190, at 16 (1998).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
85
also provide a form of quasi-moral rights protection by effectively preserving the names of
authors, owners, and other creators in connection with their works.
468
The CMI protections in section 1202 implement in U.S. law protections required by in the
WIPO Copyright Treaty (“WCT”) and the WIPO Performances and Phonogram Treaty
(“WPPT”)―collectively known as the “WIPO Internet Treaties”―which created new obligations
concerning protections for what the treaties called “rights management information” or “RMI.”
469
The concept of RMI is one that was “largely unknown beforehand in national and international
law.”
470
RMI, as defined by the WIPO Internet Treaties, includes information that identifies the
work, the author, the owner, and any terms and conditions of the work’s use.
471
Such information
serves the purpose of connecting works to their authors; the WIPO Internet Treaties seek to
protect such connection against manipulation “by unauthorized third persons through deletion,
modification, and otherwise.”
472
As with CMI in the United States, commentators have noted that
the WIPO Internet Treaties’ protection for RMI serves as a potential means of protecting an
author’s moral rights, specifically the right of attribution.
473
While section 1202 defines the kind of information that qualifies as protected CMI, it does
not detail the form that CMI can take. Information that is used to identify works can come in
both analog and digital forms, and often takes the form of metadata. Metadata, literally defined
as “data about data,” is data created, stored, and shared to describe information, which can
include a work’s copyright or attribution information. A variety of organizations and registries
have established a range of techniques to attach identifying information to works and have also
created different types of metadata to embed information. These methods vary based on the
types of works, and authors can voluntarily use these means to connect their information to their
work.
468
See MIRA T. SUNDARA RAJAN, MORAL RIGHTS: PRINCIPLES, PRACTICE AND NEW TECHNOLOGY 27 (2011) (noting that digital
rights management, which identifies a works origin, supports the attribution right. It also “lends indirect support to
the integrity principle, by offering a measure of the authenticity of the source”).
469
The concept of “RMI” as articulated in the WIPO Internet Treaties is coextensive with the concept of “copyright
management information” or “CMI” as codified in section 1202 of the Copyright Act. As used herein, “RMI” refers to
the concept as articulated in the Internet Treaties, while “CMI” will be used when referencing the concept as articulated
in U.S. law.
470
SILKE VON LEWINSKI, INTERNATIONAL COPYRIGHT LAW AND POLICY 17.91, at 462 (2008) (“VON LEWINSKI”). See also
WCT art. 12; WPPT art. 19.
471
WCT art. 12(2); WPPT art. 19(2). While the Internet Treaties do not obligate member states to impose the use of RMI,
they do oblige members to “provide adequate and effective legal remedies against” the unauthorized “knowing”
removal of RMI and the exploitation of works with altered RMI. See WCT art. 12(1); WPPT art. 19(1).
472
VON LEWINSKI 17.99, at 465.
473
See J. Carlos Fernández-Molina & Eduardo Peis, The Moral Rights of Authors in the Age of Digital Information, J. AM.
SOCY FOR INFO. SCI. & TECH. 109, 112 (2001).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
86
a) Section 1202 Protections vis-vis the Right of Attribution
It is common practice in the digital world for CMI to be stripped from works,
disconnecting a work from its authorship and ownership information.
474
Initially, the stripping of
metadata from digital works was largely due to the fact that the narrow bandwidth of dial-up
connections prioritized smaller files with little or no metadata.
475
Abetting this tendency was a
proliferation of software programs aimed at website managers, such as Rainbow Software’s JPG
Cleaner, that promised to increase the speed at which a website could be loaded by stripping
metadata from JPEGs and other files.
476
Since the advent of broadband, with its larger bandwidth,
the barriers to allowing metadata to travel with a file have fallen. Unfortunately, the habits of the
dial-up era die hard, and automatically stripping attribution from works, leaving them un- or
mis-attributed, remains the norm.
477
Additionally, the persistence of metadata can vary greatly
depending upon the type of metadata system and online platform used. In one 2015 study of the
persistence of specific embedded metadata formats on various platforms it was shown that, while
some metadata formats were able to persist on certain social media sites, others were routinely
stripped off, depending upon the site.
478
As new technologies for affixing CMI to works develop,
so too do technological means for altering or removing CMI. Unless a highly sophisticated
method of attaching or embedding CMI is used, digital CMI and metadata can easily be removed
from digital files.
479
After the DMCA’s enactment, American scholars eager for statutory moral rights
protections beyond those provided by VARA saw promise in section 1202. The potential for a
creator to have a cause of action fot the removal or alteration of their identifying information
474
See Maria Schneider, Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at
2–3 (Mar. 19, 2017).
475
See, e.g., Low-Bandwidth Design, KNOWLEDGE MGMT. FOR DEV., http://wiki.km4dev.org/Low-Bandwidth_Design (last
updated Feb. 18, 2012) (advising that to create a website for low-bandwidth quality, strip the metadata from image
files).
476
See JPG Cleaner v2.6, RAINBOW SOFTWARE PROGRAMS, http://www.rainbowsoftware.org/progr ams.html#
JPG%20Cleaner (promising to remove “Texts such as File written by Adobe Photoshop, Creator: PolyView® Version 3.32 by
Polybytes, LEAD Technologies Inc. V1.01”).
477
Cf. Session 4, Symposium Transcript, 8 GEO MASON J. INTL COM. L. at 92 (remarks of Yoko Miyashita, Getty Images)
(explaining the “right-click-copy-upload paradigm,” through which an image is “disconnected from the key
information that tells you who actually created that image”).
478
See Social Media Sites Photo Metadata Test Results, EMBEDDED METADATA MANIFESTO,
http://www.embeddedmetadata.org/ social-media-test-results.php (showing that, while Exif metadata persisted on
Pinterest and Tumblr, IIM and XMP metadata was stripped off on Tumblr, and Exif, IIM, and XMP metadata were
stripped off on Twitter and Flickr).
479
See British Photographic Council, Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Apr. 24, 2015, Notice
of Inquiry (Visual Works Letter) at 1 (July 9, 2015); Pat Thomas, Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright
Offices Apr. 24, 2015, Notice of Inquiry (Visual Works Letter) at 1 (July 9, 2015).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
87
“contain[ed] the seeds of a more general attribution right.”
480
While VARA does provide an
explicit right of attribution, its applicability is “very narrow,”
481
only covering certain visual
works authors.
482
Section 1202, however, is not limited to a specific category of work, therefore
creating “better [attribution] protection[]” for other creators.
483
Some commenters noted that
section 1202’s provisions “are far more robust than those which exist in countries with national
moral rights protections” because violations are subject to actual and statutory damages.
484
Since
section 1202’s enactment in 1998, authors and rightsholders have relied on its benefits when
enforcing their attribution rights in court in increasing numbers every year.
485
Additionally, while
the applicability of the provision to analog as well as digital works was initially questioned, such
applicability is now well-settled. At the same time, the body of case law interpreting section 1202
remains relatively contained; some of those decisions are discussed below.
b) Applicability to Analog as Well as Digital CMI
From an attribution standpoint, authorship information can be attached to a work in both
analog and digital form—from a painter’s hand drawn signature on her mural to a wedding
photographer’s watermark on his photographs. However, early courts reviewing the contours of
480
Jane C. Ginsburg, Have Moral Rights Come of (Digital) Age in the United States?, 19 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 9, 11
(2001) (Ginsburg, (Digital) Age”) (“Inclusion of the authors name in protected copyright management information
suggests that the copyright law finally affords authors of all works, not just ‘works of visual art,’ a right to recognition
of their authorial status.”). See also ROBERTA ROSENTHAL KWA LL , THE SOUL OF CREATIVITY: FORGING A MORAL RIGHTS LAW
FOR THE UNITED STATES 26 (2010) (“KWAL L, SOUL OF CREATIVITY”) (pointing out that section 1202’s CMI provisions
“included a de facto right of attribution”); Eric Schlachter, The Intellectual Property Renaissance in Cyberspace: Why
Copyright Law Could Be Unimportant on the Internet, 12 BERKELEY TECH. L.J. 15, 32 (1997) (noting that a U.S. proposal,
predating the DMCA, to introduce statutory CMI provisions “represent[s] an important step toward the recognition of
the right of attribution in the United States”).
481
Session 2, Symposium Transcript, 8 GEO. MASON J. INTL COM. L. AT 34 (remarks of Mickey Osterreicher, National Press
Photographers Association).
482
VARAs protections apply to authors of works of visual art, as defined by 17 U.S.C. § 101.
483
Session 2, Symposium Transcript, 8 GEO. MASON J. INTL COM. L. at 35 (remarks of Mickey Osterreicher, National Press
Photographers Association).
484
CCIA Initial Comments at 2. Title 17s section 1203 allows actual and statutory damages for section 1202 violations.
See 17 U.S.C. § 1203(c).
485
When Shepardizing “17 U.S.C. 1202” in Lexis, the number of citing cases was 338 through the end of 2018, with the
number of such cases rising each year. See https://advance.lexis.com/shepards/shepardspreviewpod/
?pdmfid=1000516&crid=143007de-6a08-4bb2-96e5-338c578bd5fe&pdshepid=urn%3AcontentItem%3A805F-T9K1-2NSD-
P0CK-00000-00&pdshepcat=initial&ecomp=v311k&prid=f3eb631e-f07e-4e55-862f-48e6455b2157. In 2018 there were 53
cases alleging a violation of section 1202; additionally, many of these cases pair section 1202 claims with traditional
copyright infringement claims. See https://advance.lexis.com/shepards/shepardspreviewpod/
?pdmfid=1000516&crid=ecb6b79f-4cb8-458c-b258-003abd14a11f&pdshepid=urn%3AcontentItem%3A805F-T9K1-2NSD-
P0CK-00000-00&pdshepcat=initial&ecomp=v311k&prid=f3eb631e-f07e-4e55-862f-48e6455b2157.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
88
section 1202 declined to apply it to analog attribution information, instead finding that it only
applied to CMI that was digital or part of an “automated copyright protection or management
system.” For instance, in 2006, the court in IQ Group v. Wiesner Publishing, LLC. was tasked with
deciding whether the defendant’s removal of plaintiff’s logo and hyperlink in an email
advertisement and replacement with information directing users to the defendant’s website was a
violation of section 1202.
486
The court found that there was no violation because the logo and
hyperlink were not considered CMI under section 1202. Acknowledging that the statutory text
appears to define CMI quite broadly,” the court nonetheless determined that the section should
be read narrowly in light of its legislative history.
487
The court understood the section to protect
“copyright management performed by the technological measures of automated systems,” not
“copyright management performed by people.”
488
As such, it held that to be construed as CMI
under section 1202, “the information removed must function as a component of an automated
copyright protection or management system.”
489
Likewise, the court in Textile Secrets International, Inc. v. Ya-Ya Brand Inc. held that a non-
digital copyright notice and a tag indicating ownership on the plaintiff’s fabric design did not
constitute CMI under section 1202.
490
As the IQ Group court did, the court relied on legislative
history to determine that the provision applies to circumstances that are related to “the Internet,
electronic commerce, automated copyright protections or management systems, public registers,
or other technological measures or processes.”
491
Because the plaintiff did not use any
technological process to place the notice or tag on the fabric, and because the defendant did not
use any technological process to remove the information, section 1202 was not triggered.
492
While the IQ Group and Textile Secrets courts’ section 1202 analyses require a technological
or electronic aspect, the more recent judicial trend has been to read the statute more broadly. In
fact, many courts have looked to the provision’s plain language to explicitly reject the
requirement that CMI include a digital or technological component. While the WIPO Internet
486
409 F. Supp. 2d 587, 591 (D.N.J. 2006).
487
IQ Grp. v. Wiesner Publ’g, LLC, 409 F. Supp. 2d 587, 597 (D.N.J. 2006). The court examined the evolution of section
1202 through an analysis of the WIPO Internet Treaties, the U.S. Working Group on Intellectual Property Right’s 1995
“White Paper, and statements given in section 1202’s legislative history. Id. at 593-97.
488
Id. at 597. The court concluded that there was no evidence that plaintiff intended for an automated system to use the
logo or hyperlink to manage copyrights, that the logo or hyperlink actually did manage copyrights, nor that
defendants actions impeded the effective functioning of an automated copyright protection system. Id.
489
Id. at 597.
490
524 F. Supp. 2d 1184, 1202 (C.D. Cal. 2007).
491
Te xtil e S ecret s In t’ l, I nc. v. Ya -Ya Brand Inc., 524 F. Supp. 2d 1184, 1201 (C.D. Cal. 2007).
492
Id. at 1201–02. But see Fox v. Hildebrand, No. CV 09-2085, 2009 WL 1977996, at *3 (C.D. Cal. July 1, 2009) (a more
recent decision from the District Court for the Central District of California, finding “[t]he plain language of the statute
indicates that the DMCA provision at issue is not limited to copyright notices that are digitally placed on a work”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
89
Treaties’ protections specifically extend to “electronic rights management information,”
493
the
language of section 1202 does not so limit its protections. In fact, section 1202’s CMI definition
notes that it applies to the specified information, “including in digital form.”
494
The “including in
digital form” qualifier leads to an understanding that 1202 applies to both digital and non-digital
information.
495
Second, when Congress enacted section 1202, it clarified that although “CMI in
digital form is expressly included” in the provision, “CMI need not be in digital form.”
496
This understanding is reflected in Associated Press v. All Headline News Corp., which
considered whether the removal of authorship and ownership information from news stories
violated section 1202.
497
Addressing the defendant’s reliance on IQ Group, the court noted there
was “no textual support” for limiting the provision to “technological measures of automated
systems” and concluded that section 1202 was not limited to digital information or automated
copyright protection.
498
Similarly, several other courts have criticized the earlier decisions’
reliance on legislative history when the statute’s plain meaning clearly and unambiguously does
not require CMI to “function as a component of an automated copyright protection or
management system.”
499
Courts applying this line of reasoning have interpreted section 1202 to
protect a copyright notice encoded as a hotlink to a photographer’s website, a photographer’s
name and username on the same webpage as his photographs, and an analog credit line on the
back of a record album jacket, among others.
500
The highest court to consider the scope of section
1202’s CMI definition was the Third Circuit in Murphy v. Millennium Radio Group LLC.
501
There,
the defendant scanned the plaintiff’s photograph and cut off the credit identifying the plaintiff as
the author.
502
Once again, the court rejected the defendant’s argument that section 1202 applied
only to automated copyright protection systems, and held that the literal reading of the statute
493
See WCT art. 12(1); WPPT art. 19(1).
494
17 U.S.C. § 1202(c).
495
See Jane C. Ginsburg, Moral Rights in the U.S.: Still in Need of a Guardian Ad Litem, 30 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 73, 75
(2012) (Ginsburg, Guardian Ad Litem”) (“The specification of ‘including in digital form’ clearly means that information
not in digital form is also covered.”).
496
S. REP. NO. 105-190, at 16 (1998).
497
608 F. Supp. 2d 454 (S.D.N.Y. 2009).
498
Associated Press v. All Headline News Corp., 608 F. Supp. 2d 454, 462 (S.D.N.Y. 2009).
499
Cable, 728 F. Supp. 2d at 980.
500
See, e.g., Leveyfilm Inc. v. Fox Sports Interactive Media, 999 F. Supp. 2d 1098, 1102 (N.D. Ill. 2014); Morel, 769 F. Supp. 2d
at 304–05; Cable, 728 F. Supp. 2d at 981.
501
Note that the Third Circuit Court of Appeals encompasses the District Court for the District of New Jersey, which
decided IQ Group.
502
See Murphy v. Millennium Radio Grp. LLC, 650 F.3d. 295, 299 (3d Cir. 2011).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
90
should control.
503
As such, even manual removal of credits that are not digitally embedded in a
work would render a defendant liable under section 1202.
504
c) Challenges Applying Section 1202 to Moral Rights Protections
While section 1202 is increasingly relied upon by litigants trying to protect their
attribution rights, some have pointed to its “limited firepower . . . in the moral rights arsenal.”
505
Although it does establish a cause of action for attachment of false CMI as well as CMI alteration
or removal in some situations, it does not create the right to be credited in the first
place―something that many creators view as a shortcoming.
506
Others have pointed out that
section 1202’s knowledge requirements, as well as its inapplicability to creators who do not own a
copyright in their work, contribute to its weakness.
507
(1) No Right to Be Credited
Section 1202’s protections extend only to CMI that is already attached to a work. They do
not require the inclusion of CMI; in other words, nothing in section 1202 affirmatively requires
that an author be credited. Apprehensive about the prospect of a federal attribution right being
established through mandated CMI, some in the creative industries have voiced concerns about
the burdens such a requirement might create. For example, the Recording Industry Association
of America (“RIAA”) suggested that requiring attribution for sound recordings would have
“significant unintended consequences” to digital platforms.
508
According to the RIAA, platforms
may need to undertake “costly changes” to their user interface and their metadata feeds in order
to provide attribution for the myriad of players involved in creating a sound recording.
509
Streaming services could encounter difficulties collecting attribution information for “the millions
of recordings already in [their] repertoire,” and would have to determine how to provide and
display the information “for every contributor to every sample in every recording in [their]
catalog[s].”
510
503
See id. at 305 (“Defendants are essentially asking us to rewrite § 1202 to insert a term—that is, ‘automated copyright
protection or management system’—which appears nowhere in the text of the DMCA and which lacks a clear
definition. We would need compelling justification indeed to adopt such a statutorily-unmoored interpretation.”).
504
Id. at 304–05.
505
Ginsburg, Guardian Ad Litem, 30 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. at 74.
506
See e.g., Authors Guild Initial Comments at 4; FMC Reply Comments at 7.
507
Authors Guild Initial Comments at 4–5; NWU-SFWA Joint Initial Comments at 6.
508
RIAA Reply Comments at 3.
509
Id. at 4.
510
Id. at 5. Subsequently the RIAA, along with the Artist Rights Alliance, SAG-AFTRA, and A2IM, announced a new
collaboration to build “a more robust and effective system of digital attribution and credits.” Press Release, Recording
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
91
In response, songwriters criticized the apparent prioritization of “the inconvenience of
dealing with accurate metadata over the principle of protection of the rights of the people upon
whose work the music business is built.”
511
Indeed, three streaming services have subsequently
announced intentions to add songwriter, producer, and musician credits as metadata to the songs
they stream.
512
Additionally, Google announced in September of 2018 that it will henceforth
include creator, credit, and copyright notice metadata to the photographs it displays on Google
Images.
513
Of course, none of these initiatives are mandated by section 1202, but once the musical
and photographic metadata is added, section 1202 does protect against its alteration or removal
under certain circumstances. Some in the songwriting community have not advocated for
mandatory CMI, but instead emphasize section 1202’s role as a “useful, if not indispensable,
tool[]” in achieving accountability from the internet.
514
These songwriters argue that the focus
should be on encouraging the full music community to “harness and protect” “[a]ccurate
metadata.”
515
Other creators have noted that the statutory definition of CMI could benefit from
expansion to cover certain types of metadata as well as other creators who are not regularly
credited.
516
While the increase in voluntary provision of metadata for sound recordings and
photographs on major platforms is a positive development, it is not apparent that making such
actions generally mandatory is advisable at this time. Section 1202, along with Chapter 12 in
general, is focused on protecting copyright protection and management systems that are attached
to works voluntarily, and it is a significant step from protecting such systems to requiring their use
Indus. Ass’n of America, Music Community Calls for Building a Better Digital Attribution and Credits System (Mar. 14,
2019), available at https://www.riaa.com/music-community-calls-building-better-digital-attribution-credits-system/.
511
Songwriters Protest ‘Moral Rights’ Issue to RIAA, BRITISH ACAD. SONGWRITERS, COMPOSERS & AUTHORS (Aug. 1, 2017),
http://basca.org.uk/2017/08/16/songwriters-protest-moral-rights-issue-riaa (“Songwriters Protest”).
512
See Press Release, TIDAL, TIDALs Album and Track Info Feature Offers Detailed Artist Credits And Descriptions
For Millions of Albums And Tracks (Nov. 3, 2017), available at http://www.prnewswire.com/news-releases/tidals-album-
and-track-info-feature-offers-detailed-artist-credits-and-descriptions-for-millions-of-albums-and-tracks-300549024.html;
Spotify (Finally) Adds Songwriter and Producer Credits, VARIETY (Feb. 2, 2018), http://variety.com/2018/digital/news/spotify-
adds-songwriter-and-producer-credits-1202684818; Andy Malt, YouTube to Launch Music Streaming Service Next Week,
Adds Credits to Music Videos, COMPLETE MUSIC UPDATE (May 17, 2018),
http://www.completemusicupdate.com/article/youtube-to-launch-music-streaming-service-next-week-adds-credits-to-
music-videos/. But see Marc Hogan, Don’t Give Spotify Too Much Credit for Adding Credits, PITCHFORK (Feb. 5, 2018),
http://pitchfork.com/thepitch/dont-give-spotify-too-much-credit-for-adding-credits.
513
See Paul Sawers, Google Images Will Now Display Creator and Copyright Metadata, VENTUREBEAT (Sept. 27, 2018, 8:21
AM), https://venturebeat.com/2018/09/27/google-images-will-now-display-creator-and-copyright-metadata.
514
Songwriters Protest, http://basca.org.uk/2017/08/16/songwriters-protest-moral-rights-issue-riaa.
515
Id.
516
See FMC Reply Comments at 7 (noting that session musicians and sound engineers are not covered by section 1202);
see also Songwriters Protest, http://basca.org.uk/2017/08/16/songwriters-protest-moral-rights-issue-riaa (recommending
that the categories in the ID3v2 metadata tag be included in the section 1202 definition of CMI).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
92
in the first place. There are also a number of factors that would have to be thought through, such
as the impact on anonymous and pseudonymous works, who would bear the burden of applying
such systems (individual authors? distribution platforms?), and how to effectively police the
requirement.
That said, the 2018 Orrin G. Hatch-Bob Goodlatte Music Modernization Act (“MMA”)
includes many provisions addressing the collection, usage, and sharing of metadata related to
digital music, as part of a broad overhaul of the section 115 mechanical” license. The MMA
creates a blanket license available for digital services engaging in the reproduction and
distribution of digital phonorecord deliveries (“DPDs”), to be administered by a mechanical
licensing collective (MLC”). To facilitate payment to copyright owners for uses made under the
blanket license, the MLC will work to identify musical works embodied in particular sound
recordings, and the copyright owners of such musical works.
517
Further, the MLC will establish
and maintain a publicly available database containing relevant information related to these
musical works, musical work copyright owners, and sound recordings.
518
The MMA details
specific information to be included in the database, and vests the Copyright Office with authority
to prescribe additional categories by regulation.
519
To populate this database, it requires digital
music providers to provide detailed usage reports identifying metadata on the sound recordings
and embodied musical works they stream or download.
520
As part of this process, these providers
must engage in “good-faith, commercially reasonable efforts” to collect a variety of sound
recording information, and the Copyright Office may also promulgate regulations related to the
information included on these usage reports.
521
Separately, musical work copyright owners listed
in the MLC’s database must engage in commercially reasonable efforts to provided updated
sound recording information to improve the database quality.
522
517
17 U.S.C. § 115(d)(3)(C)(III).
518
17 U.S.C. §§ 115(d)(3)(E); 115(d)(3)(C)(IV).
519
17 U.S.C. § 115(d)(3)(E)(III).
520
See 17 U.S.C. § 115(d)(4)(A)(ii)(I)(aa) (requiring digital music providers to provide, as part of their usage reports,
“identifying information for the sound recording, including sound recording name, featured artist, and, to the extent
acquired by the digital music provider in connection with its use of sound recordings of musical works to engage in
covered activities, including pursuant to subparagraph (B), sound recording copyright owner, producer, international
standard recording code, and other information commonly used in the industry to identify sound recordings and
match them to the musical works the sound recordings embody”); see also 17 U.S.C. § 115(d)(4)(A)(ii)(I)(bb) (requiring
digital music providers to “provide information concerning authorship and ownership of the applicable rights in the
musical work embodied in the sound recording (including each songwriter, publisher name, and respective ownership
share) and the international standard musical work code,” “to the extent acquired by the digital music provider in the
metadata provided by sound recording copyright owners or other licensors of sound recordings”).
521
17 U.S.C. § 115(d)(4)(A)(ii); (B).
522
17 U.S.C. 115(d)(3)(E)(IV).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
93
In addition to the attribution aspects of the MMA, the Copyright Office believes it is
important for government to encourage voluntary initiatives that work towards full attribution
for authors on the internet.
(2) Difficult to Prove Knowledge Requirement
Section 1202 neither mandates the inclusion of CMI on works, nor penalizes the mere
removal of attribution information.
523
Instead, the removal, falsification, or alteration of CMI is
only actionable under 1202 if a fairly stringent dual intent standard is satisfied. This standard is
phrased slightly differently depending upon the action. To be liable for providing, distributing,
or importing false CMI, the defendant must know that the CMI is false, and their actions must be
done with the “intent to induce, enable, facilitate, or conceal infringement.”
524
Liability for the
removal or alteration of CMI similarly requires that the actor intentionally remove the
information, or distribute or import works knowing that the CMI has been removed or altered
without the rightsholder’s authorization.
525
However, instead of the “intent” standard for false
CMI, these actions must be done with the knowledge that the removal or alteration will induce,
enable, facilitate, or conceal copyright infringement.
526
The purpose of the dual intent standard is to both fulfill the United States’ international
obligations and provide a safeguard against inadvertent violations. Initially, in 1995, the United
States Government recommended amending the U.S. Copyright Act to protect CMI associated
with a work in order to protect the public from false information and to facilitate licensing
agreements.
527
Its proposal included a knowledge requirement to prevent violations caused by
inadvertent falsifications, alterations, or removals, but notably, it did not contain the requirements
that the action be done with the intent to cause copyright infringement or with the knowledge
that it will facilitate infringement.
528
Preliminary drafts of the WCT and the WPPT’s RMI
provisions were similar to the United States’ proposal in that they only included the single initial
knowledge requirement.
529
During the course of negotiations, parties raised concerns that the
523
See S. REP. NO. 105-190, at 16–17 (1998).
524
17 U.S.C. § 1202(a).
525
17 U.S.C. § 1202(b).
526
Id. With respect to criminal remedies, the requisite standard is “knowledge,” and with respect to civil remedies, the
requisite standard is “reasonable grounds to know.” Id.
527
See BRUCE A. LEHMAN, INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY AND THE NATIONAL INFORMATION INFRASTRUCTURE: THE REPORT ON THE
WORKING GROUP ON INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY RIGHTS 235–36 (1995) (“LEHMAN”).
528
See LEHMAN at 249–50, app. 1 at 6–7. The proposal prohibited the knowing provision, distribution, and importation
of false CMI as well as the knowing removal or alteration of CMI, the knowing distribution or importation of false CMI,
and the knowing distribution or importation of copies with false CMI. Id.
529
See WIPO, Diplomatic Conference on Certain Copyright and Neighboring Rights Questions, Geneva, Dec. 2 to 20,
1996, Basic Proposal for the Substantive Provisions of the Treaty on Certain Questions Concerning the Protection of Literary and
Artistic Works to Be Considered by the Diplomatic Conference, art. 14, at 60, WIPO Doc. CRNR/DC/4 (Aug. 30. 1996),
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
94
early RMI provisions’ scope was too wide and insufficiently defined.
530
They noted that if
violations were not linked to infringing acts then correction of inaccurate information, lawful
activities, activities concerning materials in the public domain, and authorized acts would be
prohibited.
531
Thus, many parties, including the United States, supported narrowing the two
provisions’ scope by attaching liability when the actions are done knowingly and with the
knowledge that they will induce or facilitate copyright infringement,
532
proposals that are
reflected in the final language of the WCT and the WPPT.
While the WIPO Internet Treaties were being negotiated, similar issues were concurrently
being discussed in the U. S. Bills to include a CMI provision in title 17 were introduced before the
WCT and the WPPT were concluded. These initial iterations of section 1202, based on the United
States government’s 1995 recommendation, included the initial knowledge requirement, but the
actor’s intent to cause or facilitate copyright infringement, or knowledge that their actions will do
so was not an element at that time.
533
The U.S. Copyright Office questioned whether this
approach was overly broad.
534
For example, the Office did not think that de minimis alterations,
changes that clarified or supplemented information, authorship and ownership disputes in joint
work or work made for hire situations, or good faith alterations should constitute violations.
535
available at http://www.wipo.int/edocs/mdocs/diplconf/en/crnr_dc/crnr_dc_4.pdf; WIPO, Diplomatic Conference on
Certain Copyright and Neighboring Rights Questions, Geneva, Dec. 2 to 20, 1996, Basic Proposal for the Substantive
Provisions of the Treaty for the Protection of the Rights of Performers and Producers of Phonograms to Be Considered by the
Diplomatic Conference, art. 23, at 96, WIPO Doc. CRNR/DC/5 (Aug. 30, 1996), available at
http://www.wipo.int/edocs/mdocs/diplconf/en/crnr_dc/crnr_dc_5.pdf.
530
See WIPO, Diplomatic Conference on Certain Copyright and Neighboring Rights Questions, Geneva, Dec. 2 to 20,
1996, Summary Minutes, Main Committee I, ¶ 530, at 79, WIPO Doc. CRNR/DC/102, (Aug. 26, 1997), available at
http://www.wipo.int/edocs/mdocs/diplconf/en/crnr_dc/crnr_dc_102.pdf (statement by the European Communities).
531
See id. ¶ 525, at 77–78, ¶ 541, at 81 (statements by the United States of America and the Chairman).
532
See id. ¶ 516, at 75, ¶ 525, at 77–78, ¶ 528, at 78, ¶ 529, at 79, 535, at 80, ¶ 536, at 80 (statements by the Chairman, the
United States of America, Singapore, the European Communities, the United Kingdom, and Australia).
533
See NII Copyright Protection Act of 1995, S. 1284, 104th Cong. § 4 (1995); NII Copyright Protection Act of 1995, H.R.
2441, 104th Cong. § 4 (1995). The proposed section 1202 in both bills mirrored the language in the U.S. government’s
1995 recommendation. The Administration stressed that the knowledge requirement protected against inadvertent
CMI falsification, alteration, and removal. See NII Copyright Protection Act of 1995: Joint Hearing on H.R. 2441 and S. 1284
Before the Subcomm. on Courts and Intellectual Prop. of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary and the S. Comm. on the Judiciary, 104th
Cong. 39 (1995) (“NII Joint Hearing”) (statement of Bruce A. Lehman, Assistant Secretary of Commerce and
Commissioner of Patents and Trademarks, U.S. Patent and Trademark Office).
534
See NII Joint Hearing at 52 (1995) (statement of Marybeth Peters, Register of Copyrights and Associate Librarian for
Copyright Services).
535
Similar concerns were raised by other stakeholders. See NII Joint Hearing at 190 (1996) (written statement of Richard
Robinson, Chairman, President, and CEO, Scholastic, Inc., on behalf of the Association of American Publishers) (raising
concerns over the potential “misapplication” of section 1202 and disputes over ghost writing, collaborative works,
pseudonymous works, as well as legitimate disputes over ownership or the right to exercise one or more exclusive
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
95
After the United States signed the WIPO Internet Treaties, the CMI proposal before Congress was
revised to reflect the knowledge and intent standards found in the treaties.
536
This dual standard
satisfied the United States’ WCT and WPPT obligations and also resolved Office and stakeholder
concerns about section 1202’s breadth.
537
Some view the dual standard as creating “a significant impediment to many CMI claims”
because it can be difficult to prove, thus limiting its usefulness as a means to protect an author’s
attribution rights.
538
Under section 1202, plaintiffs must essentially prove that a defendant was (1)
expressly contemplating copyright infringement when (2) knowingly misattributing a work or
removing CMI.
539
Although a plaintiff is not required to show actual infringement to prove
intent, the fact that there is none may be relevant to some courts’ intent determination.
540
In some cases, plaintiffs have failed to prevail on their section 1202 claims because they
lacked evidence of the defendant’s required mental state.
541
In one recent case, Stevens v.
rights); id. at 432 (written statement of members of the Digital Future Coalition) (noting concerns that the draft
provision’s reach was “overly-broad” and would cause hardship and expense to innocent actors, such as a wholesaler
who receives a shipment of digital copies and knows that the copyright ownership has been transferred, in which case
Digital Future Coalition noted that the wholesaler would be “flatly prohibited” from redistributing the copies unless it
changed the CMI.).
536
See WIPO Copyright Treaties Implementation Act, H.R. 2281, 105th Cong. § 3 (1997) (as introduced in the House, July
29, 1997).
537
See WIPO Copyright Treaties Implementation Act; and Online Copyright Liability Limitation Act: Hearing on H.R. 2281 and
H.R. 2280 Before the Subcomm. on Courts and Intellectual Prop. of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary, 105th Cong. 51–52 (1997)
(“WCT Implementation Hearing) (written statement of Marybeth Peters, Register of Copyrights, Copyright Office of the
United States, Library of Congress) (“We believe that the knowledge and intent standards resolve the concerns we
expressed in 1995 about the prohibition’s scope of coverage. They ensure that no one will be liable who deletes, alters
or provides inaccurate information for legitimate reasons, such as technological constraints or a good faith belief that he
or she has the right to do so.”); id. at 221 (written statement of Michael K. Kirk, Executive Director, American
Intellectual Property Law Association) (pointing out that the addition of an intent requirement along with the
knowledge requirement “adequately addresses the concerns about the possibility of creating liability by innocent
distribution of copies containing false copyright management information”).
538
Jane C. Ginsburg, Keynote Address, The Most Moral of Rights: The Right to be Recognized as the Author of One’s Work, 8
GEO. MASON J. INTL COM. L. 44, 63 (2016). See also Pilch Initial Comments at 3 (“The issue of knowledge, and the
advantage of not having knowledge, is problematic.”).
539
See Greg Lastowka, Digital Attribution: Copyright and the Right to Credit, 87 B.U. L. REV. 41, 73 (2007) (“[T]he burden of
showing a culpable mental state on the part of the defendant is a heavy burden for any plaintiff.).
540
See Steele v. Bongiovi, 784 F. Supp. 2d 94, 98 (D. Mass. 2011) (finding that since an earlier court did not find copyright
infringement, plaintiff “cannot prove that defendants knew the alterations would facilitate copyright infringement
[under section 1202(b)]”).
541
See, e.g., Gordon v. Nextel Commc'ns, 345 F.3d 922, 923, 926-27 (6th Cir. 2003); Ward v. Nat'l Geographic Soc'y, 208 F.
Supp. 2d 429, 450 (S.D.N.Y. 2002); Kelly v. Arriba Soft Corp., 77 F. Supp. 2d 1116, 1122 (C.D. Cal. 1999). But see Michael
Grecco Prods., Inc. v. Alamy, Inc., No. 18-CV-3260, 2019 WL 1129432, at 6 (E.D. N.Y. Mar. 12, 2019) (denying defendants
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
96
CoreLogic, a group of real estate photographers sued a software company for violating section
1202(b).
542
CoreLogic, the software company, provided services to Multiple Listing Services,
including preparing real estate photographs for internet searching.
543
When preparing
photographs, CoreLogic’s software automatically deleted background metadata such as EXIF and
IPTC in order to reduce storage size.
544
The Ninth Circuit, affirming the district court, found that
there was no evidence that CoreLogic possessed the mental state of knowing, or having
reasonable basis to know, that [its] actions will induce, enable, facilitate, or conceal infringement,”
and thus ruled against the photographers.
545
Specifically, the court found that the photographers
failed to prove that CoreLogic demonstrated a “pattern of conduct” or “modus operandi” that
indicated that CoreLogic knew that the result of its actions would be infringement.
546
As part of
this inquiry, the court found it relevant that the photographers had never sought to use their
metadata as a way to police infringement, and that there was never alleged any actual
infringement as a result of CoreLogic’s distribution of the metadata-less photographs.
547
The Office finds the Ninth Circuit’s CoreLogic result troubling. It essentially requires that
not only must a section 1202 plaintiff prove intentional removal and distribution and prove that
this action was done with the knowledge that it will encourage infringement, but also that this
knowledge must be based on a “pattern of conduct” or “modus operandi,” a requirement not
present in the statute. Admittedly, proving that a defendant knows or has reasonable grounds to
know that an action “will
548
cause or facilitate infringement is a relatively high bar. However,
the CoreLogic opinion raises this bar impermissibly high in the Office’s view. As the then-Register
of Copyrights explained in her testimony on the bill for what would become section 1202,
Some copyright owners have expressed concern that this standard will be too
difficult to meet, requiring proof of an ultimate infringement in order to find a
violation. The Copyright Office believes that it is important to make clear,
possibly in legislative history, the reference to infringement does not mean that
motion to dismiss 1202(a) claim on grounds that plaintiffs allegations that “[d]efendant placed watermarks on the
Copyrighted Works in order to facilitate its continued marketing and sale of licenses” are sufficient to survive a motion
to dismiss); Batra v. PopSugar, Inc., No. 18-cv-03752, 2019 WL 482492, at *2 (C.D. Cal. Feb. 7, 2019) (denying defendants
motion to dismiss 1202(b) claim on grounds that there is a “plausible inference” that the removal of Instagram sidebars
containing identifying information was done “knowing that removing the CMI would help to conceal the alleged
infringement”).
542
899 F.3d 666 (9th Cir. 2018), cert denied, 586 U.S. __ (U.S. Feb. 19, 2019) (No. 18-878).
543
Id. at 670–71.
544
Id. at 671.
545
Id. at 673.
546
Id. at 675.
547
Id. at 676.
548
17 U.S.C. § 1202(b).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
97
the actor must have intended to further any particular act of infringement—just
to make infringement generally possible or easier to accomplish.
549
Note that CoreLogic appears to require more than general knowledge that infringement
will be “easier to accomplish.”
The specific issues with the CoreLogic opinion aside, many creators are frustrated that even
the intentional falsification and removal of CMI is not unlawful if they cannot prove that the
actions were either intended to encourage copyright infringement or done with the knowledge
that they would do so. Because stripping CMI is a regular occurrence, especially over social
media,
550
“it is nearly impossible to prove the intent of an individual social media user.”
551
Meeting the knowledge and intent thresholds can also be especially difficult for individual
authors who do not have the resources to engage in lengthy litigation.
552
As such, several creators
groups advocate removing or revising section 1202’s knowledge and intent requirements.
553
While the Office is very sympathetic to these legitimate concerns, section 1202’s dual
intent standard is necessary, at least in the criminal context, to ensure that innocent actors are not
swept up by the provisions of section 1202. The addition of the second intent standard found in
the current statutory language, regarding infringement, alleviated concerns that knowingly
altering CMI for innocent or good faith purposes—such as the use of a pseudonym or a ghost
writer or updating information for a change in ownership—would not lead to civil or criminal
penalties. Accordingly, the Office does not recommend any change to section 1202.
At the same time, the Office agrees that the dual intent standard raises a high bar and
excludes a large amount of misconduct that should at least raise the potential of civil liability.
Therefore, the Office recommends that Congress consider a new section 1202A that would
address the difficulty creators face when trying to use section 1202 to protect their attribution
549
WCT Implementation Hearing at 51 (written statement of Marybeth Peters, Register of Copyrights, Copyright Office of
the United States, Library of Congress).
550
This is of particular concern for photographers and other visual artists. See Copyright Alliance, Comments
Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Apr. 24, 2015, Notice of Inquiry (Visual Works Letter) at 2 (“Visual
works are more easily infringed online than any other type of work, due to the ease in which images may be uploaded
or downloaded, the ubiquity of services that automatically strip out metadata, and the availability of right-click copy
and save functionality.).
551
ARS Initial Comments at 3.
552
See Authors Guild Initial Comments at 4.
553
See ARS Initial Comments at 3; A2IM Reply Comments at 6; BMI Reply Comments at 3; CVA Initial Comments at 14;
NMPA Reply Comment at 9. But see OTW Initial Comments at 9 ([Section 1202] must remain tightly linked to the
deliberate enablement of infringement. . . . Congress should leave well enough alone.”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
98
rights―namely the requirement of intent to encourage infringement or knowledge that one’s
actions will induce infringement.
554
The Office recommends that Congress consider an addition to section 1202 that, while
retaining a dual standard, would loosen it slightly to focus on intent to conceal rather than to
infringe. Our proposed new section 1202A states that the knowing removal or alteration of any
copyright management information would be actionable only if it was done with the intent to
conceal the author’s attribution information. This would alleviate the burden on creators’ ability
to effectively use section 1202 when their identifying information has been altered or removed,
while still providing safeguards for those who remove or alter CMI for innocent or good faith
purposes. Another safeguard provided is the omission of any criminal penalty. The new
provision would retain a dual intent standard, but a plaintiff would no longer be required to
prove that the actions were meant to encourage copyright infringement, or indeed relate to it in
any way. Instead, 1202A would be much more narrowly tailored to address attribution rights.
Based on the Office’s proposal, section 1202A would read as follows:
§ 1202A Integrity of copyright management information for attribution
rights
(a) REMOVAL OR ALTERATION OF COPYRIGHT MANAGEMENT INFORMATION. –
No person shall, without the authority of the author or the law,
knowingly remove or alter any copyright management information with
the intent to conceal the individual author’s attribution information.
(b) DEFINITIONS.
(1) As used in this section, the term “copyright management
information” has the same meaning as used in section 1202(c).
(2) As used in this section, the term “attribution information”
means the name of, and other identifying information about, the
author of a work.
Technical amendments to section 1202 would read as follows:
§ 1203 Civil remedies
(a) CIVIL ACTIONS. Any person injured by a violation of section 1201, 1202, or 1202A
may bring a civil action in an appropriate United States district court for such
violation.
(b) . . .
554
See supra CoreLogic discussion.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
99
(c) AWA R D O F DAMAGES. Except as otherwise provided in this title, a person
committing a violation of section 1201, 1202, or 1202A is liable for either –
Under the Office’s proposal, the following actions could be liable under proposed section
1202A: intentionally stripping authorship metadata from a digital photograph and attaching new
metadata for someone who was not the creator; removing the title page of a printed book and
replacing it with another title page that falsely names someone else as the author; or removing a
painter’s signature from his painting, making copies available for sale, and advertising that the
painting was created by someone else. Such offenses are potentially unavailable or too difficult to
prove under the current statute. Because this proposal retains an intent standard it does not
address automatic stripping of attribution information, unless it can be proven that the automatic
system at issue was designed with the intent to conceal the author’s identity. While a court
would still have to determine if proposed section 1202A’s dual intent standard is met, the focus
on intent to conceal attribution information rather than section 1202’s intent to promote
infringement is more closely tied to protecting a creator’s moral right of attribution.
(3) Difficulties for Non-Rightsholder Authors
Under U.S. copyright law, the default rule is that the copyright initially belongs to the
author who created (or is treated by law as having created) the work. Nonetheless, there are
situations where the creator and copyright owner may not be the same, which has implications
for the author/creator’s ability to object to the removal or alteration of CMI identifying him or her.
For example, authors may transfer their ownership rights in their creations.
555
In this situation,
removal or alteration of the CMI cannot be done without the consent of the transferee, as the
copyright owner, but the author of the work does not retain the right to object to such removal or
alteration. Similarly, in a work-made-for-hire situation, the employer (or commissioner in limited
circumstances) is considered to be both the author and the copyright owner, even though an
employee (or person commissioned) actually created the work. The employer is thus the only
entity entitled either to be credited as the author or to object to the removal or alteration of CMI.
556
Some scholars have pointed out that section 1202 is more concerned with the economic interests
of those who exploit a work (e.g., the rightsholder or work-made-for-hire employer) rather than
the personality rights of the creator.
557
Under this view, there is no remedy for an author whose
attribution CMI has been altered or removed; instead, a violation is “dependent on the economic
rights of infringement that will follow from the omission of the author’s name.”
558
This is borne
out by section 1202, which requires authority from “the copyright owner or the law” for removal
555
See 17 U.S.C. § 201(d).
556
See 17 U.S.C. § 101, 201(b). In certain specific situations, commissioned works are also considered works made for
hire. See 17 U.S.C. § 101.
557
See KWA LL , SOUL OF CREATIVITY at 26; Severine Dusollier, Some Reflections on Copyright Management Information and
Moral Rights, 25 COLUM. J.L. & ARTS, 377, 397 (2001); Ginsburg, (Digital) Age, 19 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. at 13.
558
Dusollier, 25 COLUM. J.L. & ARTS at 397.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
100
or alteration of CMI, and does not mention the rights of the author.
559
Since a non-rightsholder
creator has no economic tie to the work, the ability for them to independently prove a section
1202 violation is difficult, if not impossible.
560
The Office’s proposal for a new section 1202A would, if implemented, go some distance to
ameliorating this situation, in that it gives authority to “the author or the law” and not to the
copyright owner. Thus, under this proposed section, an author who has granted her rights to
another party would retain the ability to bring an action against someone who intentionally
removed her CMI with the intent to conceal her authorship of the work in question. Because this
proposed section is focused on attribution interests, it makes sense that it gives authority to the
party who is most harmed by non-attribution or false attribution—the author herself.
4. Other Title 17 Provisions
When Congress determined that there was “a composite of laws in this country that
provides the kind of protection envisioned by Article 6bis,”
561
it identified a number of legal
routes by which an aggrieved author-plaintiff could pursue a moral rights claim under federal,
local, and state law. Existing provisions in the Copyright Act were cited as part of the
framework, including protection of an author’s exclusive rights in derivatives of his or her works,
limits on a mechanical licensee’s rights to arrange an author’s musical composition, and
termination of transfers and licenses.
562
a) Derivative Works Section 106(2)
The U.S. Copyright Act grants authors six exclusive rights, one being the section 106(2)
right to prepare and to authorize the preparation of “derivative works based upon the
copyrighted work.”
563
The Act defines a “derivative work” as one “based upon one or more
preexisting works” in which the original is “recast, transformed, or adapted.”
564
An author (who
559
17 U.S.C. § 1202(b).
560
See ASJA Initial Comments at 5 (“[T]he [section 1202] attribution of rights is tied to who owns or is licensed to use a
particular work. . . ; the moral rights of an author are not tied to money and do not begin or end with a contract.”);
NWU-SFWA Joint Initial Comments at 6 (“Section 1202 . . . fails to recognize any right which is independent of
economic rights or which survives a transfer or assignment of those rights.”). Some music industry stakeholders have
also complained that section 1202(c)’s CMI definition is too narrow because it only identifies the performers
information as CMI for phonorecords and sound recordings. The definition does not take into account songwriters,
non-featured performers, producers, engineers, and session musicians. See FMC Reply Comments at 7; Recording
Academy Reply Comments at 2–3.
561
H.R. REP. NO. 100-609, at 34 (1988).
562
See id. at 34, 37–38; S. REP. NO. 100-352, at 9–10 (1988); see also 17 U.S.C. §§ 106(2), 115(a)(2), 203.
563
17 U.S.C. § 106(2).
564
17 U.S.C. § 101. The “derivative works” definition includes, but is not limited to, translations, musical arrangements,
dramatizations, fictionalizations, motion picture versions, sound recordings, art reproductions, abridgments, and
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
101
is also an owner)
565
can therefore enforce their integrity interests by bringing an infringement
action under section 106(2) against a party making modifications to their work that results in the
creation of an unauthorized derivative work.
566
In fact, the unauthorized derivative work does
not even have to be prejudicial to the author’s honor or reputation to be infringing.
567
On the
other hand, a work that is prejudicial in this way, but that does not meet the derivative work
standard of being “recast, transformed, or adapted” (for example, exhibiting the original work
with other works that negatively comment on it), will likely not be considered a “derivative
work” at all, and thus there will be no finding of infringement.
568
Additionally, where the author has authorized the creation of a derivative work (e.g., a
film adaptation), but the creator of the derivative work makes changes to which the author objects
and that violate the terms of the license, the author may bring suit either under a breach of
contract or a copyright infringement claim.
569
If a party violates the express terms of contract, the
other party can usually bring a breach of contract action. The factor determining whether a
violation of a license to create a derivative work may also constitute copyright infringement is if
the violation is related to the licensor’s exclusive rights.
570
Thus, in a licensed derivative work
context, the right of integrity is only enforceable under copyright to the extent it overlaps with the
economic derivative work right.
condensations. Id. The degree to which the new work must be altered to qualify as a derivative work, and thus trigger
a claim of infringement by the author or owner of the original work, is somewhat unclear. Compare Mirage Editions, Inc.
v. Albuquerque A.R.T. Co., 856 F.2d 1341 (9th Cir. 1988) (holding that cutting out illustrations from an art monograph and
mounting them on tiles for retail sale infringes the derivative works right), with Lee v. A.R.T. Co., 125 F.3d 580, 582 (7th
Cir. 1997) (holding that taking notecards and mounting them on tiles for retail sale does not infringe the derivative
works right because the works were not actually “recast, transformed, or adapted”).
565
Of course, integrity rights are personal to authors, but the derivative works right is not, and, as is demonstrated
below, see infra notes 572–578 and accompanying text, corporate actors do attempt to enforce what some consider moral
rights through derivative works actions.
566
See AD HOC WORKING GRP., in 10 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS at 554.
567
See id. at 554 (pointing out that commenters have noted that “unauthorized ‘distortion, mutilation or other
modifications’ would be actionable as infringements [under section 106(2)]—whether or not prejudicial to the author’s
honor or reputation”).
568
See A.R.T. Co., 125 F.3d at 582–83; see also id. at 582 (“If [the mounting of notecards on tiles] counts as a derivative
work infringement, then the United States has established through the back door an extraordinarily broad version of
authors moral rights, under which artists may black any modification of their works of which they disapprove. No
European version of droit moral goes this far.”).
569
See generally 3 NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 10.15[A][1]–[2] (Remedies Arising Out of Violation of the Instrument of
Transfer).
570
See MDY Indus., LLC v. Blizzard Entm’t, Inc., 629 F.3d 928, 940 (9th Cir. 2010) (“To recover for copyright infringement
based on breach of a license agreement, (1) the copying must exceed the scope of the defendant’s license and (2) the
copyright owners complaint must be grounded in an exclusive right of copyright . . . .”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
102
Section 106(2) has regularly been cited as providing a right of integrity for copyright
owners.
571
For example, some highly publicized court cases have been described as seeking
damages for infringements of economic rights as a “backdoor” way of enforcing otherwise
unenforceable moral rights.
572
One commentator views the infringement cases Dr. Seuss
Enterprises v. Penguin Books USA, Inc. (seeking to enjoin the book The Cat NOT in the Hat, a
satirically-inclined retelling of the O.J. Simpson trial in the style of the Dr. Seuss children’s
books)
573
and Suntrust Bank v. Houghton Mifflin Co. (objecting to the book The Wind Done Gone, a
radical retelling of Gone with the Wind)
574
as essentially attempts to protect the integrity of the Dr.
Seuss image and the reputation of Gone with the Wind, brought to court in the guise of suits
alleging infringement of the derivative works right.
575
While both cases were brought by estates,
and not the authors themselves, they do illustrate how moral rights writ large may be protected
using the derivative work right.
576
These two cases also illustrate the interaction between moral
rights/derivative works claims and fair use: The court in Dr. Seuss Enterprises found that there
was no fair use and thus upheld the lower court’s preliminary injunction against the defendant’s
571
See 1987 BCIA Hearings at 230, 233 (statement of Peter Nolan, Vice President-Counsel, Walt Disney Productions, on
behalf of the Motion Picture Association of America); Authors Guild Initial Comments at 2; OTW Initial Comments at 1.
572
Erin E. Gallagher, Note, On the Fair Use Fence Between Derivative Works and Allegedly Infringing Creations: A Proposal for
a Middle Ground, 80 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 759, 771 (2005).
573
109 F.3d 1394 (9th Cir. 1997).
574
268 F.3d 1257 (11th Cir. 2001).
575
See Gallagher, 80 NOTRE DAME L. REV. at 772–73 (“Some sort of an integrity-like claim is involved when a marketer of
wholesome family entertainment like Dr. Seuss Enterprises wishes to protect the integrity of that image by suppressing
an adaptation of one of its identifying elements to lightheartedly portray a murder trial. Likewise, a desire to protect
the image of the characters and story associated with the novel Gone with the Wind causes the copyright holders to
dislike a new work that casts that story and those characters in a negative light.”).
576
See also Deidre A. Keller, Recognizing the Derivative Works Right as a Moral Right: A Case Comparison and Proposal, 63
CASE W. RES. L. REV. 511, 515 (2012) (arguing that The Wind Done Gone case as well as the litigation against a purported
sequel to The Catcher in the RyeSalinger v. Colting, 641 F. Supp. 2d 250 (S.D.N.Y. 2009)—sought to “enforce [moral
rights] in the guise of enforcing the derivative works right”). A more recent example of a plaintiff seeking to enforce
what appears to be a right of integrity through a derivative works suit is that of the creator of Pepe the Frog against
those who have repurposed his character to advance hate speech. See Complaint for Copyright Infringement &
Demand for Jury Trial, Furie v. Infowars, LLC, No. 18-cv-1830 (C.D. Cal. filed Mar. 5, 2018); see also Matthew Gault, Pepe
the Frog’s Creator Goes Legally Nuclear Against the Alt-Right, MOTHERBOARD (Sept. 18, 2017, 1:43 PM),
https://motherboard.vice.com/en_us/article/8x8gaa/pepe-the-frogs-creator-lawsuits-dmca-matt-furie-alt-right.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
103
book as an unauthorized derivative work.
577
However, the Suntrust Bank court found that The
Wind Done Gone qualified as a parody, and thus upheld the fair use defense.
578
Some have been more skeptical of the scope of the derivative work right’s protections vis-
à-vis moral rights, pointing out that it “implies a right against distortion, [but only] to a
degree.
579
Critics also note that determining what exactly constitutes an adaptation can be
difficult. For example, if a new work distorts an existing work “so outrageously” that only the
original (uncopyrightable) ideas are detectable, then section 106(2) has not been triggered because
the original expression was not appropriated.
580
Furthermore, derivative work rights have been
cited as being “essentially economic rights designed to regulate adaptations or arrangements,”
581
making the comparison to Berne 6bis one of “apples to oranges.”
582
However, it is well
understood that membership in the Berne Convention gives each nation the flexibility to
implement the Berne provisions as appropriate for their national law. This includes, in the
instance of the United States, the ability to merge economic rights with moral rights, as with the
derivative work right.
583
Section 106(2) remains an important piece of the United States’ moral
rights patchwork.
b) Compulsory Licenses for Nondramatic Musical Works Section 115(a)(2)
The compulsory licensing provision in section 115(a)(2) of the Copyright Act limits
rearrangement—and thus prohibits a certain level of distortionof non-dramatic musical
compositions.
584
Once a copyright owner has authorized the initial distribution of a non-dramatic
577
Dr. Seuss Enters., L.P. v. Penguin Books USA, Inc., 109 F.3d 1394, 1403 (9th Cir. 1997).
578
Suntrust Bank v. Houghton Mifflin Co., 268 F.3d 1257, 1270–71 (11th Cir. 2001); accord Dr. Seuss Enters, L.P. v. ComicMix
LLC, No. 16-CV-2779, 2019 WL 1323596, at 9, 17 (S.D. Cal. Mar. 12, 2019) (finding that even if a work using elements of
Dr. Seuss’s Oh, the Places You’ll Go! was a derivative work, it could also be “highly transformative,” and thus a fair use).
579
1987 BCIA Hearings at 681 (statement of Paul Goldstein, Professor of Law, Stanford University).
580
See id.; cf. Session 2, Symposium Transcript, 8 GEO. MASON J. INTL COM. L. at 42 (remarks of Allan Adler, Association of
American Publishers) (“[T]here’s always going to be some question of what actually is derivative. . . . [A] work can
steal completely the ideas of a prior authors work but not of course be actionable as copyright infringement because it
doesn’t take the original expression.”).
581
1987 BCIA Hearings at 1257–58 (1987–88) (written statement of Arnold P. Lutzker, Attorney, Dow, Lohnes &
Albertson).
582
Edward J. Damich, Moral Rights in the United States and Article 6bis of the Berne Convention: A Comment on the
Preliminary Report of the Ad Hoc Working Group on U.S. Adherence to the Berne Convention, 10 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS 655,
659 (1986) (“Damich, Moral Rights”).
583
See, e.g., Berne Convention Rome Text art 36(1) (Any country party to this Convention undertakes to adopt, in
accordance with its constitution, the measures necessary to ensure the application of this Convention.”).
584
See H.R. REP. NO. 100-609, at 34, 37–38 (1988); see also U.S. Adherence to the Berne Convention: Hearings on the
Implications, Both Domestic and International, of U.S. Adherence to the International Union for the Protection of Literary and
Artistic Works Before the Subcomm. on Patents, Copyrights and Trademarks of the S. Comm. on the Judiciary, 99th Cong. 685–86
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
104
musical composition in the United States, anyone can obtain a compulsory license under section
115 to make and distribute phonorecords, including in digital form, of the work.
585
These are
commonly known as cover versions. Under section 115(a)(2), any musical arrangement made as
part of the cover version can only change the original work to the degree necessary to conform to
the style or manner of interpretation of the new arrangement.
586
But the new arrangement must
“not change the basic melody or fundamental character of the [original] work, and shall not be
subject to protection as a derivative work.
587
A licensee’s ability to make more drastic changes or
to claim a derivative work copyright require the owner’s “express consent,”
588
thus protecting the
composer’s interests in the integrity of the original musical work.
When it enacted section 115 in the 1976 Copyright Act, Congress recognized the
importance of allowing a compulsory license for arrangements “without allowing the music to be
perverted, distorted, or travestied.”
589
While some have identified section 115(a)(2) as the “sole
explicit recognition of moral rights in the entire Copyright Act” prior to VARA,
590
its ability to
provide protection for moral rights has not been defined in judicial decisions. Instead, dicta in
various decisions focused on the relationship between the compulsory license and the owner’s
exclusive right to make derivative works under section 106(2), to the effect that derivative works
were said to fall outside the realm of section 115.
591
In a 2006 memorandum opinion, the Copyright Office did consider the parameters of
section 115(a)(2), noting that defining these parameters was “difficult because there is no
(1985–86) (“1985 Berne Convention Hearings”) (written statement of the Recording Industry Association of America);
Kernochan Center Initial Comments at 2 n.2; Lucille M. Ponte, Preserving Creativity from Endless Digital Exploitation: Has
the Time Come for the New Concept of Copyright Dilution?, 15 B.U. J. SCI. & TECH. L. 34, 63–65 (2009) (submitted as a
comment to this study).
585
See 17 U.S.C. § 115(a)(1). The compulsory license is only available for the distribution of phonorecords to the public
for private use. See id.
586
See 17 U.S.C. § 115(a)(2).
587
17 U.S.C. § 115(a)(2).
588
17 U.S.C. § 115(a)(2).
589
H.R. REP. NO. 94-1476, at 109 (1976).
590
3 NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 8.04[F]. See also AD HOC WORKING GRP., in 10 COLUM.-VLA J.L. & ARTS at 544-45 (stating
that section 115 “contains an explicit recognition of the more important more rights”).
591
See Campbell, 510 U.S. at 574 n.4 (noting that the defendant, who parodied plaintiffs song, “concede[d] that it is not
entitled to a compulsory license under § 115 because its arrangement changes ‘the basic melody or fundamental
character of the original”); Palladium Music, Inc. v. EatSleepMusic, Inc., 398 F.3d 1193, 1199 n.9 (10th Cir. 2005) (noting
that although the Copyright Act permits compulsory licenses, section 115(a)(2) makes clear that the copyright owner
retains the right to create derivative works); TeeVee Toons, Inc. v. DM Records, Inc., No. 05 Civ. 5602, 2007 WL 2851218, at
*8 (S.D.N.Y. Sept. 27, 2007) (stating that the ability to make derivative works is excluded from the section 115
mechanical license ).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
105
precedent.”
592
Upon referral from the Copyright Royalty Board, the Register of Copyrights was
asked to resolve whether ringtones were subject to section 115.
593
The Offices discussion of
whether a ringtone changed the “fundamental character” of the underlying work focused on a
derivative works analysis.
594
Although the analysis was specific to ringtones, the Office
concluded that because the statute “meant to avoid the desecration of the underlying musical
work,” ringtones containing additional material could be considered derivative works outside of
section 115’s scope.
595
The brief judicial references and the Office’s 2006 memorandum opinion reinforce the
relationship between the section 115 license and the owner’s exclusive right to make derivative
works under section 106(2). The provisions work together to assist owners in protecting the
integrity of their works. Section 115(a)(2) gives the owner control over how his or her work is
used. But if a new arrangement is too dramatically altered to be eligible for the license, then it
may be considered an unauthorized derivative work, enabling the owner to enforce his or her
exclusive derivative works right—also an element in the U.S. moral rights system.
While section 115(a)(2) is an important part of the moral rights patchwork, critics note that
its limited applicability “as to subject matter (nondramatic musical works) and to circumstances
(compulsory licenses for phonorecords)” confines its usefulness as a broad moral right.
596
c) Termination of Transfers Section 203
The Copyright Act, while granting authors initial ownership in works they have created,
also allows them to transfer their exclusive ownership rights in whole or in part.
597
Termination
rights act as a “safety valve[],” providing authors a means to “regain control and integrity over
their artwork.”
598
Section 203 provides that, under certain circumstances, an author who transferred their
rights on or after January 1, 1978, has an opportunity to terminate the grant of those rights and
592
Mechanical and Digital Phonorecord Delivery Rate Adjustment Proceeding: Final Order, 71 Fed. Reg. 64,303, 64,313
(Nov. 1, 2006).
593
See id.
594
See id. at 64,314–15.
595
Id. at 64,315. The Office also found that ringtones that are excerpts of preexisting sound recordings do fall within the
scope of section 115. See id. at 64,307.
596
Damich, Moral Rights, 10 COLUM.-VLA & ARTS at 659.
597
See 17 U.S.C. §§ 201(a), (d).
598
SAG-AFTRA Initial Comments at 6–7.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
106
reclaim ownership.
599
Authors can terminate transfers during a five-year termination period that
begins thirty-five years after the execution of the grant.
600
Like the moral rights provided for in
Berne article 6bis, termination rights cannot be assigned or waived, leading one scholar to refer to
them as “effectively the U.S. corollary to moral rights.”
601
When enacting the 1976 Copyright Act, Congress noted that the termination provisions of
section 203 served an equitable function by allowing authors, who may assign rights earlier in
their career when they are in an inferior bargaining position, or their heirs, a second opportunity
to share in the economic success of their works.
602
At the time of Berne’s implementation,
commentators pointed out that section 203 “may serve as a vehicle for [moral rights] protection”
by allowing an author to regain control of a transferred work.
603
Likewise, courts have stressed
that the goal of the provision “is to help authors, not publishers or broadcasters of others who
benefit from the work of authors.”
604
For example, an author may rely on section 203 to reclaim
the ability to authorize derivative works, thus preventing any future low quality reproductions.
605
599
See 17 U.S.C. § 203(a). Specifically, the transfer instrument must have been “executed” after January 1, 1978. There is
a separate provision—section 304(c)—that provides similar termination rights to authors of works in either their first or
renewal term prior to 1978, where the transfer was executed prior to 1978. See 17 U.S.C. § 304(c).
600
See 17 U.S.C. § 203(a)(3). However, if the grant conveyed the right of publication, the termination period begins
35 years after the date that the grant was executed or 40 years after the date that the work was published, whichever is
earlier. Id. The U.S. Copyright Office provides a series of tables so authors can measure the termination period of a
grant depending on several factors. U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, Notices of Termination, https://www.copyright.gov/
recordation/termination.html.
601
Michael H. Davis, The Screenwriter’s Indestructible Right to Terminate Her Assignment of Copyright: Once a Story is
“Pitched,” A Studio Can Never Obtain All Copyrights in the Story, 18 CARDOZO ARTS & ENT. L.J. 93, 106–07 (2000). See also id.
(noting that moral rights are defined by their nature as non-economic rights and their inability to be transferred, and
that termination is the one right in the United States that an author cannot assign or waive); 17 U.S.C. § 203(a)(5)
(“Termination of the grant may be effected notwithstanding any agreement to the contrary, including an agreement to
make a will or to make any future grant.”).
602
See H.R. REP. NO. 94-1476, at 124 (1976) (“[S]ection 203 safeguard[s] authors against unremunerative transfers. A
provision of this sort is needed because of the unequal bargaining position of authors, resulting in part from the
impossibility of determining a work’s value until it has been exploited.”).
603
Edward J. Damich, The Right of Personality: A Common-Law Basis for the Protection of the Moral Rights of Authors, 23 GA.
L. REV. 1, 44 (1988) (“Damich, Right of Personality”). See also 1987 BCIA Hearings at 264 (written statement of Kenneth W.
Dam, Vice President, International Business Machines); 1985 Berne Convention Hearings at 169–70 (written statement of
John M. Kernochan, Nash Professor of Law, Columbia University School of Law).
604
Korman v. HBC Fla., Inc., 182 F.3d 1291, 1296 (11th Cir. 1999). Cf. Mills Music, Inc. v. Snyder, 469 U.S. 153, 172 (1985)
(citing section 203’s legislative history to show that termination rights were “obviously intended to make the rewards
for the creativity of authors more substantial”).
605
See Damich, Right of Personality, 23 GA. L. REV. at 44. However, note that derivative works prepared while a legal
transfer is in effect may continue to be exploited after the termination of that transfer. See 17 U.S.C. § 203(b)(1).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
107
Authors who transferred their rights in 1978 became eligible to reclaim their copyrights
under section 203 on January 1, 2013. In the first high profile case to rely on the provision, one of
the Village People’s lead singers, Victor Willis, won the right to regain control of several songs he
had co-written, including “Y.M.C.A.”
606
Although the court’s discussion did not reference moral
rights, the court reiterated section 203’s importance to remedying an author’s unequal bargaining
power when making an initial transfer of ownership.
607
Willis also stressed that termination
rights provide an avenue for artists to regain control over “works that a lot of us gave away when
we were younger, before we knew what was going on.”
608
B. State Law
In addition to the federal protections outlined above, Congress also identified protections
for moral rights provided by state laws during passage of the BCIA, including state common law
principles and state statutory schemes that proved protections for the rights of attribution and
integrity.
609
While state laws have an important role in protecting authors’ moral rights under the
United States’ system of federalism, reliance on state laws continues to suffer from many of the
same defects noted by commenters at the time of the BCIA’s passage—the lack of clear, uniform
standards that are consistent throughout the country.
610
1. Defamation
The first state law identified by Congress to protect the moral rights of authors is the
common law tort of defamation.
611
Defamation provides redress for certain false statements or
assertions―either written (libel) or spoken (slander)―that harm a person’s reputation.
612
Prior to
606
See Scorpio Music S.A. v. Willis, No. 11cv1557, 2012 WL 1598043, at *5 (S.D. Cal. May 7, 2012). The court found the
author’s termination notice to be valid in 2012, but there was subsequent litigation regarding other section issues
including section 203 joint ownership claims, statute of limitations, and attorneys fees. See Scorpio Music (Black Scorpio)
S.A. v. Willis, No. 11-cv-01557, 2016 WL 7438325 (S.D. Cal. Dec. 27, 2016).
607
See Scorpio Music S.A. v. Willis, No. 11cv1557, 2012 WL 1598043, at *4 (S.D. Cal. May 7, 2012).
608
Larry Rohter, A Copyright Victory, 35 Years Later, N.Y. TIMES (Sept. 10, 2013),
http://www.nytimes.com/2013/09/11/arts/music/a-copyright-victory-35-years-later.html.
609
See H.R. REP. NO. 100-609, at 34, 37–38 (1988); S. REP. NO. 100-352, at 9–10 (1988).
610
See, e.g., 1987 BCIA Hearings at 408 (statement of Sydney Pollack, Directors Guild of America) (“With the exception of
extreme cases of blatant and outrageous misrepresentations, there is almost no consistent across the board protection in
the United States against the alteration or mutilation of an artists work.”).
611
The tort of defamation is recognized in every state, and has been codified in the Restatement (Second) of Torts. See
RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 558 et seq. (AM. LAW INST. 1977).
612
To state a claim for defamation, a plaintiff must show (1) a statement that is both false and defamatory; (2)
publication of the statement to a third party absent some privilege; (3) that the publisher’s actions amounted to
negligence or greater fault; and (4) that the statement is actionable without demonstration of special harm (defamation
per se), or that the publication caused special harm. RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 558. A defamatory statement
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
108
passage of the BCIA, authors had successfully brought claims for defamation based on violations
of their right of attribution in a number of cases, including cases where: (i) a publisher continued
to identify an individual as an editor of a work he no longer oversaw,
613
(ii) a movie studio
inaccurately identified plaintiff as the producer of a motion picture of inferior quality,
614
and (iii)
publishers falsely identified an individual as the author of a published article.
615
Likewise,
authors had asserted claims for defamation in cases involving violations of the right of integrity,
such as where a defendant made substantial changes and additions to an article submitted by the
plaintiff.
616
While one study commenter asserted that violations of the rights of integrity and
attribution “are best addressed through well-established defamation doctrines,”
617
defamation
law is relevant to only a small sub-set of fact patterns under which an author’s attribution or
integrity interests may be impacted. In fact, the Office is aware of only a single case since passage
of the BCIA in which an author or performer asserted a defamation claim in an effort to protect
his rights of attribution or integrity, and the plaintiff was unsuccessful in that case.
618
must “tend[] to harm a person’s reputation to the extent that it lowers that person in the eyes of the community or
deters others from associating with that person. Lott v. Levitt, 556 F.3d 564, 568 (7th Cir. 2009) (internal citation
omitted). A closely related tort that is often asserted under similar facts is the “false light” variation of the right of
privacy. To state a claim for a false light tort, a plaintiff must show (i) that the publicity places them in a false light that
would be highly offensive to a reasonable person, and (ii) the publisher had knowledge of or acted in reckless disregard
as to the falsity of the publication and the false light in which the plaintiff would be placed. See RESTATEMENT (SECOND)
OF TORTS, § 652E. Although a plaintiff need not show special harm to recover under a false light theory, unlike a claim
for defamation, the requirement that such actions be offensive to a reasonable person has the effect in practice of
creating significant overlap between the two torts. Accordingly, some courts have allowed claims for misattribution to
proceed under the false light theory. See, e.g., JL Powell Clothing LLC v. Powell, No. 2:13–CV–00160–NT, 2014 WL 347067,
at *4 (D. Me. Jan. 30, 2014); Dempsey v. National Enquirer, 702 F. Supp. 934, 936 (D. Me. 1989).
613
See Clevenger v. Baker Voohris & Co., 168 N.E.2d 643, 644 (N.Y. 1960) (plaintiff, a well-known expert on New York state
law, brought suit against his former publishers for continuing to use his name on a treatise he no longer edited).
614
See Carroll v. Paramount Pictures, Inc., 3 F.R.D. 95, 96 (S.D.N.Y. 1942).
615
See Ben-Oliel v. Press Publ’g Co., 167 N.E. 432, 432 (N.Y. 1929) (plaintiff brought a claim against newspaper that falsely
identified plaintiff as the author of a published article); d’Altomonte v. N.Y. Herald Co., 139 N.Y.S. 200 (App. Div. 1913),
aff’d on other grounds, 102 N.E. 1101 (N.Y. 1913) (holding that falsely attributing an article to an author for purposes of
subjecting him to ridicule constituted actionable defamation); Santana v. Item Co., 189 So. 442, 446–47 (La. 1939)
(recognizing a libel cause of action arising out of the defendant's misidentification of the plaintiff as the author of a
letter published by the defendant); Gershwin v. Ethical Publ’g Co., 1 N.Y.S.2d 904, 905 (N.Y.C. Mun. Ct. 1937).
616
See Edison v. Viva Int’l, Ltd., 421 N.Y.S.2d 203, 207–08 (App. Div. 1979) (holding that plaintiff may bring a libel action
where an authors article is published in form and content substantially altered from the original if plaintiff can show
that the new content was of an inferior writing style or expresses sentiments or opinions that differ from his own).
617
EFF Initial Comments at 2.
618
See, e.g., Rich v. Lorge, No. 150039/2010, 2011 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 6781, at *8 (Sup. Ct. July 8, 2011) (plaintiff claimed that
an edited version of his article harmed his reputation as a writer). There were also a number of cases asserting claims
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
109
There are a number of likely reasons that defamation claims have been asserted in only a
limited number of cases to protect authors’ and performers’ attribution and integrity rights, many
of them stemming from attributes inherent in the concept of defamation. One of the most
significant hurdles an author must overcome to vindicate her attribution or integrity interests
through the assertion of a claim for defamation is the requirement that a plaintiff demonstrate
that a particular claim is both false and defamatory. As one academic has noted, defamation
claims “will be of no avail to an author who believes the integrity of her work has been impaired
but cannot show damages to her professional reputation.”
619
For example, while changes or edits
to an author’s work may violate the author’s right of integrity, the mere existence of such changes
or edits will not necessarily be sufficient to support a claim for defamation. As one court noted, a
mere statement “that the published work was different from the original is not to state that the
plaintiff was libeled” because “[t]here is always a possibility that any change in the original work
was made for the better rather than the worse.”
620
For this reason, one court rejected plaintiff’s
claims for defamation based on unauthorized edits and additions to his article, finding that such
changes were “not reasonably susceptible to defamatory connotation as no ordinary reader . . .
would regard changes such as using parenthesis, placing a long name in the title, or the use of the
phrase ‘anyone who’s anyone’ as libelous.”
621
Similarly, a court rejected plaintiffs’ libel claims
based on the use of plaintiffs’ music in a film with political messages antithetical to the plaintiffs’
political beliefs, finding that the mere use of the plaintiffs’ music did not give rise to a false or
defamatory implication.
622
The requirement to demonstrate harm to the plaintiff’s reputation illustrates another
limitation of defamation for protecting moral rights: defamation will have little, if anything, to
say in cases where the author alleges that her right of attribution has been violated through a lack
of attribution. Where a plaintiff’s work is used without attribution, there will not be a sufficient
“nexus between the work and the identity of the author” to demonstrate injury to the author’s
reputation.
623
Finally, certain subsets of defamation claims are subject to heightened pleading
requirements that may make it difficult for an author or performer to successfully assert a
for defamation arising out of the failure to identify one or more coauthors on published scholarship, but in each of
these cases the defamation claims were based on statements contained in related publications, and did not stem from
the attribution, or lack thereof, on the publication at issue. See, e.g., Romero v. Buhimschi, 396 Fed. App’x. 224 (6th Cir.
2010); Giordano v. Claudio, 714 F. Supp. 2d 508 (E.D. Pa. 2010).
619
KWA LL , SOUL OF CREATIVITY at 33 (2010). Of course, some study commenters see this as a feature, not a bug. See, e.g.,
EFF Initial Comments at 2.
620
Edison, 421 N.Y.S.2d at 207.
621
Lorge, 2011 N.Y. Misc. LEXIS 6781, at *8.
622
See Shostakovich v. Twentieth Century-Fox Film Corp., 80 N.Y.S.2d 575, 578 (Sup. Ct. 1948), aff’d, 87 N.Y.S.2d 430 (App.
Div. 1949).
623
Damich, Right of Personality, 23 GA. L. REV. at 65.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
110
defamation claim. One such heightened requirement applies when the author is a public figure,
which requires the plaintiff to demonstrate that the defendant’s actions were the result of malice,
not mere negligence.
624
Similarly, when the defamation asserted does not qualify as defamation
per se, a plaintiff must plead special damages that can be difficult to demonstrate.
625
Despite these limitations, the Office does not recommend any changes to state defamation
laws, which are far too blunt of an instrument to address authors’ legitimate interests in
protecting their rights of attribution and integrity. Further, any such changes to defamation law
are likely to have unintended consequences for protected speech. For this reason, the Office
believes that defamation claims are properly reserved for those narrow situations in which
misattribution or violations of the right of integrity are so severe as to imperil the author’s
reputation.
2. Privacy and Publicity
Another set of state laws that Congress recognized as providing protection for authors’
moral rights were the right of publicity and the related tort of misappropriation of a person’s
name or image under the common law right of privacy.
626
Both of these rights provide protection
624
See Session 2, Symposium Transcript, 8 GEO. MASON J. INTL COM. L. at 29 (remarks of Allan Adler, Association of
American Publishers). But see EFF Initial Comments at 2 (noting that defamation law provides a “better frame” for
attribution and integrity claims because “it includes a variety of constitutional safeguards designed to balance the
rights of individuals to protect their reputations against the right of the public to speak freely”).
625
See, e.g., Harris v. Twentieth Century Fox Film Corp., 43 F. Supp. 119, 122 (S.D.N.Y. 1942) (dismissing for failure to plead
special damages a libel claim that was based on defendants failure to credit plaintiff as providing creative input). See
also Roberta Rosenthal Kwall, Copyright and the Moral Right: Is an American Marriage Possible, 38 VAND. L. REV. 1, 25, n.91
(1985) (Kwall, American Marriage”).
626
Both the right of publicity and the right of privacy have their origins in the common law. The right of privacy was
first articulated in 1890 by Samuel Warren and Louis Brandeis in their article “The Right to Privacy,” and was thereafter
adopted by the Supreme Court of Georgia in 1905. See Samuel D. Warren & Louis D. Brandeis, The Right to Privacy, 4
HARV. L. REV. 193, 205 (1890) (describing the right as a principle of “an inviolate personality”); Pavesich v. New England
Life Ins. Co., 50 S.E. 68 (Ga. 1905). The right of privacy later was conceptualized as having four distinct sub-branches:
the torts of (i) intrusion upon physical seclusion, (ii) public disclosure of private facts, (iii) false light, and (iv)
appropriation of a person’s name or likeness to the defendants benefit (the last of these is hereinafter referred to as the
“tort of misappropriation” or the “misappropriation tort”). See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS, § 652A. Some early
cases expressed difficulty with allowing celebrities or other public persons to recover for the misappropriation of their
names or images under the rubric of a privacy right. See, e.g., O’Brien v. Pabst Sales Co., 124 F.2d 167, 170 (5th Cir. 1941);
Pallas v. Crowley-Milner & Co., 54 N.W.2d 595, 597 (Mich. 1952). Subsequently, courts recognized a cognizable
affirmative property right in the commercial exploitation of an individuals personality, labelled by some courts and
commentators as a “right of publicity,” in addition to the previously-recognized privacy right to not have one’s name or
image appropriated for another’s benefit. See Melville B. Nimmer, The Right of Publicity, 19 L. & CONTEMP. PROBS. 203,
203–04 (1954). One of the earliest cases adopting a “right of publicity” was the Second Circuit’s opinion in Haelan Labs.,
Inc. v. Topps Chewing Gum, Inc., which held that “a man has a right in the publicity value of his photograph, i.e., the right
to grant the exclusive privilege of publishing his picture.” 202 F.2d 866, 868 (2d Cir. 1953). While some courts have
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
111
against the use by a third party of certain aspects of an author’s identity or personality, such as
use of their name, image, or signature.
At the time the BCIA was passed, the right of publicity was already well established―a
majority of states recognized some form of the right
627
―and had already been used by courts to
vindicate a number of interests analogous to the moral rights of attribution and integrity. For
example, the right of publicity had provided authors with causes of action for misattribution of
authorship,
628
material alterations to the author’s work,
629
and distribution of the author’s work in
noted technical differences between the misappropriation tort under the right of privacy and the right of publicity, the
analysis under both causes of action are similar in many respects. See, e.g., Allison v. Vintage Sports Plaques, 136 F.3d
1443, 1449 (11th Cir. 1998) (“Although it does not appear that Alabama courts ever have recognized a right denominated
as ‘publicity, we conclude that the Alabama right of privacy contains an analogous right.”); Doe v. TCI Cablevision, 110
S.W.3d 363, 368 (Mo. 2003) (“Though facially similar, the protections afforded by each tort are slightly different: the
[misappropriation of name tort] protects against intrusion upon an individual’s private self-esteem and dignity, while
the right of publicity protects against commercial loss caused by appropriation of an individual’s identity for
commercial exploitation.’”) (internal citations omitted). For ease of reference, both the misappropriation tort under the
right of privacy and the right of publicity will be referred to herein as the “right of publicity,” except where the
difference is material to the analysis.
627
Only five states—Alaska, Colorado, Minnesota, North Dakota, and Wyoming—had not had occasion to adopt either
the right of publicity or the right of privacy in its case law, or had explicitly declined to do so. Another three states—
Nevada, New Hampshire, and Vermont—had adopted the right of privacy generally, with citations to the Restatement
(Second), but had not yet had occasion to adopt either the right of publicity or the specific tort of misappropriation
under the right of privacy. In contrast, thirteen states—California, Florida, Kentucky, Massachusetts, Nebraska, New
York, Oklahoma, Rhode Island, Tennessee, Texas, Utah, Virginia, and Wisconsin—had adopted statutory protections for
an individuals name and image (with Nebraska, New York, and Wisconsin styling their statutes as codifications of the
right of privacy, including the tort of misappropriation). All other states had adopted a common law claim for the right
of publicity, the misappropriation tort under the right of privacy, or both. See generally Jennifer E. Rothman, Rothman’s
Roadmap to the Right of Publicity, http://www.rightofpublicityroadmap.com (last visited Mar. 19, 2019).
628
See, e.g., Kerby v. Hal Roach Studios, Inc., 127 P.2d 577, 580 (Cal. Dist. Ct. App. 1942) (finding a violation of plaintiffs
right of privacy when defendant attributed plaintiffs name to a letter she did not write that “cast doubt on her moral
character”); Eliot v. Jones, 120 N.Y.S. 989, 990 (Sup. Ct. 1910) (holding that a publication of advertisements using an
author’s name in conjunction with an “inferior edition” of books violated his right of privacy under New York law); cf.
Williams v. Weisser, 78 Cal. Rptr. 542, 551 (Ct. App. 1969) (finding that the publication of notes taken by defendant of
plaintiffs oral lecture violated plaintiffs right of privacy because the notes were attributed to plaintiff).
629
See, e.g., Zim v. W. Publ’g Co., 573 F.2d 1318, 1326–27 (5th Cir. 1978) (finding that publication of plaintiffs revised
books, with attribution to plaintiff, without his consent violated his right of privacy); Neyland v. Home Pattern Co., 65
F.2d 363, 365 (2d Cir. 1933) (a distorted reproduction of authors painting as an embroidery pattern, which was
attributed to the author, violated New York’s privacy statute); cf. Drummond v. Altemus, 60 F. 338, 339 (C.C. Pa. 1894)
(plaintiff had the right to prevent being named as the author of published lectures that distorted his lectures and did
not present them fully or correctly).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
112
connection with inferior packaging and artwork.
630
The right of publicity had likewise been
construed to protect something akin to a first publication right.
631
a) Post-BCIA Case Law
The right of publicity has continued to be an important mechanism for protecting the
moral rights of authors and performers. Although the modern formulation of the right of
publicity is often economic in nature,
632
there is nevertheless a good deal of overlap between the
interests that plaintiffs seek to vindicate through the right of publicity and the moral rights of the
author.
633
For example, the right of publicity has offered a way for authors to seek damages in
some cases where the right of attribution has been violated through misattribution.
634
The right of
publicity has likewise been asserted to redress specific violations of the right of integrity, such as
through the distribution of a distorted version of an author’s painting as an embroidery pattern.
635
In addition, performers have asserted the right of publicity when their names or likenesses have
been used in ways that conflict with their personal beliefs or artistic integrity.
636
630
See, e.g., Big Seven Music Corp. v. Lennon, 554 F.2d 504, 512 (2d Cir. 1977) (finding that unauthorized distribution of
musical recordings with poor production and an unartistic cover design harmed musicians reputation and violated the
privacy right).
631
See Zacchini v. Scripps-Howard Broad. Co., 351 N.E.2d 454, 459–60 (Ohio 1976), rev’d on other grounds, 433 U.S. 562 (1977)
(finding that plaintiff had a cognizable right of publicity).
632
See, e.g., Christoff v. Nestle USA, Inc., 62 Cal. Rptr. 3d 122, 140 (Ct. App. 2007) (“However, section 3344 [the California
provision providing a right of publicity] is now understood as securing a proprietary interest. . . . It is an economic
right.”), rev’d in part on other grounds, 213 P.3d 132 (Cal. 2009).
633
See, e.g., KWALL, SOUL OF CREATIVITY at 34 (noting that many right of publicity judicial decisions focus on addressing
an individuals wounded feelings, and that application of the doctrine favors the authors interpretation and
presentation of her work over the interpretation of others).
634
Kerby, 127 P.2d at 580 (finding a violation of plaintiff’s right of privacy when defendant attributed plaintiffs name to
a letter she did not write that “cast doubt on her moral character”).
635
Neyland, 65 F.2d at 365.
636
See, e.g., Waits v. Frito-Lay, Inc., 978 F.2d 1093, 1104 (9th Cir. 1992), abrogated on other grounds, Lexmark Intl, Inc. v. Static
Control Components, Inc., 572 U.S. 118 (2014) (affirming compensatory damages award for use of voice imitator, noting
clear evidence of plaintiffs public stance against doing commercial endorsements); cf. Garcia v. Google, 786 F.3d 733,
740–41 (9th Cir. 2015) (noting that while the plaintiff actress did not hold a copyright in her movie performance, the
right of publicity and defamation could have been alternative theories used to control the use and editing of her
performance in a way she did not agree with). See also SAG-AFTRA Initial Comments at 4–5 (“Our performer
members, particularly those who are more well-known and thereby more recognizable, rely on the right of publicity to
defend their artistic integrity, career choices, brand, and reputation.”). But see 1987 BCIA Hearings at 408 (written
statement of Sydney Pollack, Directors’ Guild of America, noting that state laws do not adequately protect artists or
performers because “there is almost no consistent across-the-board protection”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
113
While the right of publicity is thus a versatile tool for protection of moral rights, there are
limits to its usefulness. One limitation has to do with the nature of the right itself―because it
seeks to protect the name and likeness of the author or performer, the right cannot address
situations where the author’s name or likeness is absent. Thus, the right of publicity can stand as
a proxy for the right of attribution against violations resulting from misattribution, but has little to
say in cases where the author is not credited at all. Similarly, the right of publicity can be invoked
to vindicate the right of integrity in situations where the author’s name remains attached to a
work following its distortion, but cannot address violations of the right of integrity where the
author’s name ceases to be associated with the work, such as through the complete destruction of
the work.
637
Another limitation of the right of publicity as a vehicle for protecting the moral rights of
an author or performer is the specter of federal copyright preemption. When a right of publicity
claim rests upon the use of a work or performance that is embodied in a copyrighted work, courts
will sometimes find that the right of publicity claim is preempted.
To find preemption, a court must find that two conditions have been met: the subject of
the claim is a work fixed in a tangible medium of expression that comes within the subject matter
or scope of copyright, and the right asserted under the state law is equivalent to an exclusive right
contained in 17 U.S.C. § 106.
638
Thus, if the mere fact that a defendant undertook an act covered
by section 106—be it an act of reproduction, distribution, or public display or performance—was
by itself sufficient to infringe the right of publicity, then the right of publicity claim will be
preempted.
639
If, however, a plaintiff were required to prove an additional element in order to
state a claim for violation of the right of publicity, such a claim would not be preempted.
640
On
this basis, at least one commentator has concluded that there is no categorical preemption of the
general right of publicity,” because someone’s “name and likeness do not become works of
authorship simply because they are embodied in a copyrightable work, such as a photograph.”
641
Nonetheless, there is much confusion about the contours of copyright preemption of right of
publicity claims in practice, and courts facing fact patterns that appear similar on the surface have
reached different conclusions.
637
As one scholar phrased it, the right to privacy “protects the association of the identity of the author with the work,
rather than the integrity of the work itself.” Damich, Right of Personality, 23 GA. L. REV. at 56.
638
See KNB Enters. v. Matthews, 92 Cal. Rptr. 2d 713, 723 (Ct. App. 2000).
639
1 NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 1.14[C]. But Nimmer continues that “[a] persona can hardly be said to constitute a
`writing' of an `author' within the meaning of the Copyright Clause of the Constitution. A fortiori, it is not a `work of
authorship' under the Act. The name and likeness do not become a work of authorship simply because they are
embodied in a copyrightable work such as a photograph.” 1 NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 1.01[B][1][c].
640
Id.
641
1 NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT § 1.17[A].
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
114
One line of California cases can serve to illustrate the confusion. In Fleet v. CBS, Inc., two
actors asserted a claim for violation of the California right of publicity statute based on the
defendant’s distribution of a motion picture containing performances for which they had not
been paid.
642
The California appellate court found this claim to be preempted by the federal
copyright laws, reasoning that the plaintiffs’ performances were “dramatic works” that were
protected by copyright law, and that defendant’s distribution of the film was equivalent to one of
the exclusive rights under section 106.
643
A different California appellate court declined to
endorse such a broad interpretation of the preemption doctrine. In KNB Enterprises v. Matthews,
the court interpreted Fleet as standing only “for the solid proposition that performers in a
copyrighted film may not use their statutory right of publicity to prevent the exclusive copyright
holder from distributing the film.
644
The court held that, “[a]s between the exclusive copyright
holder and any actor, performer, model, or person who appears in the copyrighted work, the
latter may not preclude the former from exercising the rights afforded under the exclusive
copyright by claiming a violation of the right of publicity.
645
Applying this reasoning, the KNB
court found that the models’ right of publicity claims in the case before it were not preempted
despite resulting from defendant’s unauthorized display and distribution of a copyrighted
photograph, stating that “the subjects of the [right of publicity] claims are the models’ likenesses,
which are not copyrightable even though ‘embodied in a copyrightable work such as a
photograph.’”
646
For this reason, the court found that “the rights asserted under the state statute,
the right of publicity, does not fall within the subject matter of copyright.”
647
Thereafter, the
Ninth Circuit considered the holdings in both Fleet and KNB and rejected the analysis of the KNB
court, finding a plaintiff’s claim for violation of his right of publicity, based on defendant’s sale of
counterfeit copies of DVDs embodying his performances, was preempted by the Copyright Act.
648
Yet another constraint on the utility of right of publicity claims for protection of moral
rights is the fact that the right is a creature of state law. Most states recognize some form of a
right of publicity: since passage of the BCIA, an additional twelve states have adopted statutory
right of publicity laws, bringing the total of states with statutory rights of publicity to twenty-
642
See Fleet v. CBS, Inc., 58 Cal. Rptr. 2d 645, 647 (Ct. App. 1996).
643
Fleet v. CBS, Inc., 58 Cal. Rptr. 2d 645, 650–52 (Ct. App. 1996).
644
KNB, 92 Cal. Rptr. 2d at 721 (emphasis in original). The KNB court likewise expressed muted skepticism of Fleet’s
assertion that the actors had a separate copyright interest in their performances. Id.
645
Id. at 721 (emphasis in original).
646
Id. at 723.
647
Id Accord Hoffman v. Capital Cities/ABC, Inc., 33 F. Supp. 2d 867, 875 (C.D. Cal. 1999) (finding that plaintiffs name,
face, and persona as embodied in a still photograph were not “writings,” and thus were not within the exclusive subject
matter of copyright), rev’d on other grounds, 255 F.3d 1180 (9th Cir. 2001).
648
See Jules Jordan Video, Inc. v. 144942 Canada Inc., 617 F.3d 1146, 1155 (9th Cir. 2010).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
115
five.
649
The vast majority of the remaining states recognize some form of common law right of
publicity.
650
In fact, there are currently only two states that have not yet explicitly adopted either
a statutory or a common law protection for the right of publicity.
651
The appearance of near-
uniformity in adoption of some version of the right of publicity belies the degree to which the
exact contours of the right differ significantly from jurisdiction to jurisdiction, however.
652
Even
among those states that have adopted statutory protections for the right of publicity, there are
significant differences with respect to such issues as:
What attributes of a person’s persona are protected: Indiana protects an individual’s
name, voice, signature, photograph, image, likeness, distinctive appearance, gesture,
or mannerisms,
653
while Massachusetts protects only a person’s “name, portrait or
picture.”
654
Whether the plaintiff must demonstrate fame or some form of commercial value
inherent in their name or likeness: Arkansas has no such requirement,
655
while
Pennsylvania only provides protection to a “natural person whose name or likeness
has commercial value.”
656
Whether the right of publicity is available posthumously, and, if so, for how long:
649
These include Alabama, Arizona, Arkansas, Hawaii, Illinois, Indiana, Louisiana, Nevada, Ohio, Pennsylvania, South
Dakota, and Washington, although the Arizona and Louisiana statutes apply only to soldiers. See generally Jennifer E.
Rothman, Rothman’s Roadmap to the Right of Publicity, http://www.rightofpublicityroadmap.com (last visited Mar. 19,
2019); Appendix D.
650
See Appendix D.
651
The North Dakota Supreme Court has not adopted the right of publicity, and so far has declined to rule on whether
North Dakota recognizes the common law tort of misappropriation under the right of privacy. See Am. Mut. Life Ins. v.
Jordan, 315 N.W.2d 290 (N.D. 1982). A recent decision of the Supreme Court of Wyoming adopted the intrusion upon
seclusion tort under the right of privacy tort as set out in the Restatement (Second) of Torts, but did not address the
misappropriation tort. See Howard v. Aspen Way Enters. Inc., 406 P.3d 1271, 1278 (Wyo. 2017).
652
See Joshua L. Simmons & Miranda D. Means, Split Personality: Construing a Coherent Right of Publicity Statute, ABA
LANDSLIDE, May/June 2018, at 38 (“In enacting right of publicity statutes, commentators have noted that many states
struggled to adopt a strong, consistent theory of why the right exists and what it should be designed to protect. In
some states, this failure has resulted in a kind of cognitive dissonance, such as when the right of publicity is called both
a ‘privacy right’ . . . and a ‘property right,” often interchangeably. Other states have avoided planting a flag in one
theory or another by defining the right of publicity broadly, and then scaling it back based on various exceptions.”)
(citations omitted).
653
See IND. CODE § 32-36-1-6 (2002).
654
MASS. GEN. LAWS ch. 214, § 3A (1973).
655
The statute grants “individual[s]” a property right in their name, voice, signature, photograph, and likeness. ARK.
CODE § 4-75-1104 (2016).
656
42 PA. CONS. STAT. § 8316(a) (2002).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
116
Wisconsin provides no posthumous right,
657
while the Virginia statute provides a
posthumous right for 20 years
658
and the Indiana statute provides protection for 100
years.
659
What steps a claimant must take to assert such a claim: Several states, including
California,
660
Nevada,
661
Oklahoma,
662
and Texas
663
require registration with the state to
assert a right of publicity posthumously.
Further complicating the issue is the question of which state’s right of publicity law will
apply to a given claim. While the traditional rule is that an individual has to be domiciled in a
state either at the time of the claim or at the time of their death to assert a common law right of
publicity claim,
664
several states have done away with such a requirement in their statutes. For
example, the Washington statute explicitly states that the “property right does not expire upon
the death of the individual or personality, regardless of whether the law of the domicile,
residence, or citizenship of the individual or personality at the time of death or otherwise
recognizes a similar or identical property right.”
665
Thus, it may be possible to assert a claim in
Washington for a posthumous violation of that state’s right of publicity, even if the individual
was a resident of a state, such as Wisconsin, that does not recognize such a posthumous right at
the time of his or her death.
666
657
See WIS. STAT. § 995.50 (1977).
658
VA. CODE § 8.01-40 (1950).
659
IND. CODE § 32-36-1-8(a) (1994).
660
CAL. CIV. CODE § 3344.1 (West 1971).
661
NEV. REV. STAT. § 597.800 (1989).
662
OKLA. STAT. tit. 12, § 1448 (1985).
663
TEX. PROP. CODE § 26.006 (1987).
664
See, e.g., Cairns v. Franklin Mint Co., 292 F.3d 1139, 1149 (9th Cir. 2002) (applying the law of Great Britain, where the
celebrity was domiciled at the time of death); Acme Circus Operating Co. v. Kuperstock, 711 F.2d 1538, 1541 (11th Cir. 1983)
(applying the law of California, where the celebrity was domiciled at the time of death); Melinda R. Eades, Choice of Law
and the Right of Publicity: Domicile as an Essential First Step, 66 BROOK. L. REV. 1301, 1310 (2001). But see Estate of Elvis
Presley v. Russen, 513 F. Supp. 1339, 1353–54 (D.N.J. 1981) (applying New Jersey’s posthumous right of publicity even
though celebrity was domiciled in Tennessee at the time of his death).
665
WASH. REV. CODE § 63.60.010 (1998).
666
At least one lower court has held that the Washington statute violates both the Commerce and Full Faith and Credit
Clauses of the U.S. Constitution to the extent that it seeks to grant a posthumous right of publicity to individuals that
died while domiciled in a state that did not provide for such posthumous rights. See Experience Hendrix, L.L.C. v.
Hendrixlicensing.com, Ltd., 766 F. Supp. 2d 1122 (W.D. Wash. 2011). The Ninth Circuit declined to reach this issue on
appeal, however, holding that the Washington statute was constitutionally applied to sales of merchandise bearing the
deceased celebrity’s name and image that occurred within the state of Washington. See Experience Hendrix L.L.C. v.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
117
b) Considering a Federal Right of Publicity
As noted above, the right of publicity and the privacy tort of misappropriation of a
person’s name or image remain important tools for artists to vindicate their moral rights,
especially against acts of misattribution or prejudicial distortions of their work.
667
There are,
however, a number of factors that constrain the usefulness of such claims to protect an author’s
attribution and integrity interests. While some of these constraints, such as its inapplicability to
acts of non-attribution, are inherent in the nature of the right of publicity doctrine, other
constraints are an outgrowth of the fact that the rights of publicity and privacy are creatures of
state, rather than federal, law. As a result, there is significant variability among the protections
available to an author depending upon where he or she chooses to live, and the specter of federal
copyright preemption looms over many right of publicity claims. This affects not only authors
who seek to protect their moral rights, but also potential defendants who must study the nuances
of the publicity and privacy statutes and case law of dozens of different states if they wish to
create new works that may feature the names or likenesses of large numbers of individuals.
Nor is there likely to be harmonization among state right of publicity laws in the near
future. Although the American Law Institute (“ALI”) included a section on the right of publicity
in its Restatement (Third) of Unfair Competition in 1995,
668
recent bills seeking to update right of
publicity laws in Arkansas,
669
Louisiana,
670
Minnesota,
671
and New York
672
did not follow the ALI’s
model law. More recently, the Uniform Laws Commission abandoned plans to draft a uniform
act on the right of publicity at its annual meeting in July 2018.
673
If Congress wished to address some of the uncertainty and ambiguity created by the lack
of harmonization among state right of publicity laws, Congress might consider adopting a federal
right of publicity law.
674
Adoption of such a federal right of publicity would be a significant
Hendrixlicensing.com, Ltd., 762 F.3d 829, 837 (9th Cir. 2014). Cf. Estate of Elvis Presley, 513 F. Supp. at 1353–54 (applying
New Jersey’s posthumous right of publicity even though celebrity was domiciled in Tennessee at the time of his death).
667
See supra Section IV.B.2.
668
RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF UNFAIR COMPETITION §§ 46–49 (AM. LAW INST. 1995).
669
H.R. 1002, 90th Gen. Assemb., 3d Sess. (Ark. 2016); S. 9, 90th Gen. Assemb., 3d Sess. (Ark. 2016).
670
Allen Toussaint Legacy Act, HB276, 2018 Reg. Sess. (La. 2018).
671
Personal Rights in Names Can Endure (“PRINCE”) Act, S.F. 3609, 89th Leg. (Minn. 2016).
672
Assemb. 08155, 2017–18 Leg. Sess. (N.Y. 2017); S. 05857, 2017–18 Leg. Sess. (N.Y. 2017).
673
See Minutes, Annual Meeting of the Executive Committee, Uniform Law Commission at 6 (July 23, 2018), available at:
https://www.uniformlaws.org/HigherLogic/System/DownloadDocumentFile.ashx?DocumentFileKey=2986559b-3c7c-
658b-06a8-7dfc00bac2d3&forceDialog=0.
674
Several groups and commentators have called for adoption of a federal right of publicity law over the years. See, e.g.,
Int’l Trademark Ass’n, Resolution on the U.S. Federal Right of Publicity, adopted Mar. 3, 1998, available at
https://www.inta.org/Advocacy/Pages/USFederalRightofPublicity.aspx; Eric J. Goodman, A National Identity Crisis: The
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
118
undertaking, implicating additional interests beyond just authors’ attribution and integrity
interests, and accordingly would require careful study and consultations with stakeholders
beyond those that participated in this Study.
675
For this reason, the Office is not currently
recommending statutory text for such a federal right, but will set forth herein various issues
Congress may want to consider if it chooses to go down this path.
The first question Congress must consider is whether to adopt a federal law that preempts
state right of publicity laws, or instead adopt language that would serve as a “floor” for right of
publicity protections, while allowing individual states to adopt more extensive protections in the
event they determine that such additional protections would be beneficial.
676
This approach
would be consistent with the approach taken by Congress in passing the Lanham Act and the
Defend Trade Secrets Act,
677
both of which elected not to preempt state law and accordingly
allowed for the continued development of state laws in the shadow of the federal statute. In
addition, it would avoid upsetting settled economic expectations of authors, performers, and
other individuals operating under current state right of publicity regimes.
If Congress instead elects to preempt state legislation on this issue, there are a number of
topics on which state legislation differs significantly that Congress would need to resolve: the
availability of post-mortem rights, the length of protection, whether such rights are transferable,
the scope of protectable “personas,” whether the personality right of non-famous individuals
Need for a Federal Right of Publicity Statute, 9 DEPAUL-LCA J. ART. & ENT. L. 227 (1999); Brittany Lee-Richardson, Multiple
Identities: Why the Right of Publicity Should be a Federal Law, 20 UCLA ENT. L. REV. 189 (2013); Christian B. Ronald, Note,
Burdens of the Dead: Postmortem Right of Publicity Statutes and the Dormant Commerce Clause, 42 COLUM. J.L. & ARTS 142
(2019) (arguing that state right of publicity laws violate the dormant Commerce Clause and that Congress should
remedy this by either creating a federal right of publicity or authorizing states to have their own unique right of
publicity laws); Kevin L. Vick & Jean-Paul Jassy, Why a Federal Right of Publicity Statute is Necessary, 28 COMM. LAW. 14
(Aug. 2011), available at https://www.americanbar.org/content/dam/aba/publications/communications_lawyer/
august2011/why_federal_right_publicity_statute_is_necessary_comm_law_28_2.authcheckdam.pdf.
675
Merely by way of example, a decision to adopt a postmortem federal right of publicity could have significant tax and
estate planning implications for affected individuals. See Mitchell M. Gans et al., Postmortem Rights of Publicity: The
Federal Estate Tax Consequences of New State-Law Property Rights, 117 YALE L.J. POCKET PART 203 (Apr. 1, 2008). Some
commentators have expressed concern that such consequences “could force heirs to commercialize the deceased
person’s identity to pay off [estate tax] debt.” JENNIFER E. ROTHMAN, THE RIGHT OF PUBLICITY: PRIVACY REIMAGINED FOR A
PUBLIC WORLD 123 (2018).
676
This approach would have the benefit of providing a measure of certainty for authors, performers, and other
individuals regarding the minimum level of protection that they could expect in their name and persona, while
allowing states to continue to provide additional protections as they see fit. A drawback of such an approach would be
that it would not provide certainty for those who wish to utilize the names or personae of others, as they would still
have to determine what, if any, additional state protections are applicable.
677
Defend Trade Secrets Act of 2016, Pub. L. No. 114-153, 130 Stat. 376 (codified in scattered sections of 18 U.S.C.).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
119
should be protected, and the proper scope of any exceptions. The resolution of these questions
would have significant follow-on implications for both rightsholders and users.
Whichever path Congress ultimately chooses, any federal law should provide, at a
minimum, protection for an individual’s name, signature, image, and voice against commercial
exploitation during their lifetime. The Office believes that such a law would further benefit from
explicit carve-outs for expressive works and other exceptions for First Amendment-protected
activities.
678
3. Misrepresentation and Unfair Competition
The common law principles of misrepresentation and unfair competition broadly cover a
wide range of actions from fraudulent misrepresentations leading to monetary loss to unfair or
deceptive business practices.
679
For example, courts have found that use of an author’s name in
association with the advertisement, publication, and sale of books with similar titles to the
author’s works violated unfair competition law by “unfairly and fraudulently. . . trad[ing] upon
[the author’s] reputation.”
680
Misrepresentation and unfair competition laws also encompass
common law trademark infringement claims, and can arise under either state or federal
trademark statutes.
681
While state unfair competition laws often do not contain wording that is
identical to the Lanham Act, many federal courts review such claims “congruent with Lanham
Act claims.”
682
As a result, outcomes under state unfair competition law differ little from
outcomes under the Supreme Court’s interpretation of the Lanham Act in Dastar, even though
that case purportedly turned on questions of (Lanham Act) statutory interpretation.
683
The
question of federal trademark law—the Lanham Act—and its use as a moral rights tool is
discussed in detail above.
684
678
See, e.g., ALA. CODE § 6-5-773 (2015) (“Nothing in this article will allow for an abridgement of free speech rights under
the First Amendment of the U.S. Constitution. . . .”); ARK. CODE § 4-75-1110 (2016) (“It is not a violation . . . if the name,
voice, signature, photograph, or likeness of an individual is used . . . in . . . a play, book, magazine, newspaper, musical
composition, visual work, work of art, audiovisual work, radio or television program if it is fictional or nonfictional
entertainment, or a dramatic, literary, or musical work”); CAL. CIV. CODE § 3344(d) (1971) (“[U]se of a name, voice,
signature, photograph, or likeness in connection with any news, public affairs, or sports broadcast or account, or any
political campaign, shall not constitute a use for which consent is required. . . .”).
679
See RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 525; 1 GILSON ON TRADEMARKS § 1.04[1].
680
Collier v. Jones, 66 Misc. 97, 100 (N.Y. Sup. Ct. 1910).
681
See 1 GILSON ON TRADEMARKS § 1.04[1]; 1 MCCARTHY ON TRADEMARKS § 4:6.
682
UMG, 281 F. Supp. 2d at 1186.
683
See, e.g., Twentieth Century Fox Film Corp. v. Dastar Corp., No. CV98–07189FMC, 2003 WL 22669587, at *4–5 (C.D. Cal.
2003); Williams, 281 F. Supp. 2d at 1186.
684
See supra Section VI.A.1.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
120
4. State Moral Rights Laws
At the time of the BCIA, eight states had recently enacted specific statutes “protecting the
rights of integrity and paternity in certain works of art.”
685
California led the charge by enacting
the first state statute that explicitly protected the moral rights of authors of works of fine arts.
686
Soon after its enactment, the California Art Preservation Act of 1979 was labeled as “a positive
step for the protection of some moral rights for some creators.”
687
Although there was criticism
that the statute was narrower than European moral rights statutes and Article 6bis of the Berne
Convention, it was nonetheless heralded by many as a much needed “coherent and
comprehensive set of protections for the patchwork relief traditionally provided by the courts.
688
Then-Register of Copyrights Ralph Oman noted that three basic models of state moral
rights law existed at the time the BCIA was being considered—the preservation model, the moral
rights model, and the public works model.
689
The preservation model sought to provide authors
with attribution and integrity rights, while also protecting works from destruction.
690
The moral
rights model provided authors with integrity and attribution rights, without protection against
destruction.
691
State statutes falling in the public works category were more related to state police
power and were used to protect certain works, such as antiquities and works of historical value,
685
H.R. REP. NO. 609, 100th Cong., 2d Sess. 34 (1988) (citing California, Louisiana, Maine, Massachusetts, New Jersey,
New York, Pennsylvania, and Rhode Island).
686
Jill R. Applebaum, Note, The Visual Artists Rights Act of 1990: An Analysis Based on the French Droit Moral, 8 AM. U. J.
INTL L. & POLY 183, 200 n.126 (1992).
687
Kwall, American Marriage, 38 VAND. L. REV. at 33.
688
Karen Gantz, Protecting Artists’ Moral Rights: A Critique of the California Art Preservation Act as a Model for Statutory
Reform, 49 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 873, 901 (1981) (“Gantz”). Gantz criticized the California statute for protecting only works
of fine art as opposed to all copyrightable works, for confining its protections to works of “recognized quality,” for
having a shorter duration than European counterparts, and for being waivable. Id. at 883–84, 886–87.
689
See 1989 VARA Hearing at 33 (written statement of Ralph Oman, Register of Copyrights).
690
See id. at 33–36. For example, Register Oman designated the California Art Preservation Act as a preservation statute
that prohibited the intentional destruction of a work of fine art as well as providing a right of attribution. Connecticut,
Massachusetts, and Pennsylvania were also cited as part of the preservation model. Note that the Connecticut Art
Preservation and Artists’ Rights Act was not cited by Congress as part of the state moral rights patchwork because it
became effective after S. REP. NO. 100-352 (1988) and H.R. REP. NO. 100-609 (1988), discussing the existing moral rights
framework, were issued. Id.
691
See 1989 VARA Hearing at 36–38 (1989) (written statement of Ralph Oman, Register of Copyrights) (citing Louisiana,
Maine, New Jersey, New York, and Rhode Island as states with moral rights statutes that provided the traditional
attribution and integrity rights).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
121
from vandalism.
692
Which model a state employs affects which art and artists are protected, as
well as the scope of that protection.
In the years after the BCIA’s enactment, several other states enacted moral rights
legislation.
693
State moral rights still generally fall into the three categories that Oman articulated
in 1989. In addition to Oman’s three models, states have also enacted legislation establishing
minimal attribution rights for authors engaged in transactions with art dealers.
694
Since the time
of the BCIA and VARA, no new state statutes have been enacted that fall under the preservation
model. The existing preservation model statutes are unique because they not only recognize an
author’s personal attribution and integrity interests, but also the importance to the “public
interest in preserving the integrity of cultural and artistic creations.”
695
The need to protect the
public interest manifests in provisions that prevent the destruction of works.
696
Similar to
preservation model statutes, the list of traditional moral rights statutes has remained the same
except for the addition of one new statute.
697
Accordingly, the majority of new statutes fall under
the public works model
698
as well as the new model covering art sales.
692
See 1989 VARA Hearing at 33–34, 38 (written statement of Ralph Oman, Register of Copyrights) (citing New Mexicos
Art in Public Buildings law as providing “extensive rights in a very limited area,” namely the protection of attribution
and integrity rights for works displayed in public buildings, including works of art incorporated in buildings). Note
that the New Mexico statute was also enacted after S. REP. NO. 100-352 (1988) and H.R. REP. NO. 100-609 (1988).
693
See e.g., CONN. GEN. STAT. § 42-116s (2015); NEV. REV. STAT. §§ 597.720–.740 (2017); N.M. STAT. § 13-4B-3 (2019). In
addition, the legislatures in Arizona, Montana, South Dakota, and Utah passed narrowly tailored bills that grant moral
rights under certain circumstances. ARIZ. REV. STAT. § 44-1776 (2015) (granting the right of attribution when the user is
an art dealer, subject to certain limitations); MONT. CODE § 22-2-407 (2017) (granting the right of attribution when the
state acquires the work for display); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS § 1-22-16 (2018) (granting the rights of attribution and integrity
to an author whose work has been acquired by the state); UTAH CODE § 9-6-409 (granting the rights of attribution and
integrity when the artist was commissioned by the state Arts Development Program to create a work of art).
694
See ARIZ. REV. STAT. § 44-1776 (2018); CONN. GEN. STAT. § 42-116m (2015); D.C. CODE § 28-5106 (2019); FLA. STAT.
§ 686.503 (2018); 815 ILL. COMP. STAT. 320/5 (2018); N.H. REV. STAT. § 352:8 (2018); OHIO REV. CODE § 5815.46 (2018); WASH.
REV. CODE § 18.110.030 (2018).
695
CAL. CIV. CODE § 989(a) (2019). See also MASS. GEN. LAWS ch. 231, § 85S(a) (2017).
696
See CAL. CIV. CODE § 987(a) (2019); MASS. GEN. LAWS ch. 231, § 85S(a) (2017); N.M. STAT. § 13-4B-1 (2018).
697
See NEV. REV. STAT. §§ 597.720–760 (2019).
698
See GA. CODE §§ 8-5-1 to -9 (2019); MONT. CODE §§ 22-2-401 to -408 (2018); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS §§ 1-22-9 to -17 (2018);
UTAH CODE § 9-6-401 to -409 (2019); WIS. STAT. § 41.57 (2019). California and Rhode Island possess general moral rights
statutes as well as moral rights statutes related to government acquisitions. See CAL. CIV. CODE § 987–989 (2019); CAL.
GOVT CODE § 15813.3(3)(e) (2019) (stipulating, as part of Californias Art in Public Buildings provisions, that the state
shall ensure “that each work of art acquired pursuant to this chapter is properly maintained and is not artistically
altered in any manner without the consent of the artist”); 5 R.I. GEN. LAWS §§ 5-62-2 to -12 (2018) (providing general
integrity and attribution rights); R.I. GEN. LAWS § 42-75.2-8(b)(1)(2) (2018) (stating that the state becomes the sole owner
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
122
By their nature, state moral rights statutes are not uniform, but there are certain general
provisions that are common amongst many of the statutes. First, the most common theme, and
often critique, is that the statutes only apply to works of fine art.
699
This limitation was first
criticized soon after the California Art Preservation Act was passed in 1979; the plethora of
statutes enacted since have replicated this limitation.
700
Second, the rights tend to be waivable.
701
Third, the rights do not usually apply to works created under work made for hire arrangements
or works that are created under contract for advertising or commercial use.
702
The limitation for
advertising and commercial uses can often be overcome by contract.
703
Fourth, the attribution
right is generally accompanied by a right to disclaim authorship, but it must be for a “just and
valid reason.”
704
Fifth, with the exception of some of the statutes, the destruction of a covered
of the art it acquires, but subject to moral rights retained by the artist, such as “the right to have the artist's name
associated with the work” and “the right to prevent degradation, mutilation, or aesthetic ruining of the work”).
699
See e.g., ARIZ. REV. STAT. §§ 44-1771 to -1778 (2018) (governing art dealers and defining “a work of fine art” as “a visual
rendition, including a painting, drawing, sculpture, mosaic or photograph”); CAL. CIV. CODE §§ 987(a)-(b)(2), 989(1)
(2019) (governing destruction of “fine art,” which is defined as “an original painting, sculpture, or drawing, or an
original work of art in glass, of recognized quality, and of substantial public interest”); CONN. GEN. STAT. § 42-116s(2)
(2015); N.J. STAT. § 2A:24A-3(e) (2019); 73 PA. CONS. STAT. § 2102 (2018); see also 3 NIMMER ON COPYRIGHT §8D.02[A]
(“[B]oth the federal and state laws [expressly covering moral rights of attribution and integrity] relate solely to
protection for works of visual art and have no application to other copyrightable subject matter. . . . Moral rights
protection for works of visual art follows explicit but circumscribed boundaries, in contrast to the broad but amorphous
protection accorded to all other types of copyrightable compositions.”); Edward J. Damich, State “Moral Rights” Statutes:
An Analysis and Critique, 13 COLUM.–VLA J.L. & ARTS 291, 293 (1989) (“[S]tate statutes do not provide substantial
protection of moral rights as measured by article 6bis of the Berne Convention. . . . [T]he state statutes recognize moral
rights in a much smaller class of works: in general moral rights are recognized only in the visual and graphic arts.”).
700
See Gantz, 49 GEO. WASH. L. REV. at 883.
701
See, e.g., CAL. CIV. CODE § 987(g)(3) (2019.); CONN. GEN. STAT. § 42-116t(d) (2015); MASS. GEN. LAWS ch. 231, § 85S(g)
(2017); NEV. REV. STAT. § 597.750 (2017); N.M. STAT. § 13-4B-3(E) (2018); 73 PA. CONS. STAT § 2107(2) (2018). But see ARIZ.
REV. STAT. § 44-1777 (2018).
702
See, e.g., CAL. CIV. CODE § 987(b), (g) (2019); CONN. GEN. STAT. § 42-116s(2) (2015); ME. REV. STAT. tit. 27, § 303(4)(B)
(2018); N.J. STAT. § 2A:24A-7 (2019); N.M. STAT. § 13-4B-2(A) (2018); LA. REV. STAT. § 51:2155(D) (2018); MASS. GEN. LAWS
ch. 231, § 85S(b) (2017); NEV. REV. STAT. § 597.720(3) (2017); N.J. STAT. § 2A:24A-7 (2019); N.M. STAT. § 13-4B-2(A) (2018);
N.Y. ARTS & CULT. AFF. LAW § 14.03(3)(d) (2018); 73 PA. CONS. STAT. § 2107(3) (2018); 5 R.I. GEN. LAWS § 5-62-5(d) (2018).
703
See, e.g., LA. REV. STAT. § 51:2155(D) (2018); N.J. STAT. § 2A:24A-7 (2019); N.Y. ARTS & CULT. AFF. LAW § 14.03(3)(d)
(2018); 73 PA. CONS. STAT. § 2107(3) (2018); 5 R.I. GEN. LAWS § 5-62-5(d) (2018).
704
CAL. CIV. CODE § 987(d) (2019); MASS. GEN. LAWS ch. 231, § 85S(d) (2017); N.M. STAT. § 13-4B-3(B) (2018). See also 73 PA.
CONS. STAT. §§ 2103–2014 (2018) (stating that an author may disclaim ownership for intentional or grossly negligent acts
resulting in the “defacement, mutilation, alteration or destruction of a work of fine art”). Some statutes explicitly state
what constitutes a just and valid reason. See LA. REV. STAT. § 51:2154(C) (2018) (Just and valid reason for disclaiming
authorship shall include that the work of fine art has been altered, defaced, mutilated, or modified without the artists
consent and damage to the artists reputation is reasonably likely to result or has resulted therefrom.”); ME. REV. STAT.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
123
work is generally permissible,
705
although alteration is prohibited in those states that assign an
integrity right.
706
Despite the above commonalities, state moral rights statutes also vary in many aspects,
most notably in the form of protections afforded, when those protections kick in, and the types of
works protected. When Congress determined that the United States met its Berne article 6bis
obligations to provide attribution and integrity rights to authors, it cited eight existing state
statutes in its rationale.
707
At the time, those eight statutes all provided some form of attribution
and integrity right. State moral rights statutes subsequently enacted have generally provided
more limited rights, establishing attribution rights rather than integrity rights. While this is not
tit. 27, § 303(3) (2018); NEV. REV. STAT. § 597.730(2) (2017); N.J. STAT. § 2A:24A-5 (2019); N.Y. ARTS & CULT. AFF. LAW §
14.03 (2)(a) (2018); 5 R.I. GEN. LAWS § 5-62-4(a) (2018).
705
See, e.g., LA. REV. STAT. §§ 51:2153, 51:2155(F)(1) (2018) (not prohibiting destruction in general, and waiving the artists
moral rights if removal of a work from a building would result in the works destruction); ME. REV. STAT. tit. 27, § 303(2)
(2018) (not prohibiting destruction); NEV. REV. STAT. § 597.740(1) (2017) (not prohibiting destruction); N.J. STAT. § 2A:24A-
4 (2019) (not prohibiting destruction); N.Y. ARTS & CULT. AFF. LAW § 14.03(2)(a) (2018) (not prohibiting destruction); 5 R.I.
GEN. LAWS § 5-62-3 (2018) (not prohibiting destruction). But see CAL. CIV. CODE § 987(c)(1) (2019) (prohibiting physical
defacement, mutilation, alteration, or destruction of a work of fine art); CONN. GEN. STAT. § 42-116t(a) (2015) (prohibiting
destruction unless done by the author); MASS. GEN. LAWS ch. 231, § 85S(c) (2017) (prohibiting the physical defacement,
mutilation, alteration, or destruction of a work of fine art unless done by the author); N.M. STAT. § 13-4B-3(A) (2018)
(prohibiting the intentional physical defacement, mutilation, alteration, or destruction of a work of fine art in public
view, but if a work is removed from a building and the alteration is unavoidable, the right is waived); 73 PA. CONS. STAT.
§§ 2104, 2108 (2018) (prohibiting the intentional physical defacement, mutilation, alteration, or destruction of a work,
but if a work is removed from a building and the alteration is unavoidable, the right is waived); 42 R.I. GEN. LAWS § 42-
75.2-8 (2018) (granting author right to prevent degradation, mutilation, or aesthetic ruining of works owned by the
state); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS § 1-22-16(3) (1989) (granting the author the right to prevent degradation, mutilation, or
aesthetic ruining of works owned by the state).
706
See, e.g., CONN. GEN. STAT. § 42-116t(a) (2015) (prohibiting physical defacement or alteration); GA. CODE § 8-5-5(5)
(2019) (prohibiting artistic alteration without the artist’s consent of art in state buildings); LA. REV. STAT. § 51:2153 (2018)
(prohibiting display or publication of a work or a reproduction that has been altered, defaced, mutilated, or modified);
ME. REV. STAT. tit. 27, § 303(2) (22018) (prohibiting display or publication of a work or reproduction that has been
altered, defaced, mutilated, or modified in a way that would damage the artists reputation); NEV. REV. STAT. § 597.740(1)
(2017) (prohibiting display or publication of a work or a reproduction that has been defaced, mutilated, or altered if
damage to the reputation of the artist is reasonably foreseeable); N.J. STAT. § 2A:24A-4 (2019) (prohibiting display,
publication, and reproduction of a work that has been altered, defaced, mutilated, or modified in a way that damages
the artists reputation); N.Y. ARTS & CULT. AFF. LAW § 14.03(1)(a) (2018) (prohibiting display or publication of a work or
reproduction that has been altered, defaced, mutilated, or modified if harm to the artist’s reputation is likely); 5 R.I.
GEN. LAWS § 5-62-3 (2018) (prohibiting display or publication of a work or reproduction that has been altered, defaced,
mutilated, or modified); 42 R.I. GEN. LAWS § 42-75.2-8(b)(2) (2018) (preventing degradation, mutilation, or aesthetic
ruining of works acquired by the state); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS § 1-22-16(3) (2018) (preventing degradation, mutilation, or
aesthetic ruining of works acquired by the state).
707
See S. REP. NO. 100-352, at 11 (1988).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
124
the case with all post-BCIA statutes, the trend has been to establish only attribution rights for
artists in connection with display in public buildings or art sales.
708
Relatedly, an artist’s ability to
enforce his or her moral rights varies greatly state by state. For example, some states attach moral
rights to artists’ works broadly regardless whether the work was created privately by an artist or
commissioned by the state.
709
Others only extend protection to works commissioned by the state
or displayed in state buildings
710
or to artwork involved in sales or commissions.
711
Lastly, while
state moral rights statutes only protect works of visual art, there is no uniform definition of the
term. Most of the statutes define covered works as “works of fine art,” but the specific definitions
vary greatly. Some enumerate long lists of examples
712
and others simply refer to only visual and
708
See, e.g., ARIZ. REV. STAT. § 44-1776(A)(1) (2018) (providing attribution in transactions with art dealers); FLA. STAT. §
686.503(4) (2018) (providing attribution in consignment transactions); 815 ILL. COMP. STAT. § 320/5(2) (2018) (providing
attribution in transactions with art dealers); MONT. CODE § 22-2-407 (2017) (providing attribution in state-owned works);
N.H. REV. STAT. § 352:8 (2018) (providing attribution in transactions with art dealers); OHIO REV. CODE 5815.46 (2018)
(providing attribution in transactions with art dealers); WASH. REV. CODE § 18.110.030(2) (2018) (providing attribution in
transactions with art dealers). But see CONN. GEN. STAT. § 42-116t(a),(b), § 42-116m(d) (2015) (providing general
attribution and integrity rights to artists as well as attribution in consignment transactions); GA. CODE §§ 8-5-5(5), § 8-5-
7(a) (2019) (providing integrity and attribution for works in state buildings); NEV. REV. STAT. § 597.730 (2017) (providing
attribution and integrity rights to artists); N.M. STAT. § 13-4B-3(A), (B) (2018) (providing integrity rights to works in or
on state buildings and attribution rights in general); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS § 1-22-16(1) to (3) (2018) (providing attribution
and integrity rights to works in public buildings); UTAH CODE § 9-6-409 (2019) (providing attribution in state-
commissioned works and a quasi-integrity right by allowing the artist to disclaim authorship if conservation or repair
damages the works integrity); see also D.C. CODE § 28-5106(a),(b) (2019) (providing attribution in transactions with art
dealers well as compensation for loss or damage to consigned works); WIS. STAT. §§ 41.57, 129.06 (2019) (providing only
integrity for art in state public buildings and only attribution in art sales).
709
See, e.g., CAL. CIV. CODE §§ 987–989 (2019); N.Y. ARTS & CULT. AFF. LAW § 14.03 (2018).
710
See, e.g., GA. CODE § 8-5-1 to -9 (2019); MONT. CODE § 22-2-407 (2017); S.D. CODIFIED LAWS § 1-22-16 (2018); UTAH CODE
§ 9-6-409 (2019).
711
See, e.g., ARIZ. REV. STAT. § 44-1776 (2018); D.C. CODE § 28-5106 (2019); FLA. STAT. § 686.503 (2018); 815 ILL. COMP. STAT.
320/5 (2018); N.H. REV. STAT. § 352:8 (2018); OHIO REV. CODE § 5815.46 (2018); WASH. REV. CODE § 18.110.030 (2018).
712
See, e.g., CONN. GEN. STAT. § 42-116s(2) (2015) (defining “work of fine art” as “any drawing; painting; sculpture;
mosaic; photograph; work of calligraphy; work of graphic art, including any etching, lithograph, offset print, silkscreen
or other work of graphic art; craft work in clay, textile, fiber, metal, plastic or other material; art work in mixed media,
including any collage, assemblage or other work combining any of the artistic media named in this definition, or
combining any of said media with other media; or a master from which copies of an artistic work can be made, such as
a mold or a photographic negative, with a market value of at least two thousand five hundred dollars; provided work
of fine art shall not include (A) commissioned work prepared under contract for trade or advertising usage, provided
the artist, prior to creating the work, has signed an agreement stating that said work shall be a commissioned work
which may be altered without consent; (B) work prepared by an employee within the scope of his employment
duties”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
125
graphic works including, but not limited to, paintings, drawings, or sculptures.
713
Some states
also expressly exclude works that are included in other jurisdictions, like film and video.
714
Understandably, the variety of state statutes can be difficult to navigate, and this system of
inconsistent state laws only protects a thin subset of works.
State moral rights laws provided the most explicit expression of statutory moral rights in
the United States until the passage of VARA in 1990. VARA amended the Copyright Act’s
preemption provision (section 301), providing that this federal statute preempts “all legal or
equitable rights that are the equivalent to” the attribution and integrity rights conferred by VARA
with respect to “works of visual art to which the rights conferred by section 106A apply.”
715
According to the legislative history, “[a] single Federal system is preferable to State statutes or
municipal ordinances on moral rights because creativity is stimulated more effectively on a
uniform, national basis.”
716
Subsection 301(f) outlines several exceptions to VARA’s preemption authority including
that the provision does not apply to causes of action commenced before the effective date of
VARA (June 1, 1991).
717
For example, in Pavia v. 1120 Avenue of the Americas Associates, the U.S.
District Court for the Southern District of New York found that the plaintiff’s claim regarding the
display of his work in an altered form under New York’s Artists Authorship Rights Act (AARA)
was not preempted by VARA because the improper display started in 1988, before the effective
date of the federal legislation.
718
VARA also does not preempt any activities that violate legal or
equitable rights that are not “equivalent” to any of the rights conferred by VARA with respect to
“works of visual art.
719
Activities violating legal or equitable rights that extend beyond the life of
713
See, e.g., 73 PA. CONS. STAT. § 2102 (2018) (defining “fine art” as “an original work of visual or graphic art of
recognized quality created using any medium. The term shall include, but not be limited to, a painting, drawing or
sculpture”).
714
See LA. REV. STAT. § 51:2152(7) (2018) (excluding sequential imagery such as motion pictures); ME. REV. STAT. tit. 27,
§ 303(1)(D) (2018) (excluding sequential imagery such as motion pictures); N.J. STAT. § 2A:24A-3(e) (2019) (excluding
sequential imagery such as motion pictures). But see 815 ILL. COMP. STAT. 320/1(7)(a) (2018) (including videotape); MASS.
GEN. LAWS ch. 231, § 85S(b) (2017) (including audio and video tape and film); N.M. STAT. § 13-4B-2(B) (2018) (including
audio and videotape and film).
715
Visual Artists Rights Act of 1990, Pub L. No. 101-650, § 605 (1990) (codified at 17 U.S.C. § 301(f)).
716
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 21 (1990) (quoting 1989 VARA Hearing at 36 (written statement of Ralph Oman, Register of
Copyrights)).
717
See 17 U.S.C. § 301(f)(2)(A).
718
901 F. Supp. 620, 626–27 (S.D.N.Y. 1995).
719
17 U.S.C. § 301(f)(2)(B).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
126
the author are also not preempted under this provision.
720
Thus, post-mortem rights for artists
under state laws that address misattribution, mutilation, or destruction of works of visual art
likely remain available to eligible parties.
721
For determining when VARA preempts a plaintiff’s state law claim, the courts follow the
standard for determining preemption under the broader Copyright Act. For preemption to occur,
the work of authorship in which rights are claimed must fall within the subject matter of
copyright; and the state law must create legal or equitable rights that are equivalent to any of the
exclusive rights within the general scope of copyright.
722
For example, the U.S. District Court for
the Southern District of New York in Board of Managers of Soho International Arts Condominium v.
City of New York held that an artist’s claim under New York’s AARA regarding the destruction of
a mural on a building was preempted by VARA.
723
The court found that the mural falls within
the subject matter of copyright and that the integrity rights under AARA are equivalent to those
under VARA. While the artist argued that the rights under AARA are not equivalent to VARA’s
rights as AARA does not limit the right of integrity to “works of recognized stature” as under
VARA, the court disagreed stating that preemption can occur even when the state statute is
broader.
724
The court further emphasized that VARA and AARA have nearly identical provisions
regarding the right of integrity; and thus the rights under AARA are “equivalent” to VARA’s
rights for the purposes of the preemption analysis.
725
The limited availability of relevant case law leaves many questions unanswered regarding
the drafting and interpretation of VARA’s preemption provision. For example, it is unclear
whether the phrase “with respect to works of visual art to which the rights conferred by section
106A apply” would permit claims concerning works that do not meet section 101’s definition of a
“work of visual art” or would preempt any claims relating to “pictorial, graphic, or sculptural”
works. The legislative history states that “works that are not covered by the law, such as
audiovisual works, photographs produced for non-exhibition purposes” would not be
720
17 U.S.C. § 301(f)(2)(C).
721
See, e.g., CAL. CIV. CODE § 987(g)(1) (2019); MASS. GEN. LAWS ch. 231, § 85S(g) (2017).
722
See H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 21 (1990).
723
No. 01 Civ. 1226, 2003 WL 21403333, at *16 (S.D.N.Y. June 17, 2003), reheard on other grounds, No. 01 Civ. 1226, 2005 WL
1153752 (S.D.N.Y. May 13, 2005).
724
See Bd. of Managers of Soho Int’l Arts Condo. v. City of New York, No. 01 Civ. 1226, 2003 WL 21403333, at *14 (S.D.N.Y.
June 17, 2003), reheard on other grounds, No. 01 Civ. 1226, 2005 WL 1153752 (S.D.N.Y. May 13, 2005); see also H.R. REP. No.
101-514, at 21 (1990) (stating that VARA “will preempt a State law granting the right of integrity in paintings or
sculpture, even if the State law is broader than Federal law”).
725
Bd. of Managers of Soho Int’l Arts Condo., 2003 WL 21403333.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
127
preempted.
726
If claims for these types of works are not preempted, then works that do not meet
the limited definition of a “work of visual art” may be able to claim potentially greater remedies
under state law.
727
5. Contracts and Licenses
Contracts and licenses, which are governed by state law, have been at the forefront of
protecting moral rights in the U.S. A tradition of private ordering was an important part of the
U.S. patchwork of moral rights when the United States joined the Berne Convention.
728
Although
the practice of bargaining with the rights of attribution and integrity has its critics, the use
remains common. The Office has identified five main types of contracts, the use of which affect
authors’ moral rights.
Party-Negotiated. Two-party licenses negotiated between an author and a user
(such as a publisher or a recording company) are fundamental to many copyright
industries. In such negotiated licenses, authors may include or trade the right of
attribution and the right of integrity as desired, based on bargaining power.
729
During the hearings leading up to the U.S. joining the Berne Convention, many
stakeholders noted the moral rights aspects of such agreements.
730
726
H.R. REP. NO. 101-514, at 21 (1990).
727
See Gegenhuber v. Hystopolis Prods., Inc., No. 92 C 1055, 1992 WL 168836 (N.D. Ill. July 13, 1992); see also Gegenhuber v.
Hystopolis Prods., Inc., 660 N.E.2d 107 (1995) (holding that attribution claims relating to puppets, costumes, sets, and the
performance of a puppet show are not preempted by VARA as the works do not qualify as “works of visual art.”).
728
See H.R. REP. NO. 100-609, at 34 (1988), reprinted in 1987 BCIA Hearings at 1043 (explaining that the hearing testimony
support the majority view that “there is a composite of laws in this country that provides the kind of protection
envisioned by Article 6bis” and that this composite includes contracts.); see also 1987 BCIA Hearings at 350 (written
statement of David Ladd on behalf of the Coalition to Preserve the American Copyright Tradition) (discussing how
authors may use contracts to control integrity of their work.); id. at 639 (statement of David Lawson) (discussing the use
of contracts to secure rights of integrity and attribution in the architecture industry); id. at 697 (statement of Barbara A.
Ringer) (discussing the patchwork of moral rights and how contracts fit in the patchwork); id. at 824 (written statement
of the Association of American Publishers) (discussing membership views that contracts and long-established trade
practices were in compliance with Berne Article 6bis); id. at 970–971 (written statement of the Honorable Carlos J.
Moorhead) (explaining that the administration’s proffered Berne Implementation bill “proceeds from the assumption
that the totality of U.S. law, including…common law rights of contract…provide protection for the rights of paternity
and integrity sufficient to comply with the Berne Convention”).
729
See AAP Initial Comments at 5; CCIA Initial Comments at 5; DGA/WGAW Initial Comments at 4; SAG-AFTRA Initial
Comments at 2.
730
See, e.g., 1987 BCIA Hearings at 47 (written statement of Ralph Oman, Register of Copyrights and Assistant Librarian
for Copyright Services, Library of Congress) (“Contracts between authors and publishers may provide [moral rights].”);
id. at 145 (written statement of Donald J. Quigg, Assistant Secretary and Commissioner of Patents and Trademarks)
(“The Administrations bill reflects the view taken by many copyright experts that the totality of current U.S. law,
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
128
Industry-Negotiated. Large, complex, well-established copyright industries such as
the American film industry operate under heavily-negotiated employment
agreements that govern a myriad of topics including copyright ownership and
licensing.
731
The agreements generally bind large groups as parties with a guild or
association on one side and movie studios or production companies on the other.
732
Known as collective bargaining agreements, these agreements exist partly to offset
the loss of copyright by individual contributors under the work-made-for-hire
doctrine.
733
Works-made-for-hire. “Work-made-for-hire” refers to two very specific situations as
defined in section 101 of the U.S. Copyright Act. The first situation is when a work
is created by an employee in the scope of employment. The second covers works
in nine categories created by independent contractors who have a written
agreement with the commissioning party confirming the work is intended to be a
work-made-for-hire.
734
When a work is made for hire, the employer or
including . . . contract rights . . . provides sufficient protection for the rights of paternity and integrity.”); id. at 225
(statement of Irwin Karp, Chairman, Ad Hoc Working Group on U.S. Adherence to the Berne Convention) (discussing
clauses in motion picture contracts dealing with transfers of rights of integrity).
731
See MPAA Initial Comments at 14 (“These CBAs [collective bargaining agreements], negotiated by sophisticated
attorneys and business people on both sides, cover in fine detail virtually every conceivable aspect of the relationship
between the producer and certain creative talent, including compensation and working conditions. . . . [T]he CBAs also
protect individuals’ rights of attribution and integrity by contract.”).
732
See, e.g., Directors Guild of America, Inc. Basic Agreement of 2014, at 1–7 (July 1, 2014); 2017 Memorandum of
Agreement Between the Screen Actors Guild-Am. Fed’n of Television and Radio Artists and the All. of Motion Picture
& Television Producers, at 70–76 (Sept. 29, 2017).
733
See DGA/WGAW Initial Comments at 1 (noting that because writers’ and directors’ contributions often fall under the
work-made-for-hire doctrine, that “statutory provision gives producers a significant power that is taken away from
American audiovisual creators (writers and directors)” but that “in the U.S., the Guilds have used the process of
collective bargaining to enshrine creative and economic benefits for their members, including provisions that partially
address moral rights of writers and directors”).
734
The Copyright Act defines a work made for hire as either:
(1) a work prepared by an employee within the scope of his or her employment; or
(2) a work specially ordered or commissioned for use as a contribution to a collective work, as a part of a motion
picture or other audiovisual work, as a translation, as a supplementary work, as a compilation, as an instructional
text, as a test, as answer material for a test, or as an atlas, if the parties expressly agree in a written instrument signed
by them that the work shall be considered a work made for hire.
17 U.S.C. § 101.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
129
commissioning party is considered to be the author of the work for copyright
purposes.
735
Author-dictated. Author-dictated licenses are written by (or at the request of) the
author to exactly match their desired terms. Examples of such licenses include
shrink-wrap, click-wrap, and other methods of presenting licenses in terms of
service. Authors, generally companies in these situations, can choose to require
attribution and to prohibit derivative works as they see fit.
Author-chosen. Author-chosen licenses are generally pre-made documents, such as
those developed by Creative Commons, that are selected and applied by the
author.
736
a) The Role of Contracts in Moral Rights
The freedom to include or exclude moral rights from an agreement is a key element of
American copyright law that proponents maintain has long provided authors with the credit and
control they desire over their works while allowing users to make modifications necessary to the
use of the work. Public comments in response to the Office’s Notice of Inquiry reveal that some
stakeholders believe contractual agreements effectively protect moral rights
737
while others assert
that is not the case.
738
Those who argue that contractual agreements are an appropriate and
735
See 17 U.S.C. §201(b). This allows a single party to control the rights in works created by many hands. See also
MPAA Initial Comments at 7 (explaining the importance of the work-made-for-hire doctrine, “[g]iven the large number
of creative contributors to a major motion picture”).
736
Creative Commons offers a suite of licenses, including several open license options as well as more restrictive
licenses. All current Creative Commons licenses include an attribution requirement, and authors who wish to preserve
their right of integrity can choose licenses that reserve their derivative work rights. There are two license options that
reserve the right to make derivative works, a feature referred to as “NoDerivatives.” These licenses are the BY-ND
(Attribution NoDerivatives) and BY-NC-ND (Attribution NonCommercial NoDerivatives). See Licensing Types,
CREATIVE COMMONS, https://creativecommons.org/share-your-work/licensing-types-examples/ (last visited Mar. 22,
2019). Creative Commons also offers other legal tools related to placing or recognizing works in the public domain. See
CC0 1.0 Universal (CC0 1.0) Public Domain Dedication, CREATIVE COMMONS, https://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/
zero/1.0/ (last visited Mar. 22, 2019).
737
See, e.g., AAP Initial Comments at 5 (arguing that addressing attribution and integrity as part of contracts “gives
authors and publishers the necessary flexibility to agree on how to address these issues as they see fit”); CCIA Initial
Comments at 3 (“An author can always choose to license works in a manner to ensure attribution and integrity if they
so choose.”); NMPA Reply Comment at 12 (stating that “contractual rights, and the process for adjudicating the
problem, can and almost always do offer more comprehensive and efficient solutions than a legislative alternative”);
SAG-AFTRA Initial Comments at 2 (“But to the American performer, there are perhaps no greater rights than the
ability to enforce contracts. . . . Contracts, whether entered into individually or through union representation, provide
performers flexibility to negotiate for fair compensation, the sorts of moral rights articulated in the [WIPO Internet]
treaties, and much more.”).
738
See, e.g., Authors Guild Initial Comments at 8 (As for contract law, it is not a solution to moral rights.”); CVA Initial
Comments at 9 (“Unfortunately, most artists are lax or ill-informed about creating written contracts for the sale or
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
130
effective approach to moral rights cite flexibility, control, and certainty as benefits. For example,
the American film industry has been using contracts to address moral rights at least as far back as
the 1930s and continues to do so today.
739
The music industry has also spoken on the value of
contracts as a means of addressing attribution and integrity interests.
740
The importance of such
flexibility in the publishing world has been noted each time the United States has discussed the
possibility of statutorily recognizing moral rights.
741
The American Association of Publishers
recently noted that contracts give “authors and publishers the necessary flexibility to agree on
how to address” attribution and integrity.
742
Indeed, one authors group pointed out that contracts
licensing of their work); CRA Reply Comments at 3 (“The CRA supports the argument of the Authors Guild, Inc. that
contracts provide no solution given the imbalance of negotiating power between authors and publishers.”); IFJ Initial
Comments at 9 (Contract provisions cannot substitute for enforceable statutory moral rights.”); SCL Initial Comments
at 3 (“The Society of Composers & Lyricists disagrees with the William Strauss report [STUDY NO. 4: THE MORAL RIGHT
OF THE AUTHOR (1959)] that states a patchwork of common laws, such as torts and contracts is sufficient to cover moral
rights protections for an author.”).
739
See MPAA Initial Comments at 2 (“Through the existing legal framework and myriad contractual agreements,
producers obtain the valuable services of individual creators as well as the rights necessary to exploit the finished
product in accordance with their business judgment.”); Letter from Wallace McClure, Chairman, Inter-Departmental
Comm. on Copyright, to Sen. F. Ryan Duffy (May 18, 1935) (on file with the Wisconsin Historical Society) (explaining
that film studios paid for the right to modify a work when licensing the work from author).
740
See A2IM Reply Comments at 4 (“Many independent record agreements, in all their different iterations, already
incorporate and address attribution and integrity rights.”); RIAA Reply Comments at 2 (“[C]ontracts between artists
and record labels routinely include provisions that address attribution.”).
741
See 1987 BCIA Hearings at 319 (additional material submitted by Kenneth W. Dam, Vice President, Law and External
Affairs, IBM) (“Preventing authors from entering binding contractual arrangements . . . could significantly impair
commercial flexibility and make publishers unwilling to invest in works which may require modification to be
marketed effectively. ‘This would not only have the result of restricting the market for artistic works in general, but
would especially harm those authors who are more than willing to allow changes to be made in their work to render
them marketable. The consequence to the public at large would be a reduced access to intellectual and artistic works.’”)
(quoting Comment, Protection of Artistic Integrity: Gilliam v. American Broadcasting Companies, 90 HARV. L. REV. 473,
479 (1976)). In December of 1937, Senator F. Ryan Duffy received at least five letters with identical requests for
reservations to the Berne Convention. One of the included requests was for a reservation that would protect the
sanctity of contracts with respect to moral rights. Each letter included the same reservation language: “The
safeguarding of contractual rights between the producers and users of copyrightable material unfettered by the theory
‘le droit moral.’” Letter from Cass Canfield, President, Harper & Bros. Publishers, to Sen. F. Ryan Duffy (Dec. 15, 1937)
(on file with the Wisconsin Historical Society); Letter from Alfred A. Knopf, President, Alfred A. Knopf, Inc., to Sen. F.
Ryan Duffy (Dec. 21, 1937) (on file with the Wisconsin Historical Society); Letter from Frank L. Dodd, President, Dodd,
Mead & Co., Inc. Publishers, to Sen. F. Ryan Duffy (Dec. 16, 1937) (on file with the Wisconsin Historical Society); Letter
from John Macrae, President, E.P. Dutton & Co., Inc. Publishers, to Sen. F. Ryan Duffy, (Dec. 14, 1937) (on file with the
Wisconsin Historical Society); Letter from Frederic G. Mulcher, Chairman, Copyright Comm., R. R. Bowker Co.
Publishers, to Sen. F. Ryan Duffy, Comm. on Foreign Relations (Dec. 14, 1937) (on file with the Wisconsin Historical
Society).
742
AAP Initial Comments at 5.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
131
can assist in protecting moral rights.
743
A contract concerning a work of authorship may take
account of such aspects as how to include attribution in different formats, the author’s desires,
and, as the RIAA pointed out, “the commercial context in which those works will be distributed,
promoted and otherwise exploited.”
744
In some sectors, authors and publishers can also reach
agreement after publication or distribution to make changes to previously agreed terms.
745
Over the past century there have been many examples of contracts allowing authors and
users of works to make mutually beneficial arrangements on attribution and modifications.
Collective bargaining agreements in the film industry have particularly been highlighted for their
role.
746
When testifying before the House of Representatives in 1936, Edwin P. Kilroe, Chairman
of the Copyright Committee of the Hays organization (predecessor to the Motion Picture
Association of America (“MPAA”)), emphasized both the importance of being able to alter a story
on which a film is based and the role contracts play in allowing authors to limit the rights of the
studio to alter the underlying work.
747
Fifty years later, in testimony before the House, the
Directors’ Guild expressed similar sentiments regarding the importance of contracts in preserving
rights against alteration when it discussed its opposition to the practice of colorization without
director consent.
748
The author-dictated and author-chosen contract models have offered additional
opportunities for authors to preserve their moral rights. Authors have found value in the ability
to use Creative Commons licenses to explicitly require attribution in the manner they desire or to
743
See Authors Alliance Initial Comments at 8 (“Authors can currently realize attribution, integrity, and other non-
economic authorial rights by harnessing their copyrights and insisting on license terms that vindicate those rights.”).
But see IFJ Initial Comments at 9 (asserting that moral rights must be unwaivable to be effective, stating that “larger
publishers and broadcasters routinely impose waivers in contracts presented without the possibility of negotiation”).
744
RIAA Reply Comments at 2–3.
745
This includes handling issues such as removing an authors attribution at the request of an author. The Committee
on Publication Ethics has published guidelines to help publishers navigate such requests. See Changes in Authorship
(d) Request for Removal of Author after Publication, COMM. ON PUBLN ETHICS, https://publicationethics.org/files/
Authorship%20D.pdf (note that in this example requested removal is done at discretion of the publisher).
746
See DGA/WGAW Initial Comments at 4–6 (noting that directors’ attribution and full control of the integrity of the
“director’s cut” are preserved in collective bargaining agreements, but that it is production companies who “have
ultimate authority over the final product of the project”); MPAA Reply Comments at 5–6; SAG-AFTRA Initial
Comments at 9–11.
747
Revision of Copyright Laws Hearings at 1013 (statement of Edwin P. Kilroe, Attorney, Twentieth Century Fox Film
Corporation and Movietonews, Inc.) (reading a statement by the Board of Trade of England).
748
See 1987 BCIA Hearings at 418–19 (written statement of the Directors Guild of America) (expressing concerns that
directors who did not have such provisions in their contracts had no legal means to object to alterations of which they
did not approve).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
132
limit modifications of works.
749
These licenses, which are new since the United States joined the
Berne Convention, can protect attribution and integrity interests. Authors can easily choose the
license they would like through the Creative Commons license chooser tool without the cost of
engaging a lawyer to write a license.
750
But these pre-made, author-chosen licenses are not
appropriate in all instances, limiting their utility as mechanisms for protection of attribution and
integrity interests for many artists. For example, almost all of these licenses allow a user to
redistribute the original work for noncommercial purposes, and thus use of a Creative Commons
license would not be appropriate for an author wishing to maximize compensation for their
work.
751
Instead, such licenses are more appropriate for authors who either do not want to
monetize their work at all, or who only want to monetize some rights in their work, such as the
creation of derivative works
752
or commercial uses of their original work.
753
In the latter case,
users and authors would still need to negotiate a separate license for the creation of derivative
works or for commercial uses of the original work. For this reason, author-chosen licensing
749
See Authors Alliance Initial Comments at 8; PK Initial Comments at 1. Creative Commons is an international
nonprofit organization founded in 2001 with the goal of creating content licensing options between full copyright and
the public domain. See Hal Plotkin, All Hail Creative Commons / Stanford Professor and Author Lawrence Lessig Plans a Legal
Insurrection, S.F. GATE (Feb. 11, 2002), https://www.sfgate.com/news/article/All-Hail-Creative-Commons-Stanford-
professor-2874018.php.
750
The Creative Commons license chooser is available at http://creativecommons.org/choose. It walks licensors through
two questions to help them find the appropriate license for how they would like their work to be used: Allow
adaptations of your work to be shared? Allow commercial uses of your work?”
751
See ASJA Initial Comments at 7; Mira T. Sundara Rajan, Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright
Offices Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 12 (May 15, 2017) (“Sundara Rajan Reply Comments”); NWU-SFWA Joint
Initial Comments at 9–10.
752
The two NoDerivatives licenses allow a licensee to “produce and reproduce, but not Share, Adapted Material.”
These two licenses are Attribution-NoDerivatives (BY-ND) and Attribution NonCommercial-NoDerivatives (BY-NC-
ND). See Attribution-NoDerivatives 4.0 International, CREATIVE COMMONS, http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-
nd/4.0/legalcode (last visited Mar. 22, 2019) (section 2(a)(1)(B) of the license terms lays out this part of the scope);
Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International, CREATIVE COMMONS, http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-
nc-nd/4.0/legalcode (last visited Mar. 22, 2019) (section 2(a)(1)(B) of the license terms lays out this part of the scope).
753
The three noncommercial licenses all require attribution and do not allow any uses “primarily intended for or
directed towards commercial advantage or monetary compensation.” They are: BY-NC (Attribution NonCommercial);
BY-NC-SA (Attribution NonCommercial ShareAlike), which also requires that any derivative works be licensed under
the same or a compatible license; and BY-NC-ND (Attribution, NonCommercial NoDerivatives), which prohibits
sharing derivative works. See Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International, CREATIVE COMMONS,
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/legalcode (last visited Mar. 22, 2019) (sections 1(i) and 2(a) lay out this
information); Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International, CREATIVE COMMONS,
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/legalcode (last visited Mar. 22, 2019) (sections 1(k) and 2(a) lay out
this information); Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International, CREATIVE COMMONS,
http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/legalcode (last visited Mar. 22, 2019) (sections 1(h) and 2(a) lay out
this information).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
133
models such as the Creative Commons licenses are best suited for protecting attribution and
integrity interests in connection with non-economically compensated uses
Author-dictated licenses can also preserve the moral right of integrity.
754
For example,
license terms of the Regular License on design platform Envato Market allow waiver of some
aspects of the integrity right by allowing licensees to remove unwanted elements from works that
they license, but preserve other aspects by prohibiting the extraction and use of a single element
of the work for use on its own.
755
For example, a website template licensee can delete icons from
the template, but the icons cannot be removed and used in other templates.
756
In this way, author-
dictated licenses give authors more control over their attribution and integrity interests, but the
non-negotiated nature of these licenses means fewer options for authors and users to come to
agreement on other potential provisions.
b) Concerns about Protecting Moral Rights Through Contract
Concerns over using contracts and other private agreements to protect moral rights tend
to focus on two things: privity and alienability. The privity requirement for contractual
relationships affects whether negotiated moral rights protections will be preserved with
downstream uses. Alienability affects the waiving of copyright rights that one party to an
agreement may require. The concern is that rights may be waived in licensing due to lack of
bargaining power rather than true desire to part with such rights. Additionally, of course, private
agreements are purely voluntary and do not provide legal baselines that affect all parties
regardless of bargaining power, as would statutory moral rights.
(1) Privity
A contract cannot bind anyone who is not a party to the contract. The Creative Commons
licenses address this issue by structuring their licenses so that every down-stream user licenses
from the original licensor, thus creating new privity between new parties.
757
But for licenses
754
Cf. U.S. COPYRIGHT OFFICE, SOFTWARE-ENABLED CONSUMER PRODUCTS 4 n.26 (2016), available at
https://www.copyright.gov/policy/software/software-full-report.pdf (discussing the limits that software licensees may
encounter, such as how devices with licensed software can be used).
755
See Regular License, ENVATOMARKET, http://audiojungle.net/licenses/terms/regular (last visited Mar. 22, 2019). Envato
Market describes itself as “a collection of themed marketplaces, where creatives sell digital assets.” For example, users
can purchase Photoshop actions, video footage, WordPress themes, and plugins. See Envato Market, ENVATO,
http://envato.com.
756
See Regular License, ENVATOMARKET, http://audiojungle.net/licenses/terms/regular (last visited Mar. 22, 2019).
757
See, e.g., Attribution-NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International, CREATIVE COMMONS,
https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/legalcode (last visited Mar. 22, 2019) (section 2(a)(5)(A) of the license
terms states that in terms of downstream recipients “[e]very recipient of the Licensed Material automatically receives
an offer from the Licensor to exercise the Licensed Rights under the terms and conditions of this Public License”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
134
where the terms are negotiated between specific parties, privity remains a concern.
758
For
example, if Party A licenses a work to Party B with a requirement that all uses of the work include
attribution, and Party C uses the work without a license, there is no requirement for Party C to
obey Party B’s promise to attribute the work to Party A. In the publishing world, this can happen
when digital pirates circulate misattributed, unauthorized copies of books; the pirates have no
contractual obligation to the author that can be enforced.
759
However, agreements may specify that certain rights carry through to any sublicensees.
For example, if Party A licenses a work to Party B with a requirement that all uses of the work
include attribution, Party A can also require that any sublicenses issued by Party B also include
this term. When Party C sublicenses the work from Party B, Party A’s attribution requirement
will be preserved. Record labels routinely do this when licensing works to third parties.
760
(2) Alienability
Attribution and integrity, like the right of reproduction or the ability to exercise a right in
a certain jurisdiction, are sticks in the larger bundle of rights that an author can exchange and
trade.
761
As traditionally conceptualized in many common law countries, moral rights are
alienable in the sense that they are waivable—that is they can be traded away—but not
transferable except for devolution to heirs upon death of the author. Authors generally cannot
sell the right to sue for lack of attribution or for modifications to which they object. Moral rights
may be waived either through non-inclusion or through explicit waiver language.
762
Making
moral rights inalienable would remove them from the contracting process entirely.
On one hand, the ability to waive moral rights is beneficial because it creates market
efficiency by allowing each author and user to assign their own value to the rights being
758
See, e.g., Authors Guild Initial Comments at 9; CVA Initial Comments at 9; DGA/WGAW Initial Comments at 7.
759
See Authors Guild Initial Comments at 9.
760
See RIAA Reply Comments at 2.
761
See, e.g., CCIA Initial Comments at 5 (noting that authors can address contract issues by “seeking greater
consideration in exchange for foregoing attribution, or receiving less consideration where the specific use makes
attribution desirable”); Kernochan Center Initial Comments at 12 (“[A]n author may have to trade attribution for other
payments or protections she might otherwise seek.”).
762
ASJA Initial Comments at 2 (“Recently, ASJA members, many of whom write for print and online magazines and
other publications on a freelance basis, are noting something new in their contracts with publishers: clauses saying
they waive any moral rights claims to their work or the management of it.”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
135
exchanged.
763
On the other hand, proponents of making moral rights inalienable argue that
allowing waiver can result in a default status quo of waiver in every agreement.
764
Proponents of maintaining the alienability of moral rights stress that this keeps current
contracts from being disturbed
765
and allows future agreements to account for differing
circumstances.
766
They point out that prohibiting waiver by making moral rights inalienable
impedes the freedom to contract. As both the National Music Publishers’ Association and the
American Association of Independent Music opine, a clause waiving moral rights “is simply too
much of a material term of a contract” for statutory override.
767
Additionally, authors sometimes
want to release their works directly into the public domain or with as few strings as possible.
768
The ability to waive moral right helps facilitate such action.
769
763
See, e.g., Christopher Buccafusco & Christopher Jon Sprigman, Joint Comments Submitted in Response to U.S.
Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 1 (May 28, 2017) (“Buccafusco-Sprigman Joint Initial Comments”)
(explaining economic efficiency of contract negotiations and the findings of their empirical research that “[t]he current
regime [where the default rule is to not provide attribution] allows authors to request attribution during licensing, and,
in doing so, it increases the likelihood that licenses for productive uses of works will take place”); CCIA Initial
Comments at 5 (noting that contracting for moral rights in mutual and voluntary agreements “results in optimal
outcomes for both parties”); NMPA Reply Comment at 4 (pointing out that the moral rights patchwork, which includes
contracts, “forms a healthy moral rights jurisprudence that . . . brings certainty and efficiency to enforcement of these
rights in the marketplace”).
764
See Authors Alliance Initial Comments at 9 (discussing the pros and cons of waiver and pointing out that “easy
waivability is also a matter of concern as this may negate or weaken the benefit that statutory recognition of
noneconomic authorial rights would otherwise provide authors in their negotiations”); IFJ Initial Comments at 9
(noting that in the United Kingdom and Ireland, jurisdictions that allow waiver of moral rights, “larger publishers and
broadcasters routinely impose waivers in contracts presented without the possibility of negotiation”).
765
See BMI Reply Comments at 2 (“So long as moral rights are waivable, then such rights are not likely to upset current
contract practices.”); NMPA Reply Comment at 7 (asserting that maintaining contractual moral rights waivers is
important because “[a]dopting a moral rights law that would override carefully negotiated contractual terms will cause
significant disruption and uncertainty, depriving the publisher of an essential bargained-for term that may severely
limit their rights to fully exploit the musical work, engendering a reciprocal negative effect on its songwriter).
766
See Sundara Rajan Reply Comments at 13 (discussing how waivability of moral rights can address needs of various
industries).
767
NMPA Reply Comment at 7; A2IM Reply Comments at 4.
768
See, e.g., Authors Alliance Initial Comments at 9 (discussing the pros and cons of waiver and noting that “[o]n the one
hand, it is important that these rights be waivable such that authors can dedicate their works to the public domain with
‘no strings attached’”).
769
While the licenses in the Creative Commons license suite preserve moral rights, Creative Commons also has a legal
tool designed to place works directly into the public domain. This tool, called CC0 is designed to waive all copyright
and related rights. However, as discussed above, moral rights are unwaivable in many foreign jurisdictions—or at least
the ability to waive them is unclear. The CC0 tool addresses this issue by with a fallback royalty-free, non-transferable
license and an affirmation not to enforce moral rights. See CC0 1.0 Universal, CREATIVE COMMONS,
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
136
Proponents of making moral rights inalienable explain that when parties have unequal
negotiating positions, authors may be forced to trade rights they do not really want to trade in
exchange for any exploitation of their work.
770
For example, the American Society of Journalists
& Authors points out that the majority of freelance journalists are required to sign contracts
waiving any moral rights as a condition for obtaining a writing job; there is no negotiation on this
point.
771
In addition, in the case of joint works, because any single coauthor may wholly license a
coauthored work, each coauthor of a work has the power to use as bargaining chips the rights of
all the authors.
772
Some industries have developed norms for addressing situations in which one
coauthor may affect the attribution or integrity of other coauthors.
773
Proponents of making moral
rights explicitly inalienable stress that allowing waiver means that contracts would frequently
default to waiver, which would significantly weaken any statutorily granted rights.
774
https://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/legalcode (last visited Mar. 22, 2019). In addition, Creative
Commons has introduced a system for including metadata about the author, title of the work, and the jurisdiction
where the work is being offered under CC0. Embedding the information also requires affirmative consent to release the
work under CC0. See CC0 Waiver, CREATIVE COMMONS, http://creativecommons.org/choose/zero/waiver (last visited
Mar. 22, 2019).
770
Cf. Authors Alliance Initial Comments at 8 (“In practice, however, some authors currently may not feel that they have
sufficient bargaining power to insist upon these terms, or may have assigned their copyrights long ago when such
practices were not widespread.”); CVA Initial Comments at 2 (Mar. 28, 2017) (“[V]isual artists are at a disadvantage in
the negotiation process with a well-armed client.); SCL Initial Comments at 4 ([I]n the absence of collective
bargaining, the AV composer has limited negotiation power with respect to rights.”); Sundara Rajan Reply Comments
at 10 (“The ability to develop provisions on moral rights in copyright contracts is typically limited by the unequal
bargaining power of the parties involved.). But see, NMPA Reply Comment at 6 (“Songwriters gain much more
through contractual bargaining . . . than they would through a one size fits all statutory solution.”).
771
ASJA Initial Comments at 3 (“Since publishers are now inclined to have writers contractually waive moral rights
before the fact, and most writers must sign contracts in order to eat, American writers have no moral rights. A right one
can’t access is not possessed.”).
772
The Copyright Act defines a joint work as one “prepared by two or more authors with the intent that their
contributions be merged into inseparable or interdependent parts of a unitary whole.” 17 U.S.C. § 101. Each
contributor of a joint work owns an undivided interest in the entire work, so, while there are nuances, the general rule
is that a single contributor may license the work without the authorization of the other contributors. See 1 NIMMER ON
COPYRIGHT § 6.10[A][2].
773
For example, the Committee on Publication Ethics has produced a flow chart for providing guidance to academic
and scholarly publishers for when a coauthor requests removal of their name from a paper. The actions the publisher
should take include checking with all other coauthors that they agree with such removal. See Changes in Authorship – (d)
Request for Removal of Author After Publication, COMM. ON PUBLN ETHICS, https://publicationethics.org/files/
Authorship%20D.pdf.
774
See NWU-SFWA Joint Initial Comments at 8 (stating that the “disparity in bargaining power . . . would lead, in
practice, to the inclusion of blanket waivers of moral rights”).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
137
Others argue not that moral rights should be inalienable, but that they should be statutory
so that their exclusion from a contract must be explicit. One commenter maintains that, were
moral rights more explicitly protected in U.S. law, contractual clauses protecting the right of
attribution and integrity would be more common.
775
Empirical research submitted in connection
with this study supports this argument, showing that authors place greater value on moral rights,
and are thus more likely to want them included in contracts, when they already hold these rights
and are negotiating to sell (trade them away) rather than to buy (obtain them).
776
The study
found that affirmative waiver—trading away of rights explicitly granted—has a higher value to
artists than waiver by non-inclusionnot requiring the inclusion of rights otherwise not
granted.
777
As discussed above, this affirmative waiver approach is the one taken by VARA.
778
Given the concerns over both alienability and inalienability of moral rights, and the
capability of contracts to address privity issues with restrictions on sublicensing, the Office
recommends that any potential changes to the moral rights patchwork not upset the existing
contractual order. United States copyright law rarely interferes with private agreements, and this
general principle should be maintained with regard to moral rights.
(3) Concerns Unique to Works Made for Hire
Works made for hire present a special set of concerns because under the Copyright Act, a
work-made-for-hire relationship does not involve transferring rights in a work; it instead means
that the employer or commissioning party is the legal author of the work from its inception.
779
This brings up two particular issues: whether works-made-for-hire should have explicit statutory
moral rights attach to them, and, if so, who should be deemed the author for the purposes of
those moral rights.
In the comments received for this study, some argued that moral rights should not attach
to works made for hire because the works, no longer having an explicit connection to the creator,
do not represent part of the creator’s personality.
780
Others suggested that authorship for the
775
Authors Alliance Initial Comments at 4.
776
Buccafusco-Sprigman Joint Initial Comments at 2–5 (“photographers valued the same right somewhere between four
or five times more when they were contemplating selling it versus when they were contemplating buying it”).
777
Buccafusco-Sprigman Joint Initial Comments at 5.
778
VARA provides for very specific waiver “if the author expressly agrees to such waiver in a written instrument signed
by the author.” 17 U.S.C. § 106A(e)(1). That signed instrument must identify the work and its uses, and will only apply
to the specified work and uses.
779
See 17 U.S.C. § 201(b).
780
See BMI Reply Comments at 2 (explaining that “a corporate entity does not have the same personal creative
relationship and interest in the work as does the creator of a work”); CVA Initial Comments at 8.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
138
purpose of moral rights should attach to the creator while economic rights continue to the
employer or commissioning party under the work-made-for-hire doctrine.
781
Congress has frequently reviewed the work-made-for-hire doctrine since it was first
codified in the 1909 Act.
782
In the ensuing century-plus, it has reviewed comments ranging over
the same spectrum as those received for this study, from work-made-for-hire is best as-is, to
suggestions for changes to how the doctrine is applied, to overall skepticism of the concept in
general.
783
Congress has consistently decided that work-made-for-hire is an important element of
U.S. copyright law, as evidenced by the 1909 Act and the 1976 Act. As discussed, under the
current work made for hire system, moral rights like rights of attribution and control over
derivative works can be designated to either the actual creator or the legal author as appropriate.
This flexibility is important and should be preserved.
6. Other Forms of Private Ordering
a) Plagiarism
Attribution is a long held fundamental norm in American society, one whose importance
is instilled from a young age through an emphasis in education systems on proper attribution and
citation.
784
Some argue that such social and professional norms may do better to regulate
attribution than any legal or statutory means, given the highly contextual nature of attribution
781
See CVA Initial Comments at 5 (“The moral right of attribution should include works created by independent
creators created under work made for hire contracts.”); FMC Reply Comments at 4 (“Attribution on works for hire
would allow songwriters proper association with their creative endeavors.”); Music Creators Initial Comments at 3
(suggesting “[e]nactment of specific provisions of the US Copyright Act recognizing the right of attribution for the
actual creative authors of copyrighted works (including creators of so-called ‘works made for hire’), notwithstanding
any waiver of such rights by authors and authors for hire”); NWU-SFWA Joint Initial Comments at 13 (“Legislation is
necessary to protect the moral rights of authors of ‘work for hire.’”).
782
See, e.g., BORGE VARMER, STUDY NO. 13: WORKS MADE FOR HIRE AND ON COMMISSION (1958), reprinted in STAFF OF S.
COMM. ON THE JUDICIARY, 86TH CONG., COPYRIGHT LAW REVISION: STUDIES PREPARED FOR SUBCOMM. ON PATENTS,
TRADEMARKS, AND COPYRIGHTS OF THE COMM. ON THE JUDICIARY, U.S. SENATE, STUDIES 11–13, at 127–43 (Comm. Print 1960)
(including history of consideration of the issue going back to 1906).
783
See generally Definition of Work Made for Hire in the Copyright Act of 1976: Hearing on S. 2044 Before the S. Comm. on the
Judiciary, 97th Cong. (1982); United States Copyright Office and Sound Recordings as Work Made for Hire: Hearing Before the
Subcomm. on Courts & Intellectual Prop. of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary, 106th Cong. (2000).
784
See, e.g., Academic Integrity Policy, BROOKLYN TECHNICAL HIGH SCH., available at http://www.bths.edu/
School_Policies/PDF_Policies/Academic%20Integrity%20-%20Plagiarism.pdf; Student Academic Code of Ethics,
MONTGOMERY COUNTY CMTY. COLL., available at https://www.mc3.edu/about-mccc/policies-and-procedures/student-
academic-code-of-ethics; Harvard College Handbook for Students: Academic Integrity and Academic Dishonesty, HARV. UNIV.,
available at https://handbook.fas.harvard.edu/book/academic-integrity#two; Use of Others’ Material, ASSOCIATED PRESS,
https://www.ap.org/about/news-values-and-principles/telling-the-story/use-of-others-material.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
139
requirements.
785
While a norms-based approach to plagiarism may not be legally enforceable, a
violation of these norms may carry serious consequences.
786
An act of plagiarism can result in a
range of penalties including suspension or expulsion, firing, loss of tenure or revocation of a
license, not to mention the reputational harm that can occur from a mere allegation of
plagiarism.
787
Such policies and norms concerning plagiarism can differ greatly across institutions and
types of media. For instance, as discussed above, the film and television industry has a highly
structured attribution system whereby guilds representing the various contributors to a work
negotiate legally enforceable credit rights with production companies.
788
Other sectors, such as
academia and journalism utilize a less formal, more norms-based approach to attribution.
789
785
See Jonathan Band & Matt Schruers, Dastar, Attribution, and Plagiarism, 33 AIPLA Q.J. 1, 11 (2005); see also
Organization for Transformative Works (“OTW”), Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s
Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 2 (May 15, 2017) (“OTW Reply Comments”). But see National Writers Union
(“NWU”) Reply Comments Submitted in Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Jan. 23, 2017, Notice of Inquiry at 3 (May
15, 2017) (“NWU Reply Comments”) (noting that a norms-based approach has a limited effect as “ethics and
professionalism are irrelevant to the activities of for-profit corporations”).
786
LCA Initial Comments at 2 (“Although these plagiarism policies are not directly enforceable in a court of law, breach
of these policies can result in punishments far more severe than the remedies for copyright infringement.”).
787
See Stuart P. Green, Plagiarism, Norms, and the Limits of Theft Law: Some Observations on the Use of Criminal Sanctions in
Enforcing Intellectual Property Rights, 54 HASTINGS L.J. 167, 174–75 (2002). Some high profile cases of plagiarism have
involved severe consequences at academic and media institutions. See Dan Barry et al., Correcting the Record; Times
Reporter Who Resigned Leaves Long Trail of Deception, N.Y. TIMES (May 11, 2003), https://www.nytimes.com/2003/05/11/
us/correcting-the-record-times-reporter-who-resigned-leaves-long-trail-of-deception.html (Jayson Blair of the New York
Times resigned after it was discovered that he committed “frequent acts of journalistic fraud” over the course of several
years, including plagiarizing material from other news articles); Marc Santora, Columbia Professor in Noose Case Is Fired
on Plagiarism Charges, N.Y. TIMES (June 24, 2008), https://www.nytimes.com/2008/06/24/nyregion/24columbia.html
(Professor Madonna Constantine was sanctioned and later terminated over charges of plagiarizing a former colleague
and former students’ works); see also Maggie Haberman, After Plagiarism Reports, Monica Crowley Won’t Take White House
Job, N.Y. TIMES (Jan. 16, 2017), https://www.nytimes.com/2017/01/16/us/politics/monica-crowley-plagiarism.html
(detailing how a National Security Council candidate ultimately rejected the position after allegations of plagiarism
surfaced).
788
See SAG-AFTRA Initial Comments at 10 (discussing SAG-AFTRAs collective bargaining agreement provision on
billing); Catherine L. Fisk, Credit Where It’s Due: The Law and Norms of Attribution, 95 GEO. L.J. 49, 77 (2006) (“Fisk,
Credit”).
789
Plagiarism policies in these areas can be articulated both by institutions themselves (see, e.g., Academic Integrity,
COLUM. COLL., http://www.college.columbia.edu/academics/academicintegrity) as well as by professional organizations
(see, e.g., Statement on Standards of Professional Conduct (Updated 2019)Plagiarism, AM. HIST. ASSN,
http://www.historians.org/jobs-and-professional-development/statements-standards-and-guidelines-of-the-
discipline/statement-on-standards-of-professional-conduct#Plagiarism; The Washington Post Standards and Ethics, AM.
SOCY OF NEWS EDITORS, http://asne.org/content.asp?contentid=335).
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
140
Plagiarism policies and norms can also vary within industries. In academia, for example,
attribution norms for multi-author works with large-scale collaborations, such as are common in
scientific fields, tend to be more formal.
790
Attribution norms can also vary depending on the
medium used. For instance, radio or podcast journalism tend to have less stringent norms
governing attribution than print or even television journalism, as giving attribution to every
contributor on air may not be practical.
791
Similarly, in the art world, plagiarism and attribution
norms can vary greatly depending on the medium and type of work, and these norms continue to
evolve as new art forms emerge. While appropriation in art is nothing new,
792
as more extreme
styles of appropriation art, such as those employed by Richard Prince and Jeff Koons, become
normalized, perceptions of what it means to plagiarize another artist’s work in the context of
modern art are shifting.
793
Thus, attribution tends to happen in large part due to the professional or societal
consequences, rather than any legal consequences, of plagiarism. Norms regarding attribution
and what it means to plagiarize have the advantage of being flexible and adaptable as
technologies develop and new means of creating and distributing art and media emerge. The
downside to such norms-based rules is that their very flexibility can result in inconsistent
application, both across time and even within a given field. Still, it is unclear whether institutions
or fields lacking more formal and longstanding policies and procedures regarding plagiarism
would benefit from a statutory attribution right which could standardize these requirements.
Any such right would, of course, need to account for the differences in attribution standards
across different industries, professions, and modes of creative expression.
b) Voluntary Initiatives
In conjunction with legal and regulatory means of enforcing the rights to attribution and
integrity, voluntary initiatives and private ordering also work to secure these rights for authors.
In addition to the systems that have developed around plagiarism, many sectors are developing
their own systems of attribution and industry norms that work to ensure proper attribution for
creators without the use of formalized legal regimes. Similarly, many sectors are also pursuing
790
See Fisk, Credit, 95 GEO. L.J. at 83–84.
791
This may be changing, though, as new technologies in broadcast journalism develop; many podcasts now give on-air
credit to producers, editors, engineers, and even interns. See e.g., Dear Sugars, WBUR, http://www.wbur.org/dearsugar
(each podcast concludes with a reading of the credits).
792
See generally Timothy Anglin Burgard, Picasso and Appropriation, 73 ART BULL., 479 (1991) (discussing Pablo Picassos
use of appropriation).
793
See Jonathan Bailey, Why So Many Photographers Hate Richard Prince, PLAGIARISM TODAY (May 21, 2015),
http://www.plagiarismtoday.com/2015/05/21/why-so-many-photographers-hate-richard-prince; Henri Neuendorf, Jeff
Koons Sued Yet Again Over Copyright Infringement, ARTNET NEWS (Dec. 15, 2015), http://news.artnet.com/art-world/jeff-
koons-sued-copyright-infringement-392667; see also Glendon Mellow, How Plagiarized Art Sells for Millions, SCI. AM. (Jan.
9, 2014), http://blogs.scientificamerican.com/symbiartic/how-plagiarized-art-sells-for-millions.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
141
voluntary initiatives to help fill some of the gaps left by the moral rights patchwork in the United
States.
Often, these voluntary initiatives are developed by companies looking to solve problems
with content management in their respective industries. Over the past decade, such initiatives
have become more common as creative industries grapple with maintaining effective means of
providing attribution and preventing unlicensed uses in the digital age. For instance, in 2007,
YouTube launched Content ID, one of the first large-scale content management systems.
794
The
Content ID system scans user-uploaded videos on YouTube against a database of files that have
been submitted by rights holders participating in the program.
795
Once a match has been
identified, rights holders can then choose to block the video, monetize the video by running ads
against it, or track the video’s viewership statistics.
796
Similar digital fingerprinting technologies
are being employed by other content platforms, typically in attempts to combat online piracy.
797
However, these content management technologies also help to combat misattribution, as well as
alerting authors to instances where their work is being used without attribution. Additionally, by
flagging unlicensed uses, these technologies can allow authors to assert their right of integrity by
preventing or disabling uses of their work that modify or distort their original expression.
Several companies have also created their own content management databases in order to
effectively match creative works to their author and/or rights holders. In 2016, SoundExchange
launched its International Standard Recording Code (“ISRC”) Search Site.
798
Unique ISRC’s are
used to identify sound recordings.
799
The ISRC Search Site provides users with access to
794
See Liz Gannes, YouTube Finally Launches Video ID Tool, GIGAOM (Oct. 15, 2007),
http://gigaom.com/2007/10/15/youtube-finally-launches-video-id-tool.
795
How Content ID works, YOUTUBE, http://support.google.com/youtube/answer/2797370.
796
Id.
797
Other platforms have developed content matching technology similar to YouTube’s. Scribd, a service that provides
access to literary works and allows users to self-publish, established BookID to filter uploaded works. The program
compares reference samples of works in their database with uploaded materials, and a matched upload is blocked. See
BookID, SCRIBD, https://www.scribd.com/copyright/bookid. Audible Magic created filtering technology that is licensed
to social media platforms. Audio and video files uploaded to the platform are matched against files registered with
Audible Magic’s database. If there is a match, the database relays to the platform ownership information and rules
specifying how the owner wants the file to be used. The service is used by SoundCloud, Facebook, Vimeo, Twitch, and
Dailymotion, among others. See Copyright Compliance Service: Compliance Automation for Media Sharing Platforms,
AUDIBLE MAGIC, http://www.audiblemagic.com/compliance-service/#how-it-works.
798
SoundExchange Launches Public Search Website with Access to Industry’s Best ISRC Data, SOUNDEXCHANGE (Mar. 8, 2016),
http://www.soundexchange.com/news/soundexchange-launches-public-search-website-with-access-to-industrys-best-
isrc-data.
799
See About: What is an ISRC?, INTL STANDARD RECORDING CODE, https://www.usisrc.org/about/index.html. ISRCs are
also used to identify music video recordings.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
142
SoundExchange’s sound recording metadata linked to the ISRC identifier.
800
While this data was
previously available through other sources, SoundExchange’s creation of a single comprehensive
online database allows more accessibility for artists, rights holders, digital music providers, and
listeners to accurately identify sound recordings and locate their related metadata.
Similarly, in addition to their “Content ID” management system, YouTube also recently
adopted the International Standard Name Identifier (“ISNI”) standard number for artists and
songwriters.
801
ISNI’s are unique numbers used to identify the different creators associated with a
work.
802
As a registration agency for ISNI, YouTube will request an identifier be assigned to all
creators, including both performers and authors, whose works are uploaded to the platform.
803
By adopting ISNI, YouTube is attempting to simplify the often complex process of associating a
work with its author or rights owner. The adoption of one standard identifier across the platform
will hopefully allow for more accurate attribution for creators.
Another voluntary initiative working towards ensuring proper attribution and
permissible uses for authors is the Picture Licensing Universal System (“PLUS”) Registry. The
PLUS Registry is run by the non-profit PLUS Coalition whose mission is to “facilitate the
communication and management of image rights.
804
The Registry currently assigns a unique
identifier to each creator, rights holder, distributor, licensor, and licensee, and in the future it will
allow users to assign unique identifiers to images and manage the information and metadata
associated with each image.
805
Importantly, the PLUS Registry also tracks and allows users to
update the rights information associated with an image, including current contact information for
related creators, rightsholders, and institutions.
806
This allows users to more easily track down
rights holders in order to gain permission for a use or to properly attribute a work.
Companies are also utilizing new technologies, such as blockchain, to develop content
management systems. Kodak has partnered with WENN Digital to launch KODAKOne, an
800
SoundExchange Launches Public Search Website with Access to Industry’s Best ISRC Data, SOUNDEXCHANGE (Mar. 8, 2016),
http://www.soundexchange.com/news/soundexchange-launches-public-search-website-with-access-to-industrys-best-
isrc-data.
801
YouTube Adopts ISNI ID for Artists & Songwriters, ISNI (Jan. 22, 2018), http://www.isni.org/content/youtube-adopts-
isni-id-artists-songwriters.
802
See International Standard Name Identifier (ISO 27729), ISNI, http://www.isni.org/. ISNIs can be used to identify
researchers, investors, writers, artists, visual creators, performers, producers, publisher, and aggregators, among others.
803
YouTube Adopts ISNI ID for Artists & Songwriters, ISNI (Jan. 22, 2018), http://www.isni.org/content/youtube-adopts-
isni-id-artists-songwriters.
804
About: PLUS Coalition, PLUS REGISTRY, https://www.plusregistry.org/cgi-bin/WebObjects/PlusDB.woa/2/wo/
OhbePL99GXyRRAWaE998dg/0.111.27.
805
Id.
806
See id.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
143
image rights management platform.
807
KODAKOne is based on an encrypted, digital ledger of
rights ownership, which photographers can use to manage rights information, receive payment
for licensing their works on the platform, and sell their work on a secure blockchain platform.
808
Similar to YouTube’s Content ID, KODAKOne also provides continual web crawling to monitor
uses of images registered in the KODAKOne system.
809
When an unlicensed use is detected,
KODAKOne will offer infringers an easy payment system to legitimize their uses.
810
Along with voluntary initiatives to develop content management and identification
systems, voluntary initiatives can also take the form of licensing agreements. For instance, Getty
Images and Google have announced the formation of a multiyear global licensing partnership.
811
While the agreement allows for Google to use Getty Imagescontent in its products and services,
the agreement also requires Google to modify its image search function to improve attribution of
works.
812
Other modifications Google will need to implement under this initiative include
making copyright disclaimers more prominent and removing “view image” links to the original
image URL.
813
While these types of voluntary initiatives may represent a step forward in filling the gaps
left by the existing moral rights landscape in the United States, such initiatives cannot offer a
comprehensive solution to the problems with attribution and integrity faced across creative
industries. These initiatives are limited in applicability to the specific industry or platform at
hand, and without formal legal requirements, enforceability is confined to a platform’s internal
policies. Moreover, content management technologies―both voluntary and not―raise concerns
about the role of automation in policing content platforms. Digital fingerprinting technologies
can be prone to error, and automated matching systems cannot take into account permissible uses
of copyrighted material such as fair use. The Office supports the on-going use and development
of voluntary initiatives, but recognizes the need for the law to supplement and support these
systems.
* * *
807
KODAK and WENN Digital Partner to Launch Major Blockchain Initiative and Cryptocurrency, KODAK (Jan. 9, 2018),
http://www.kodak.com/US/en/corp/Press_center/KODAK_and_WENN_Digital_Partner_to_Launch_Major_Blockchain
_Initiative_and_Cryptocurrency/default.htm.
808
Id.
809
Id. Note that, while YouTubes Content ID only crawls YouTube.com, the KODAKOne system crawls the entire web.
810
See id.
811
See Thuy Ong, Google Will Make Copyright Disclaimers More Prominent in Image Search, VERGE (Feb. 9, 2018),
http://www.theverge.com/2018/2/9/16994508/google-copyright-disclaimers-getty-images-search.
812
Id.
813
See id.
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
144
To briefly conclude, the Copyright Office believes that this Report demonstrates that the
U.S. moral rights patchwork continues to provide important protections, despite there being
room for improvement. The Copyright Act and other federal and state laws, including unfair
competition and misappropriation, combined with a robust private ordering landscape, provide
authors with a variety of means by which to protect and enforce their attribution and integrity
interests. In particular, the Copyright Office believes that some of the voluntary initiatives in this
space hold the potential to improve authors’ ability to be persistently identified with their works.
The Copyright Office believes that there is an important role for government to encourage and
foster such voluntary initiatives, and will continue to look for opportunities to do so.
However, should Congress wish to strengthen the U.S. moral rights framework, this
Study provides some guidelines for doing so, and the U.S. Copyright Office stands ready to assist
Congress with this task. Our recommendations for amending the Lanham Act and VARA to
better protect attribution and integrity interests, along with our suggestions regarding a new
section 1202A and advice for considering a federal right of publicity, should provide Congress
with several options for bolstering moral rights in the United States.
Specifically, the Office believes that the text of the Lanham Act and the reasoning of the
Dastar decision leave open claims for mis- or non-attribution of creative works in the following
cases: (i) claims for passing off or material distortions of a work; (ii) claims under § 43(a)(1)(B),
and (iii) claims for repackaging of expressive works in a way that misattributes them. However,
Congress may want to consider adopting a narrowly crafted amendment to section 43(a) of the
Lanham Act that would expand the unfair competition protections to include false
representations regarding authorship of expressive works.
Further, the Office has identified three targeted legislative improvements to the Visual
Artists Rights Act, codified in title 17 as section 106A, for consideration by Congress. The first
amendment would clarify that the exclusion for “commercial art” is limited to artworks both
created pursuant to a contract and intended for commercial use. The second amendment would
add language clarifying how courts should interpret the “recognized stature” requirement,
requiring courts to consult a broad range of sources. The third amendment would provide that
no joint author could waive another joint author’s moral rights under VARA without the written
consent of each affected author.
Regarding section 1202, Congress may want to consider adding a new cause of action as
section 1202A to title 17, which would offer a creator the ability to recover civil damages upon
proof that a defendant knowingly removed or altered copyright management information with
the intent to conceal an author’s attribution information. Such a dual intent standard would, in a
manner similar to the existing section 1202, protect against liability for innocent or good faith
removal of CMI, while giving creators a new tool to prevent deliberate efforts to conceal their
authorship of a work.
Finally, Congress may also wish to consider adoption of a federal right of publicity law as
a means to reduce the uncertainty and ambiguity created by the diversity of state right of
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
145
publicity laws. A federal right of publicity law, rather than preempting state laws, could serve as
a floor for minimum protections for an individual’s name, signature, image, and voice against
commercial exploitation during their lifetime.
authors, attribution, and integrity: examining moral rights in the united states
u.s. copyright office
appendix a PARTiciPAnTs in ThE symPOsium On
AuThORs, ATTRibuTiOn, And inTEgRiTy:
ExAmining mORAL RighTs in ThE
uniTEd sTATEs
APRiL 18, 2016
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
Appendix A
Participants in the
Authors, Attribution, and Integrity:
Examining Moral Rights in the United States Symposium
April 18, 2016
Complete Symposium agenda available at
https://www.copyright.gov/events/moralrights/agenda.pdf
1. Adler, Allan (Association of American Publishers)
2. Aistars, Sandra (George Mason University School of Law and Senior Scholar and
Director of Copyright Research and Policy at the Center for the Protection of Intellectual
Property)
3. Barblan, Matthew (Center for the Protection of Intellectual Property at the George Mason
University School of Law)
4. Besek, June M. (The Kernochan Center for Law, Media and the Arts at Columbia Law
School)
5. Bonneau, Sonya G. (Georgetown University Law Center)
6. Castle, Chris (Christian L. Castle, Attorneys)
7. Crabtree-Ireland, Duncan (SAG-AFTRA)
8. French, Alec (Thorsen French Advocacy, representing Directors Guild of America)
9. Gervais, Daniel J. (Vanderbilt Law School)
10. Gibbs, Melvin (Musician/composer)
11. Ginsburg, Jane C. (Morton L. Janklow Professor of Literary and Artistic Property Law at
Columbia University School of Law)
12. Levy, Paul Alan (Public Citizen Litigation Group)
13. Lowery, David (Songwriter/recording artist)
14. Marks, Steven M. (Recording Industry Association of America)
15. Martin, Scott (Paramount Pictures Corporation)
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
16. Miyashita, Yoko (Getty Images)
17. Mopsik, Eugene (American Photographic Artists)
18. O’Connor, Sean M. (University of Washington School of Law)
19. Osterreicher, Mickey H. (National Press Photographers Association)
20. Pierre-Louis, Stanley (Entertainment Software Association)
21. Robinson, Roxana (Authors Guild)
22. Schultz, Mark (Center for the Protection of Intellectual Property at the George Mason
University Law School)
23. Schwartz, Eric J. (Mitchell Silberberg & Knupp LLP)
24. Spelman, Katherine C. (Lane Powell PC)
25. Turow, Scott (Author)
26. Wolfe, Michael (Authors Alliance)
27. Wolff, Nancy E. (Cowan, DeBaets, Abrahams & Sheppard LLP)
28. Yu, Peter K. (Texas A&M University School of Law)
authors, attribution, and integrity: examining moral rights in the united states
u.s. copyright office
appendix B nOTicE Of inquiRy: sTudy On ThE
mORAL RighTs Of ATTRibuTiOn And
inTEgRiTy
7870
Federal Register / Vol. 82, No. 13 / Monday, January 23, 2017 / Notices
1
In this Notice, we use the general term ‘‘author’’
to include all creators, including visual artists and
performers.
2
See Sam Ricketson & Jane C. Ginsburg,
International Copyright and Neighboring Rights:
The Berne Convention and Beyond ¶¶ 10.03–.04, at
587–89 (2d ed. 2006).
3
See Miha
´
ly Ficsor, World Intellectual Property
Organization, Guide to the Copyright and Related
Rights Treaties Administered by WIPO and
Glossary of Copyright and Related Rights Terms ¶
BC-6bis, at 44 (2003).
4
Berne Convention for the Protection of Literary
and Artistic Works art. 6bis(1), Sept. 9, 1886, as
revised July 24, 1971, and as amended Sept. 28,
1979, S. Treaty Doc. No. 99–27 (1986).
SUMMARY
: In accordance with the
provisions of the Federal Advisory
Committee Act (FACA), and after
consultation with the General Services
Administration, the Secretary of Labor
is renewing the charter for the Maritime
Advisory Committee for Occupational
Safety and Health. The Committee will
better enable OSHA to perform its
duties under the Occupational Safety
and Health Act (the OSH Act) of 1970.
The Committee is diverse and balanced,
both in terms of segments of the
maritime industry represented (e.g.,
shipyard employment, longshoring, and
marine terminal industries), and in the
views and interests represented by the
members.
FOR FURTHER INFORMATION CONTACT
:
Amy Wangdahl, Director, Office of
Maritime and Agriculture, Directorate of
Standards and Guidance, U.S.
Department of Labor, Occupational
Safety and Health Administration,
Room N–3609, 200 Constitution Avenue
NW., Washington, DC 20210; telephone:
(202) 693–2066.
SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION
: The
Committee will advise OSHA on matters
relevant to the safety and health of
employees in the maritime industry.
This includes advice on maritime issues
that will result in more effective
enforcement, training, and outreach
programs, and streamlined regulatory
efforts. The maritime industry includes
shipyard employment, longshoring,
marine terminal, and other related
industries, e.g., commercial fishing and
shipbreaking. The Committee will
function solely as an advisory body in
compliance with the provisions of
FACA and OSHA’s regulations covering
advisory committees (29 CFR part 1912).
Authority and Signature
Jordan Barab, Acting Assistant
Secretary of Labor for Occupational
Safety and Health, U.S. Department of
Labor, 200 Constitution Avenue NW.,
Washington, DC 20210, authorized the
preparation of this notice pursuant to
Sections 6(b)(1), and 7(b) of the
Occupational Safety and Health Act of
1970 (29 U.S.C. 655(b)(1), 656(b)), the
Federal Advisory Committee Act (5
U.S.C. App. 2), Section 41 of the
Longshore and Harbor Workers’
Compensation Act (33 U.S.C. 941),
Secretary of Labor’s Order 1–2012 (77
FR 3912, Jan. 25, 2012), and 29 CFR part
1912.
Signed at Washington, DC, on January 13,
2017.
Jordan Barab,
Acting Assistant Secretary of Labor for
Occupational Safety and Health.
[FR Doc. 2017–01407 Filed 1–19–17; 8:45 am]
BILLING CODE 4510–26–P
LIBRARY OF CONGRESS
U.S. Copyright Office
[Docket No. 2017–2]
Study on the Moral Rights of
Attribution and Integrity
AGENCY
: U.S. Copyright Office, Library
of Congress.
ACTION
: Notice of inquiry.
SUMMARY
: The United States Copyright
Office is undertaking a public study to
assess the current state of U.S. law
recognizing and protecting moral rights
for authors, specifically the rights of
attribution and integrity. As part of this
study, the Office will review existing
law on the moral rights of attribution
and integrity, including provisions
found in title 17 of the U.S. Code as well
as other federal and state laws, and
whether any additional protection is
advisable in this area. To support this
effort and provide thorough assistance
to Congress, the Office is seeking public
input on a number of questions.
DATES
: Written comments must be
received no later than 11:59 p.m.
Eastern Time on March 9, 2017. Written
reply comments must be received no
later than 11:59 p.m. Eastern Time on
April 24, 2017. The Office may
announce one or more public meetings,
to take place after written comments are
received, by separate notice in the
future.
ADDRESSES
: For reasons of government
efficiency, the Copyright Office is using
the regulations.gov system for the
submission and posting of public
comments in this proceeding. All
comments must be submitted
electronically. Specific instructions for
submitting comments will be posted on
the Copyright Office Web site at https://
www.copyright.gov/policy/moralrights/
comment-submission/. To meet
accessibility standards, all comments
must be provided in a single file not to
exceed six megabytes (MB) in one of the
following formats: Portable Document
File (PDF) format containing searchable,
accessible text (not an image); Microsoft
Word; WordPerfect; Rich Text Format
(RTF); or ASCII text file format (not a
scanned document). All comments must
include the name of the submitter and
any organization the submitter
represents. The Office will post all
comments publicly in the form that they
are received. If electronic submission of
comments is not feasible due to lack of
access to a computer and/or the
Internet, please contact the Office, using
the contact information below, for
special instructions.
FOR FURTHER INFORMATION CONTACT
:
Kimberley Isbell, Senior Counsel for
Policy and International Affairs, by
email at [email protected] or by telephone at
202–707–8350; or Maria Strong, Deputy
Director for Policy and International
Affairs, by email at [email protected] or
by telephone at 202–707–8350.
SUPPLEMENTARY INFORMATION
:
I. Background
The term ‘‘moral rights’’ is taken from
the French phrase droit moral, and
generally refers to certain non-economic
rights that are considered personal to an
author.
1
Chief among these are the right
of an author to be credited as the author
of his or her work (the right of
attribution), and the right of an author
to prevent prejudicial distortions of the
work (the right of integrity). These rights
have a long history in international
copyright law, dating back to the turn of
the 20th century when several European
countries included provisions on moral
rights in their copyright laws.
2
A
provision on moral rights was first
adopted at the international level
through the Berne Convention for the
Protection of Literary and Artistic
Works (‘‘Berne Convention’’) during its
Rome revision in 1928.
3
The current
text of article 6bis(1) of the Berne
Convention states: ‘‘Independently of
the author’s economic rights, and even
after the transfer of the said rights, the
author shall have the right to claim
authorship of the work and to object to
any distortion, mutilation or other
modification of, or other derogatory
action in relation to, the said work,
which would be prejudicial to his honor
or reputation.’’
4
In contrast to the early adoption of
strong moral rights protections in
VerDate Sep<11>2014 19:02 Jan 19, 2017 Jkt 241001 PO 00000 Frm 00088 Fmt 4703 Sfmt 4703 E:\FR\FM\23JAN1.SGM 23JAN1
mstockstill on DSK3G9T082PROD with NOTICES
7871
Federal Register / Vol. 82, No. 13 / Monday, January 23, 2017 / Notices
5
Berne Convention Implementation Act of 1988,
Public Law 100–568, 102 Stat. 2853 (‘‘BCIA’’).
6
See discussion on the BCIA infra notes 15–23
and accompanying text.
7
See Moral Rights, Termination Rights, Resale
Royalty, and Copyright Term: Hearing Before the
Subcomm. on Courts, Intellectual Prop., & the
Internet of the H. Comm. on the Judiciary, 113th
Cong. (2014) (‘‘Moral Rights Hearing’’).
8
Moral Rights Hearing at 4.
9
Id.
10
Register’s Perspective on Copyright Review:
Hearing Before the H. Comm. on the Judiciary,
114th Cong. 34–35 (2015) (written statement of
Maria A. Pallante, Register of Copyrights and Dir.,
U.S. Copyright Office) (‘‘Register’s Perspective
Hearing’’).
11
Register’s Perspective Hearing at 49 (statement
of Rep. John Conyers, Ranking Member, H. Comm.
on the Judiciary).
12
As part of the consideration for possible
accession to the Berne Convention, the general
review of the 1909 Act took more than 20 years and
resulted in the 1976 Copyright Act.
13
See William Strauss, Study No. 4: The Moral
Right of the Author (1959), in Staff of S. Comm. on
the Judiciary, 86th Cong., Copyright Law Revision:
Studies Prepared for the Subcomm. on Patents,
Trademarks, and Copyrights of the Comm. on the
Judiciary, United States Senate: Studies 1–4, at 109
(Comm. Print 1960).
14
Strauss at 142. The report rejected the idea of
an ‘‘irreconcilable breach between European and
American concepts of protection of authors’
personal rights,’’ instead concluding that U.S. and
European courts generally arrived at the same
results in upholding the same rights or limitations
on those rights, just in different ways. Id. at 141–
42.
15
H.R. Rep. No. 100–609, at 33 (1988).
16
See S. Rep. No. 100–352, at 6 (1988); H.R. Rep.
No. 100–609, at 33 (1988).
17
See H.R. Rep. No. 100–609, at 37 (1988); S. Rep.
No. 100–352, at 10 (1988); see also Letter from Dr.
A
´
rpa
´
d Bogsch, Dir. Gen., World Intellectual Prop.
Org., to Irwin Karp, Esq. (June 16, 1987), reprinted
in Berne Convention Implementation Act of 1987:
Hearing on H.R. 1623 Before the Subcomm. on
Courts, Civil Liberties & the Admin. of Justice of the
H. Comm. on the Judiciary, 100th Cong. 213 (1987)
(‘‘In my view, it is not necessary for the United
States of America to enact statutory provisions on
moral rights in order to comply with Article 6bis
of the Berne Convention. The requirements under
this Article can be fulfilled not only by statutory
provisions in a copyright statute but also by
common law and other statutes.’’).
18
See S. Rep. No. 100–352, at 9–10 (1988); H.R.
Rep. No. 100–609, at 37–38 (1988); see also S. Exec.
Rep. No. 100–17, at 55 (1988) (to accompany S.
Treaty Doc. No. 99–27 (1986)) (statement of John K.
Uilkema on behalf of Am. Bar Ass’n before the S.
Comm. on Foreign Relations) (‘‘Whether greater or
lesser moral rights per se should be the subject of
legislative consideration in the United States is a
question that is separate and apart from the Berne
adherence compatibility question.’’).
19
See 15 U.S.C. 1125(a).
20
See 17 U.S.C. 106(2).
21
See 17 U.S.C. 115(a)(2).
22
See 17 U.S.C. 203.
23
See H.R. Rep. No. 100–609, at 34 (1988).
Contract law is particularly important for authors to
control aspects of their economic and moral rights.
For example, the collective bargaining agreements
that govern the creation of major motion pictures
often contain explicit requirements with regards to
attribution for actors, writers, directors, and other
guilds. Many copyright sectors that involve
numerous authors and participants in the creative
process, such as filmed entertainment, business and
entertainment software, music production, and
book publishing, also rely on both employment
agreements and the work-for-hire doctrine to
determine ownership issues, which in turn may
include elements related to attribution and
integrity.
24
Visual Artists Rights Act (VARA) of 1990,
Public Law 101–650, 104 Stat. 5128–29 (codified at
17 U.S.C. 106A). In the Report accompanying H.R.
2690 (Visual Artists Rights Act of 1990), the House
Judiciary provided background information on the
Berne Convention and moral rights, noting that the
Continued
Europe, the United States’ experience
with the concept of moral rights is more
recent. The United States did not adopt
the Berne Convention right away, only
joining the Convention in 1989.
5
At that
time, the United States elected not to
adopt broad moral rights provisions in
its copyright law, but instead relied on
a combination of various state and
federal statutes to comply with its Berne
obligations.
6
In July 2014, the Subcommittee on
Courts, Intellectual Property, and the
Internet of the House Judiciary
Committee held a hearing that focused
in part on moral rights for authors in the
United States as part of its broader
review of the nation’s copyright laws.
7
At that hearing, the Chairman of the
House Judiciary Committee,
Representative Bob Goodlatte, noted
that ‘‘we should consider whether
current law is sufficient to satisfy the
moral rights of our creators or, whether
something more explicit is required.’’
8
The Ranking Member of the
Subcommittee, Representative Jerrold
Nadler, also indicated his interest in a
further evaluation of the status of moral
rights in the United States, asking ‘‘how
our current laws are working and what,
if any, changes might be necessary and
appropriate.’’
9
Register of Copyrights
Maria Pallante recommended further
study of moral rights in her testimony
before Congress at the end of the two-
year copyright review hearings
process,
10
at which time the Ranking
Member of the House Judiciary
Committee requested that the Office
undertake this study.
11
As part of the
preparation for this study, the Copyright
Office co-hosted a day-long symposium
on moral rights in April 2016 in order
to hear views about current issues in
this area. The Office is now
commencing a formal study on moral
rights and soliciting public input.
A. Moral Rights in the United States
Prior to Implementation of the Berne
Convention in 1989
In the late 1950s, the Copyright Office
and Congress reviewed the issue of
moral rights as part of the larger,
comprehensive review of the copyright
laws leading to a general revision of the
1909 Copyright Act.
12
In support of the
review, William Strauss completed a
study for the Office entitled ‘‘The Moral
Right of the Author’’ in 1959.
13
The
report found that U.S. common law
principles, such as those governing tort
and contract actions, ‘‘afford an
adequate basis for protection of [moral]
rights’’ and can provide the same
protection given abroad under the
doctrine of moral rights.
14
Later, Congress considered the
specific question of ‘‘whether the
current law of the United States is
sufficient, or whether additional laws
are needed, to satisfy [Berne article
6bis’s] requirements.’’
15
The majority of
those who testified before Congress
argued against any change to U.S. law
concerning an artist’s right to control
attribution or any alteration to his
creation, stating that current U.S. law
was sufficient.
16
Indeed, WIPO Director
General Dr. A
´
rpa
´
d Bogsch explained to
Congress that the United States did not
need to make any changes to U.S. law
to meet the obligations of article 6bis.
17
Both the House and Senate Judiciary
Committees accepted this conclusion,
18
finding that U.S. law met the
requirements outlined in the Berne
Convention’s article 6bis based on the
existing patchwork of laws in the
United States, including:
Section 43(a) of the Lanham Act
relating to false designations of origin
and false descriptions, which could be
applied in some instances to attribution
of copyright-protected work.
19
The Copyright Act’s provisions
regarding protection of an author’s
exclusive rights in derivatives of his or
her works;
20
limits on a mechanical
licensee’s rights to arrange an author’s
musical composition;
21
and termination
of transfers and licenses.
22
State and local laws relating to
publicity, contractual violations, fraud
and misrepresentation, unfair
competition, defamation, and invasion
of privacy.
23
B. Subsequent Developments After the
U.S. Implementation of the Berne
Convention
Since the United States’
implementation of the Berne
Convention over 25 years ago, there
have been a number of legal and
technological developments affecting
the scope and protection of moral rights.
In 1990, Congress passed the Visual
Artists Rights Act (VARA), codified at
section 106A of the Copyright Act,
24
VerDate Sep<11>2014 19:02 Jan 19, 2017 Jkt 241001 PO 00000 Frm 00089 Fmt 4703 Sfmt 4703 E:\FR\FM\23JAN1.SGM 23JAN1
mstockstill on DSK3G9T082PROD with NOTICES
7872
Federal Register / Vol. 82, No. 13 / Monday, January 23, 2017 / Notices
Congress at the time of the BCIA agreed that
existing federal and state laws were sufficient to
comply with the Berne Convention requirements,
but that ‘‘adherence to the Berne Convention did
not end the debate about whether the United States
should adopt artists’ rights laws, and the
Subcommittee on Courts, Intellectual Property, and
the Administration of Justice continued its review
of the issue in [hearings held] in June.’’ H.R. Rep.
No. 101–514, at 8 (1990). Congress cited the
‘‘critical factual and legal differences in the way
visual arts and audiovisual works are created and
disseminated’’ in support of providing additional
protections for visual artists. H.R. Rep. No. 101–
514, at 9 (1990).
25
See 17 U.S.C. 101 (definition of a ‘‘work of
visual art’’); § 106A(a)(1) (providing for the right of
attribution); § 106A(a)(3) (providing for the right of
integrity). Section 604 of VARA, codified at 17
U.S.C. 113, created special rules for removal of
works visual art incorporated into buildings. Unlike
Berne’s article 6bis, VARA’s protections only apply
to works of visual art.
26
See H.R. Rep. No. 101–514, at 18 (1990). VARA
permits authors to waive these rights only if
expressly agreed in a written instrument signed by
the author. See 17 U.S.C. 106A(e).
27
See Visual Artists Rights Act of 1990, Public
Law 101–650, 608, 104 Stat. 5128, 5132 (1990). The
Copyright Office’s 1992 study concluded there was
insufficient economic and copyright policy
justification to establish droit de suite in the United
States. See U.S. Copyright Office, Droit De Suite:
The Artist’s Resale Royalty xv (1992), http://
www.copyright.gov/history/droit_de_suite.pdf. In
2013, the Copyright Office responded to a
congressional request and issued a second report
which examined the changes in law and practice
regarding resale royalties, in both the United States
and abroad, since the 1992 report. See U.S.
Copyright Office, Resale Royalties: An Updated
Analysis (2013), http://www.copyright.gov/docs/
resaleroyalty/usco-resaleroyalty.pdf.
28
See U. S. Copyright Office, Waiver of Moral
Rights in Visual Artworks: Final Report of the
Register of Copyrights xiii, 186 (1996), https://
www.copyright.gov/reports/waiver-moral-rights-
visual-artworks.pdf (‘‘Waiver of Moral Rights’’).
29
Waiver of Moral Rights at 183.
30
539 U.S. 23 (2003). Dastar involved the
distribution of an edited version of a 1949 broadcast
to which Twentieth Century Fox had owned the
copyright but which it failed to renew, placing the
work in the public domain. Dastar distributed
copies of the edited series listing Dastar and its
subsidiary as the producer and distributor of the
edited work, rather than Fox. Fox sued for reverse
passing off, claiming Dastar violated section 43(a)
of the Lanham Act’s prohibition against false
designation of origin.
31
Id. at 35.
32
Id.at 34.
33
See id. at 31–32.
34
Id. at 34 (internal quote marks omitted). The
Supreme Court left open the possibility of a
Lanham Act claim under section 43(a)(1)(B) where,
in advertising for a copied work of authorship, the
copier ‘‘misrepresents the nature, characteristics
[or] qualities’’ of the work. Id. at 38.
35
See, e.g., Kehoe Component Sales Inc. v. Best
Lighting Prods., Inc., 796 F.3d 576, 587 (6th Cir.
2015); Gen. Universal Sys., Inc. v. Lee, 379 F.3d
131, 148–49 (5th Cir. 2004); Zyla v. Wadsworth, 360
F.3d 243, 251–52 (1st Cir. 2004); Carroll v. Kahn,
No. 03–CV–0656, 2003 WL 22327299, at *5–6
(N.D.N.Y. Oct. 9, 2003).
36
See, e.g., Jane C. Ginsburg, Moral Rights in the
U.S.: Still in Need of a Guardian Ad Litem, 30
Cardozo Arts & Ent. L.J. 73, 83–87 (2012); Justin
Hughes, American Moral Rights and Fixing the
Dastar ‘‘Gap,’’ 2007 Utah L. Rev. 659 (2007). At
least one commenter has argued that not only do
section 43(a)(1)(B) claims survive Dastar, but so do
some section 43(a)(1)(A) claims. See Hughes at 692–
95.
37
See WIPO Copyright Treaty art. 1(4), Dec. 20,
1996, 2186 U.N.T.S. 121 (‘‘WCT’’); see also
Summary of the WIPO Copyright Treaty (WCT)
(1996), WIPO, http://www.wipo.int/treaties/en/ip/
wct/summary_wct.html.
38
See WIPO Performances and Phonograms
Treaty art. 5(1), Dec. 20, 1996, 2186 U.N.T.S. 203
(‘‘WPPT’’). Like the Berne Convention, the WPPT
provides that the duration of protection shall be at
least for the term of economic rights and shall be
governed by national law. WPPT arts. 5(2)–(3).
39
See WCT art. 12; WPPT art. 19. WCT article 12
and WPPT article 19 define rights management
information to include identification of the author
and owner and terms of use of the work or sound
recording.
40
See J. Carlos Ferna
´
dez-Molina & Eduardo Peis,
The Moral Rights of Authors in the Age of Digital
Information, 52 J. Am. Soc’y for Info. Sci. & Tech.
109, 112 (2001) (explaining how the WIPO Internet
Treaties’ rights management information provisions
fit within the treaties and also are useful in
protecting moral rights).
41
Digital Millennium Copyright Act (DMCA),
Public Law 105–304, 103 122 Stat. 2860, 2863–76
(1998) (codified as amended at 17 U.S.C. 1201–
1205). The WIPO Internet Treaties were submitted
to Congress for advice and consent the previous
year, and the Senate voted to approve the Treaties
shortly before passage of the DMCA. See S. Treaty
Doc. No. 105-17 (1997); 105 Cong. Rec. S12,972–73
(daily ed. Oct. 21, 1998).
which guarantees to authors of works of
‘‘visual arts’’ the right to claim or
disclaim authorship in a work and
limited rights to prevent distortion,
mutilation, or modification of a work.
25
In contrast to how moral rights were
often adopted elsewhere, with VARA,
Congress identified specific instances in
which the limited rights could be
waived.
26
As part of the legislation,
Congress also directed the Copyright
Office to conduct studies on the VARA
waiver provision and also on resale
royalties.
27
In its 1996 report on the waiver
provision, the Office concluded it could
not make an accurate assessment of the
impact of VARA’s waiver provisions
because artists and art consumers were
generally unaware of moral rights and
recommended that in order for artists to
take advantage of their legal rights
under VARA, further education about
moral rights in the United States would
be necessary.
28
The Office also made
observations about the implementation
of moral rights obligations in other
countries, finding that, of the laws
reviewed by the Office, only the moral
rights laws of the United Kingdom and
Canada contained express waiver
provisions.
29
The Supreme Court’s 2003 Decision in
Dastar
In 2003, some scholars began to
question the strength of the U.S.
patchwork of protection as a result of
the U.S. Supreme Court’s ruling in
Dastar Corp. v. Twentieth Century Fox
Film Corp. (‘‘Dastar’’), which foreclosed
some attribution claims under section
43(a) of the Lanham Act.
30
The Court
unanimously rejected an interpretation
of section 43(a) that would ‘‘require
attribution of uncopyrighted
materials.’’
31
Citing VARA, the Court
said that when Congress has wanted to
provide an attribution right under
copyright law, ‘‘it has done so with
much more specificity than the Lanham
Act’s ambiguous use of ‘origin.’ ’’
32
The
Court found that ‘‘origin of goods’’ is
most naturally understood as referring
to the source of a physical product, not
the person or entity that originated the
underlying creative content.
33
In a well-
known sentence, Justice Scalia, writing
for the Court, stated that permitting a
section 43(a) claim for such
misattribution ‘‘would create a species
of mutant copyright law that limits the
public’s ‘federal right to copy and to
use’ expired copyrights.’’
34
Some lower courts have read Dastar
as a broad prohibition on applying
federal trademark and unfair
competition laws in the realm of
copyright, regardless of whether the
copyrighted work remains under the
term of protection or has fallen into the
public domain.
35
In contrast, some
scholars have argued that the Court did
not write federal trademark and unfair
competition law out of the patchwork
entirely.
36
Rights Management Information and
Moral Rights for Performers
Since implementation of the Berne
Convention, the United States has
joined two additional international
treaties that address moral rights—the
WIPO Copyright Treaty (WCT) and the
WIPO Performances and Phonograms
Treaty (WPPT). The WCT incorporates
the substantive provisions of Berne,
including those of article 6bis.
37
Article
5 of the WPPT expands the obligations
of Contracting Parties to recognize the
moral rights of attribution and integrity
for performers with respect to their live
performances and performances fixed in
phonograms.
38
Furthermore, both the
WCT and the WPPT include new
obligations concerning rights
management information (RMI).
39
These
provisions protect new means of
identifying and protecting works while
also helping protect the rights of
attribution and integrity.
40
The United States implemented its
WCT and WPPT obligations via
enactment of the 1998 Digital
Millennium Copyright Act (‘‘DMCA’’),
41
and signed as a contracting party to both
treaties in 1999, three years before the
VerDate Sep<11>2014 19:02 Jan 19, 2017 Jkt 241001 PO 00000 Frm 00090 Fmt 4703 Sfmt 4703 E:\FR\FM\23JAN1.SGM 23JAN1
mstockstill on DSK3G9T082PROD with NOTICES
7873
Federal Register / Vol. 82, No. 13 / Monday, January 23, 2017 / Notices
42
See WCT Notification No. 10: WIPO Copyright
Treaty: Ratification by the United States of
America, WIPO (Sept. 14, 1999), available at http://
www.wipo.int/treaties/en/notifications/wct/treaty_
wct_10.html; WPPT Notification No. 8: WIPO
Performances and Phonograms Treaty: Ratification
by the United States of America, WIPO (Sept. 14,
1999), available at http://www.wipo.int/treaties/en/
notifications/wppt/treaty_wppt_8.html.
43
The other sections of chapter 12 include
sections 1203 and 1204, which set forth available
civil remedies and criminal sanctions for violation
of sections 1201 and 1202, and section 1205, which
explicitly carves out federal and state laws affecting
Internet privacy. 17 U.S.C. §§ 1203–1205.
44
H.R. Rep. No. 105-551, pt. 1, at 9 (1998).
45
The term ‘‘copyright management information’’
in the Copyright Act is seen as a synonymous term
for ‘‘rights management information’’ as used in the
WCT and WPPT. See S. Rep. No. 105–190, at 11
n.18 (1998) (‘‘Rights management information is
more commonly referred to in the U.S. as copyright
management information (CMI).’’).
46
Section 1202 makes it an offense to
‘‘intentionally remove or alter any copyright
management information,’’ which includes the
name of a work’s author. 17 U.S.C. §§ 1202(b)(1),
(c)(2). See Jane C. Ginsburg, Have Moral Rights
Come of (Digital) Age in the United States?, 19
Cardozo Arts & Ent. L.J. 9, 11 (2001) (‘‘The DMCA
may contain the seeds of a more general attribution
right. . . .’’); see also Greg Lastowka, Digital
Attribution: Copyright and the Right to Credit, 87
B.U. L. Rev. 41, 69–73 (2007).
47
See 17 U.S.C. 1202(a)–(b); see also Stevens v.
Corelogic, No. 14-cv-1158, 2016 WL 4371549, at *5,
6 (S.D. Cal. July 1, 2016) (‘‘Under § 1202(b)(1),
Plaintiffs must present evidence that [defendant]
intentionally removed or altered CMI. . . . ’’ and
‘‘[a]lthough Plaintiffs need not show actual
infringement, the fact that there was none is
relevant to Plaintiffs’ burden to show that
[defendant] had a reasonable ground to believe it
was likely to happen.’’).
48
Compare Murphy v. Millennium Radio Grp.
LLC, 650 F.3d 295, 305 (3d Cir. 2011) (rejecting
argument that the definition of CMI under section
1202 is ‘‘restricted to the context of ‘automated
copyright protection or management systems’’’),
and Williams v. Cavalli S.p.A., No. CV 14–06659–
AB (JEMx), 2015 WL 1247065, at *3 (C.D. Cal. Feb.
12, 2015) (holding that ‘‘[t]he plain meaning of
§ 1202 indicates that CMI can include non-digital
copyright information’’), and Leveyfilm, Inc. v. Fox
Sports Interactive Media, LLC, 999 F. Supp. 2d
1098, 1101–02 (N.D. Ill. 2014) (noting that the
majority of courts have rejected a requirement for
CMI to be digital under section 1202), and Fox v.
Hildebrand, No. CV 09–2085 DSF (VBKx), 2009 WL
1977996, at *3 (C.D. Cal. July 1, 2009) (‘‘The plain
language of the statute indicates that the DMCA
provision at issue is not limited to copyright notices
that are digitally placed on a work.’’), with Textile
Secrets Int’l Inc. v. Ya-Ya Brand Inc., 524 F. Supp.
2d 1184, 1201 (C.D. Cal. 2007) (‘‘[T]he Court []
cannot find that the provision was intended to
apply to circumstances that have no relation to the
Internet, electronic commerce, automated copyright
protections or management systems, public
registers, or other technological measures or
processes as contemplated in the DMCA as a
whole.’’), and IQ Grp., Ltd. v. Wiesner Publ’g, LLC,
409 F. Supp. 2d 587, 597 (D.N.J. 2006) (holding that
‘‘[t]o come within § 1202, the information removed
must function as a component of an automated
copyright protection or management system’’). The
majority position seems to accord with statements
from the legislative history. See, e.g., S. Rep. No.
105–190, at 16 (1998) (‘‘CMI need not be in digital
form, but CMI in digital form is expressly
included.’’).
49
See Waiver of Moral Rights at 53.
50
See Waiver of Moral Rights at 47–51, 53.
51
See Performances (Moral Rights, etc.)
Regulations 2006, SI 2006/18, arts. 5–6 (UK).
52
See Beijing Treaty on Audiovisual
Performances, June 24, 2012, 51 I.L.M. 1214 (2012)
(‘‘Beijing Treaty’’).
53
See Beijing Treaty art. 5 (‘‘Moral Rights’’), art.
16 (‘‘Obligations Concerning Rights Management
Information’’). Negotiations to conclude this treaty
took more than a decade, with a major point of
contention involving the provision on contractual
transfers. See Beijing Treaty art. 12; see also Press
Release, WIPO, WIPO Diplomatic Conference
Opens in Beijing to Conclude Treaty on Performers’
Rights in Audiovisual Productions, WIPO Press
Release PR/2012/713 (June 20, 2012), available at
http://www.wipo.int/pressroom/en/articles/2012/
article_0012.html (noting that as far back as the year
2000 negotiators could not agree on the issue
involving transfer of rights, and a breakthrough
compromise occurred in June 2011). This treaty has
not yet entered into force, and the United States has
not yet ratified it. The Obama Administration has
submitted a legislative package to Congress in
support of U.S. implementation of the Beijing
Treaty. See Letter from Michelle K. Lee, Under
Sec’y Commerce for Intellectual Prop. & Dir., U.S.
Patent & Trademark Office, to Joseph R. Biden,
President of the Senate (Feb. 26, 2016), available at
http://www.uspto.gov/sites/default/files/
documents/Beijing-treaty-package.pdf (treaty
implementation package for the Beijing Treaty on
Audiovisual Performances which includes a
transmittal letter, Beijing Treaty Implementation
Act of 2016, and Statement of Purpose and Need
and Sectional Analysis).
54
Founded in 2001, Creative Commons offers
various open source content licenses. Creative
Commons Project, Cover Pages (Aug. 22, 2008),
http://xml.coverpages.org/creativeCommons.html.
These types of licenses were held to be governed
by copyright law rather than contract law in
Continued
treaties entered into force.
42
Congress
added a new chapter 12 to title 17,
which contained two new provisions to
implement the treaties—section 1201,
which addresses technological
protection measures, and section 1202,
which protects rights management
information (called copyright
management information in U.S.
law)
43
—but did not make any
additional changes, finding that ‘‘[t]he
treaties do not require any change in the
substance of copyright rights or
exceptions in U.S. law.’’
44
Section 1202 includes prohibitions on
both providing false copyright
management information (‘‘CMI’’), and
removing or altering CMI.
45
In addition
to facilitating the administration of an
author’s or right holder’s economic
rights, the CMI protections afforded by
section 1202 may have implications for
authors’ protection and enforcement of
their moral rights.
46
However, two
aspects of section 1202 may limit its
usefulness as a mechanism to protect an
author’s moral rights. First, to be liable
under section 1202, a person who
removes copyright management
information must know both that they
have caused its removal and that such
removal is likely to cause others to
infringe the work.
47
Second, while most
courts recognize section 1202 as
protecting against any removal of
attribution from works, a minority of
courts have limited section 1202 to
protect only against removal of
attribution that is digital or part of an
‘‘automated copyright protection or
management system.’’
48
Recent International Developments
There have also been changes to the
landscape of moral rights protection
internationally since the U.S. acceded to
the Berne Convention in 1989. The
Copyright Office noted in its 1996 report
Waiver of Moral Rights in Visual
Artworks that, while statutory
recognition of the commonly recognized
moral rights—i.e., attribution and
integrity—is the norm internationally,
the strength of the moral rights laws
varied among Berne members, even
among those with the same basic legal
systems.
49
For example, at the time of
the Report the United Kingdom required
an author or her heirs, in some cases, to
assert the right of paternity and was
generally considered to have adopted
one of the more restrictive approaches
to implementing moral rights.
50
However, ten years later, in 2006, the
United Kingdom amended its moral
rights provision by extending to
qualifying performances the right to
attribution and the right to object to
derogatory treatment of a work.
51
The most recent international
development on CMI and moral rights
occurred four years ago at a Diplomatic
Conference in Beijing where WIPO and
its member states concluded a new
treaty on audiovisual performances.
52
Similar to the approach of the WPPT,
the Beijing Treaty on Audiovisual
Performances also contains provisions
on CMI and moral rights for audiovisual
performers.
53
Availability and Use of Licenses,
Contracts, and State Laws
Another part of the patchwork upon
which moral rights protection in the
United States relies is state contract law,
which allows authors to negotiate for
protection of their rights of attribution
and integrity through private ordering.
Since the United States’ accession to the
Berne Convention, a major change to
this area has been the emergence of
Creative Commons and its various
licenses that have simplified licensing
for all kinds of authors and users, large
and small. The CC license suites have
served to facilitate private ordering,
including for individual authors that
would not previously have been able to
afford the services of a lawyer to create
licenses to govern use of their works.
54
VerDate Sep<11>2014 19:02 Jan 19, 2017 Jkt 241001 PO 00000 Frm 00091 Fmt 4703 Sfmt 4703 E:\FR\FM\23JAN1.SGM 23JAN1
mstockstill on DSK3G9T082PROD with NOTICES
7874
Federal Register / Vol. 82, No. 13 / Monday, January 23, 2017 / Notices
Jacobsen v. Katzer, 535 F.3d 1373, 1380–83 (Fed.
Cir. 2008).
55
Creative Commons, https://
creativecommons.org/ (last visited Jan. 5, 2017)
(‘‘1.1 billion works and counting.’’).
56
For example, the PLUS Coalition has created an
image rights language to allow for global
communication of image rights information, and it
is currently developing an image registry that will
function as a hub connecting registries worldwide
and providing both literal and image-based
searches. PLUS Coalition, Comments Submitted in
Response to U.S. Copyright Office’s Apr. 24, 2015
Notice of Inquiry (Visual Works Study) at 1 (July
22, 2015) (noting that the Coalition’s unique image
rights language is meant to address the ‘‘challenges
[arising] from a present inability to ensure that any
person or machine encountering a visual work has
ready access to rights information sufficient to
allow the work to be identified, and sufficient to
facilitate an informed decision regarding the
display, reproduction and distribution of the
work’’).
57
Indeed, CMI is of particular interest to visual
artists who embed copyright information in their
works only to find it unlawfully stripped from
digital copies. This makes it difficult for potential
users to identify and contact the copyright owner
to obtain a license to use a work found online. See
Columbia University Libraries, Comments
Submitted in Response to U.S. Office’s Apr. 24,
2015 Notice of Inquiry (Visual Works Study) at 2
(July 23, 2015) (‘‘Rights metadata that includes
author attribution and source information would [ ]
facilitate subsequent re-uses of visual works while
at the same time support the interests of legitimate
copyright owners.’’).
58
The Office co-hosted this symposium with the
George Mason University School of Law and its
Center for the Protection of Intellectual Property.
Videos of the proceedings can be accessed on the
U.S. Copyright Office Web site event page at http://
www.copyright.gov/events/moralrights/. The official
transcript has been published by the George Mason
Journal of International Commercial Law. See
Symposium, Authors, Attribution, and Integrity:
Examining Moral Rights in the United States, 8 Geo.
Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 1 (2016), available at http://
www.georgemasonjicl.org/wp-content/uploads/
2016/08/Summer-Issue-2016.pdf.
59
See Session 4: The Importance of Moral Rights
to Authors, 8 Geo. Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 87, 90
(2016).
60
See Session 1: Overview of Moral Rights, 8 Geo.
Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 7 (2016).
61
See, e.g., Jane C. Ginsburg, Keynote Address,
The Most Moral of Rights: The Right to be
Recognized as the Author of One’s Work, 8 Geo.
Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 44, 48, 60–72 (2016); Session
4: The Importance of Moral Rights to Authors, 8
Geo. Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 87, 91–93 (2016)
(comments of Yoko Miyashita, Getty Images).
62
See Jane C. Ginsburg, Keynote Address: The
Most Moral of Rights: The Right to be Recognized
as the Author of One’s Work, 8 Geo. Mason J. Int’l
Com. L. 44, 72–81 (2016).
63
See, e.g., Session 2: The U.S. Perspective, 8
Geo. Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 26, 30–34 (2016)
(remarks of Duncan Crabtree-Ireland, SAG–AFTRA,
& Peter K. Yu, Tex. A&M Univ. Sch. of Law);
Session 6: New Ways to Disseminate Content and
the Impact on Moral Rights, 8 Geo. Mason J. Int’l
Com. L. 125, 139 (2016) (remarks of Stanley Pierre-
Louis, Entm’t Software Ass’n).
64
See Session 5: The Intersection of Moral Rights
and Other Laws, 8 Geo. Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 106,
119–20 (2016) (remarks of Paul Alan Levy, Pub.
Citizen).
65
See Session 2: The U.S. Perspective, 8 Geo.
Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 26, 27–29 (2016) (remarks of
Allan Adler, Ass’n of Am. Publishers (‘‘AAP’’))
(noting that the testimony of AAP at the 2014
hearing ‘‘raise[d] the threshold policy question of
‘whether to superimpose vague, subjective, and
wholly unpredictable new rights upon a
longstanding balanced and successful copyright
system.’’’).
66
See Session 2: The U.S. Perspective, 8 Geo.
Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 26, 30 (2016) (remarks of
Duncan Crabtree-Ireland, SAG–AFTRA).
67
See, e.g., Jane C. Ginsburg, Keynote Address,
The Most Moral of Rights: The Right to be
Recognized as the Author of One’s Work, 8 Geo.
Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 44, 53 (2016); Session 5: The
Intersection of Moral Rights and Other Laws, 8 Geo.
Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 106, 107–10, 113–14 (2016)
(remarks of Sonya G. Bonneau, Geo. Univ. Law Ctr.;
Eugene Mopsik, Am. Photographic Artists; & Nancy
E. Wolff, Cowan, DeBaets, Abrahams & Sheppard
LLP).
68
See Session 5: The Intersection of Moral Rights
and Other Laws, 8 Geo. Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 106,
110 (2016) (remarks of Eugene Mopsik, Am.
Photographic Artists).
69
See Session 4: The Importance of Moral Rights
to Authors, 8 Geo. Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 87, 92
(2016) (remarks of Yoko Miyashita, Getty Images).
70
Session 7: Where Do We Go From Here?, 8 Geo.
Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 142, 147 (2016) (remarks of
Mira Sundara Rajan, Univ. of Glasgow Sch. of Law).
71
See Session 1: Overview of Moral Rights, 8 Geo.
Mason J. Int’l Com. L. 7, 15 (2016) (remarks of
Daniel Gervais, Vand. Law Sch.).
Currently there are over one billion
works licensed under Creative
Commons licenses, most of which
require attribution of the author.
55
Changes in Technology to Deliver
Content and Identify Content
The evolution of technology in the
past few decades has also impacted the
availability of moral rights protections
for modern authors. Technology can
facilitate improved identification and
licensing of works with persistent
identifiers,
56
while, at the same time, it
can also make it easier to remove
attribution elements and distribute the
unattributed works widely.
57
II. Congressional Copyright Review and
This Study
As part of its effort to begin a dialogue
about moral rights protections in the
United States, the Copyright Office
organized a symposium entitled
‘‘Authors, Attribution, and Integrity:
Examining Moral Rights in the United
States,’’ which was held on April 18,
2016.
58
The symposium served as a
launching point for the issuance of this
Notice of Inquiry.
Seven sessions covered the historical
development of moral rights, the value
authors place on moral rights, the
various ways current law provides for
these rights, and new considerations for
the digital age. Participants, including
professional authors, artists, musicians,
and performers, discussed the
importance that copyright law generally,
and attribution specifically, plays in
supporting their creative process and
their livelihood.
59
Leading academics
provided an overview of the scope of
moral rights and how countries,
including the United States, approach
these concepts.
60
Many participants identified the right
of attribution as particularly important
to authors, both from a personal and
from an economic perspective. For
example, participants cited the role of
copyright management information for
purposes of attribution, and discussed
the perceived strengths and limitations
of section 1202.
61
Keynote speaker
Professor Jane Ginsburg posited ways to
strengthen the right of attribution.
62
Others discussed the possibilities of
using non-copyright laws post-Dastar,
63
as well as expressing concerns about
how potential moral rights-like causes
of action might interact with First
Amendment protections.
64
Some participants asserted that the
current patchwork of laws, particularly
the availability of contract law, the work
for hire doctrine, and collective
bargaining agreements (available in
some industry sectors), provides
sufficient protection for moral rights
concerns.
65
In contrast, several voices
criticized the limited scope of existing
law, ranging from upset that a right of
publicity is not a federal right
66
to
disappointment with VARA’s under-
inclusiveness and strict standards.
67
Discussion also addressed the role of
technology, both in creation and in
dissemination of authorized and
unauthorized works. For example, a
photographer noted the importance of
attribution that stays with images,
68
and
a photo company described the
technology they use to persistently
connect authorship information to
images.
69
Looking at what lessons might be
gleaned from the experiences of other
countries, one panelist commented that
there is ‘‘tremendous diversity in how
different countries have implemented
moral rights,’’
70
and another confirmed
that moral rights litigation constitutes
only a small percentage of the copyright
cases on those countries’ litigation
documents.
71
III. Subjects of Inquiry
The Copyright Office seeks public
comments addressing how existing law,
including provisions found in title 17 of
the U.S. Code as well as other federal
and state laws, affords authors with
effective protection of their rights,
equivalent to those of moral rights of
attribution and integrity.
The Office invites written comments
in particular on the subjects below. A
party choosing to respond to this Notice
of Inquiry need not address every
subject, but the Office requests that
responding parties clearly identify and
VerDate Sep<11>2014 19:02 Jan 19, 2017 Jkt 241001 PO 00000 Frm 00092 Fmt 4703 Sfmt 4703 E:\FR\FM\23JAN1.SGM 23JAN1
mstockstill on DSK3G9T082PROD with NOTICES
7875
Federal Register / Vol. 82, No. 13 / Monday, January 23, 2017 / Notices
separately address each numbered
subject for which a response is
submitted.
General Questions Regarding
Availability of Moral Rights in the
United States
1. Please comment on the means by
which the United States protects the
moral rights of authors, specifically the
rights of integrity and attribution.
Should additional moral rights
protection be considered? If so, what
specific changes should be considered
by Congress?
Title 17
2. How effective has section 106A
(VARA) been in promoting and
protecting the moral rights of authors of
visual works? What, if any, legislative
solutions to improve VARA might be
advisable?
3. How have section 1202’s provisions
on copyright management information
been used to support authors’ moral
rights? Should Congress consider
updates to section 1202 to strengthen
moral rights protections? If so, in what
ways?
4. Would stronger protections for
either the right of attribution or the right
of integrity implicate the First
Amendment? If so, how should they be
reconciled?
5. If a more explicit provision on
moral rights were to be added to the
Copyright Act, what exceptions or
limitations should be considered? What
limitations on remedies should be
considered?
Other Federal and State Laws
6. How has the Dastar decision
affected moral rights protections in the
United States? Should Congress
consider legislation to address the
impact of the Dastar decision on moral
rights protection? If so, how?
7. What impact has contract law and
collective bargaining had on an author’s
ability to enforce his or her moral
rights? How does the issue of waiver of
moral rights affect transactions and
other commercial, as well as non-
commercial, dealings?
Insights From Other Countries’
Implementation of Moral Rights
Obligations
8. How have foreign countries
protected the moral rights of authors,
including the rights of attribution and
integrity? How well would such an
approach to protecting moral rights
work in the U.S. context?
Technological Developments
9. How does, or could, technology be
used to address, facilitate, or resolve
challenges and problems faced by
authors who want to protect the
attribution and integrity of their works?
Other Issues
10. Are there any voluntary initiatives
that could be developed and taken by
interested parties in the private sector to
improve authors’ means to secure and
enforce their rights of attribution and
integrity? If so, how could the
government facilitate these initiatives?
11. Please identify any pertinent
issues not referenced above that the
Copyright Office should consider in
conducting its study
Dated: January 13, 2017.
Karyn Temple Claggett,
Acting Register of Copyrights and Director
of the U.S. Copyright Office.
[FR Doc. 2017–01294 Filed 1–19–17; 8:45 am]
BILLING CODE 1410–30–P
LIBRARY OF CONGRESS
Copyright Royalty Board
[Docket Nos. 17–0008–CRB–AU and 17–
0009–CRB–AU]
Notice of Intent To Audit
AGENCY
: Copyright Royalty Board,
Library of Congress.
ACTION
: Public notice.
SUMMARY
: The Copyright Royalty Judges
announce receipt of two notices of
intent to audit the 2013, 2014, and 2015
statements of account submitted by
broadcasters Cox Radio (Docket No. 17–
CRB–0009–AU) and Hubbard
Broadcasting (Docket No. 17–CRB–
0008–AU) concerning royalty payments
each made pursuant to two statutory
licenses.
FOR FURTHER INFORMATION CONTACT
:
Anita Brown, Program Specialist, by
telephone at (202) 707–7658 or by email
SUMMARY INFORMATION
: The Copyright
Act, title 17 of the United States Code,
grants to copyright owners of sound
recordings the exclusive right to
publicly perform sound recordings by
means of certain digital audio
transmissions, subject to limitations.
Specifically, the right is limited by the
statutory license in section 114 which
allows nonexempt noninteractive digital
subscription services, eligible
nonsubscription services, and
preexisting satellite digital audio radio
services to perform publicly sound
recordings by means of digital audio
transmissions. 17 U.S.C. 114(f). In
addition, a statutory license in section
112 allows a service to make necessary
ephemeral reproductions to facilitate
the digital transmission of the sound
recording. 17 U.S.C. 112(e).
Licensees may operate under these
licenses provided they pay the royalty
fees and comply with the terms set by
the Copyright Royalty Judges. The rates
and terms for the section 112 and 114
licenses are set forth in 37 CFR parts
380 and 382–84.
As part of the terms set for these
licenses, the Judges designated
SoundExchange, Inc., as the Collective,
i.e., the organization charged with
collecting the royalty payments and
statements of account submitted by
eligible nonsubscription services such
as broadcasters and with distributing
the royalties to copyright owners and
performers entitled to receive them. See
37 CFR 380.33(b)(1).
As the designated Collective,
SoundExchange may, once during a
calendar year, conduct an audit of a
licensee for any or all of the prior three
years in order to verify royalty
payments. SoundExchange must first
file with the Judges a notice of intent to
audit a licensee and deliver the notice
to the licensee. See 37 CFR 380.35.
On December 22, 2016,
SoundExchange filed with the Judges
notices of intent to audit licensee
broadcasters Cox Radio, Inc., and
Hubbard Broadcasting, Inc., for 2013–
15. The Judges must publish notice in
the Federal Register within 30 days of
receipt of a notice announcing the
Collective’s intent to conduct an audit.
See 37 CFR 380.35(c). Today’s notice
fulfills this requirement with respect to
SoundExchange’s December 22, 2016
notices of intent to audit.
Dated: January 13, 2017.
Suzanne M. Barnett,
Chief Copyright Royalty Judge.
[FR Doc. 2017–01319 Filed 1–19–17; 8:45 am]
BILLING CODE 1410–72–P
LIBRARY OF CONGRESS
Copyright Royalty Board
[Docket No. 17–0004–CRB–AU, 17–0007–
CRB–AU, and 17–0010–CRB–AU]
Notice of Intent To Audit
AGENCY
: Copyright Royalty Board,
Library of Congress.
ACTION
: Public notice.
SUMMARY
: The Copyright Royalty Judges
announce receipt of three notices of
intent to audit the 2013, 2014, and 2015
statements of account submitted by
commercial webcasters Radionomy
(Docket No. 17–CRB–0004–AU), IMVU,
Inc. (Docket No. 17–CRB–0007–AU),
VerDate Sep<11>2014 19:02 Jan 19, 2017 Jkt 241001 PO 00000 Frm 00093 Fmt 4703 Sfmt 4703 E:\FR\FM\23JAN1.SGM 23JAN1
mstockstill on DSK3G9T082PROD with NOTICES
authors, attribution, and integrity: examining moral rights in the united states
u.s. copyright office
appendix c PARTiEs whO submiTTEd cOmmEnTs
in REsPOnsE TO ThE jAnuARy 23, 2017
nOTicE Of inquiRy
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
Appendix C
Parties Who Submitted Comments
in Response to the January 23, 2017 Notice of Inquiry
Initial Commenters
1. American Association of Law Libraries (“AALL”)
2. American Society of Journalists & Authors (“ASJA”)
3. Art Law Committee of the New York City Bar (“NY Bar Association”)
4. Artists Rights Society (“ARS”)
5. Association of American Publishers (“AAP”)
6. Authors Alliance
7. Authors Guild, Inc. (“Authors Guild”)
8. B., Courtney
9. Buccafusco, Christopher and Sprigman, Christopher (“Buccafusco-Sprigman”)
10. Claiborne, Omer
11. Clarke, Glenn
12. Coalition of Visual Artists (“CVA”)
13. Computer & Communications Industry Association (“CCIA”)
14. Creators’ Rights Alliance (“CRA”)
15. Directors Guild of America, Inc. and Writers Guild of America, West
(“DGA/WAGAW”)
16. Electronic Frontier Foundation (“EFF”)
17. Folkens, Pieter
18. Foss, Lance 1
19. Foss, Lance 2
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
20. Gonzalez, Israel
21. Gordon, Wendy J
22. International Federation of Journalists (“IFJ”)
23. International Trademark Association (“INTA”)
24. Keller, Jenny
25. Kelley, Chapman
26. Kernochan Center for Law, Media and the Arts, Columbia Law School
(“Kernochan Center”)
27. Kojreau, AC
28. Kwall, Roberta
29. Lee, Becki
30. Library Copyright Alliance (“LCA”)
31. Liimatainen-Peterson, Donna
32. McCutcheon, Jani
33. Motion Picture Association of America, Inc. (“MPAA”)
34. Music Creators North America (“Music Creators”)
35. National Writers Union and Science Fiction and Fantasy Writers of America
(“NWU-SFWA”)
36. Nimpagaritse, Awen
37. Odenkirk, Sarah Conley
38. Organization for Transformative Works (“OTW”)
39. Pilch, Janice
40. Ponte, Lucille M.
41. Public Knowledge (“PK”)
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
42. Screen Actors Guild-American Federation of Television and Radio Artists
(“SAG-AFTRA”)
43. Schneider, Maria
44. Society of Composers & Lyricists (“SCL”)
45. Van Norman, John
46. Weiss, Maximilian
Reply Commenters
1. American Association of Independent Music (“A2IM”)
2. Authors Guild, Inc. (“Authors Guild”)
3. Broadcast Music, Inc. (“BMI”)
4. Center for Democracy & Technology (“CDT”)
5. Creators’ Rights Alliance (“CRA”)
6. Future of Music Coalition (“FMC”)
7. Kernochan Center for Law, Media and the Arts, Columbia Law School
(“Kernochan Center”)
8. Kubota, Zandra
9. Motion Picture Association of America, Inc. (“MPAA”)
10. National Music Publishers Association, Inc. (“NMPA”)
11. National Writers Union (“NWU”)
12. Organization for Transformative Works (“OTW”)
13. Recording Academy
14. Recording Industry Association of America, Inc. (“RIAA”)
15. Sundara Rajan, Mira T.
16. University of Michigan Library
authors, attribution, and integrity: examining moral rights in the united states
u.s. copyright office
appendix d RighT Of PubLiciTy chART
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
Legend: ü Yes ¢ Unclear/Mixed
State Right of Publicity Statutes
1
State
Statute
Covers
Post-Mortem
(Years)
Registration System
Famous / Commercial
Value Required
Common Law Rights
Recognized
Name
Image
Signature
Voice
Likeness
Other
2
Alabama
ALA. CODE
§ 6-5-770 et seq.
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(55)
¢
3
Unclear
4
Alaska
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
5
Arizona
6
ARIZ. REV. STAT. §
12-761
ü
ü
ü
7
Right of Publicity
8
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
9
Arkansas
ARK. CODE
§ 4-75-1101 et
seq.
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(50)
Unclear
10
California
CAL. CIV. CODE §
3344
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
Right of Publicity
11
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
12
California
CAL. CIV. CODE §
3344.1
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(70)
ü
ü
13
See above
Colorado
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
14
Connecticut
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
15
Delaware
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
16
District of
Columbia
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
17
Florida
FLA. STAT. § 540.08
ü
ü
ü
ü
(40)
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
18
Georgia
N/A
Right of Publicity
19
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
20
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
Legend: ü Yes ¢ Unclear/Mixed
State
Statute
Covers
Post-Mortem
(Years)
Registration System
Famous / Commercial
Value Required
Common Law Rights
Recognized
Name
Image
Signature
Voice
Likeness
Other
2
Hawaii
21
HAW. REV. STAT.
§ 482P-1 et seq.
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(70)
ü
22
¢
23
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
24
Idaho
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
25
Illinois
765 ILL. COMP. STAT.
§ 1075/1 et seq.
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(50)
N/A
26
Indiana
IND. CODE
§ 32-36-1-1 et seq.
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(100)
ü
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
28
Iowa
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
29
Kansas
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
30
Kentucky
KY. REV. STAT. §
391.170
ü
ü
ü
(50)
ü
31
Unclear
32
Louisiana
33
LA. REV. STAT. §
14:102.21
ü
ü
ü
34
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
35
Maine
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
36
Maryland
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
37
Massachusetts
MASS. GEN. LAWS
ch. 214, § 3A
ü
ü
¢
38
¢
39
Unclear
40
Michigan
N/A
Right of Publicity
41
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
42
Minnesota
43
N/A
Right of Publicity
44
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
45
Mississippi
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
46
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
Legend: ü Yes ¢ Unclear/Mixed
State
Statute
Covers
Post-Mortem
(Years)
Registration System
Famous / Commercial
Value Required
Common Law Rights
Recognized
Name
Image
Signature
Voice
Likeness
Other
2
Missouri
N/A
Right of Publicity
47
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
48
Montana
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
49
Nebraska
50
NEB. REV. STAT.
§ 20-201 et seq.
ü
ü
ü
ü
51
N/A
52
Nevada
NEV. REV. STAT.
§ 597.770 et seq.
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(50)
ü
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
53
New
Hampshire
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
54
New Jersey
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
55
New Mexico
N/A
Right of Publicity
56
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
57
New York
58
N.Y. CIV. RIGHTS LAW
§ 51
59
ü
ü
ü
N/A
60
North Carolina
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
61
North Dakota
N/A
Unclear
62
Ohio
OHIO REV. CODE
§ 2741.01 et seq.
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(60)
ü
63
Right of Publicity
64
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
65
Oklahoma
66
OKLA. STAT.
tit. 12 § 1448
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(100)
ü
ü
67
Unclear
Oklahoma
OKLA. STAT
tit. 12 § 1449
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
See above
Oregon
N/A
Right of Publicity
68
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
69
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
Legend: ü Yes ¢ Unclear/Mixed
State
Statute
Covers
Post-Mortem
(Years)
Registration System
Famous / Commercial
Value Required
Common Law Rights
Recognized
Name
Image
Signature
Voice
Likeness
Other
2
Pennsylvania
42 PA. CONS. STAT. §
8316
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(30)
ü
Unclear
Rhode Island
9 R.I. GEN. LAWS §
9-1-28
ü
ü
N/A
70
Rhode Island
9 R.I. GEN. LAWS
§ 9-1-28.1
71
ü
ü
ü
N/A
72
South Carolina
N/A
Right of Publicity
73
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
74
South Dakota
S.D. CODIFIED LAWS
§ 21-64-1 et seq.
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(70)
ü
ü
N/A
Tennessee
TENN. CODE
§ 47-25-1101 et
seq.
ü
ü
ü
75
Right of Publicity
76
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
77
Texas
TEX. PROP. CODE
§ 26.001 et seq.
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(50)
ü
ü
78
Right of Publicity
79
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
80
Utah
81
UTAH CODE
§ 45-3-1 et seq.
ü
ü
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
82
Vermont
N/A
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
83
Virginia
84
VA. CODE § 8.01-40
ü
ü
ü
(20)
N/A
85
Washington
WASH. REV. CODE
§ 63.60.010 et
seq.
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
ü
(10 /
75)
Right of Publicity
86
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
87
West Virginia
N/A
Right of Publicity
88
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
89
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
Legend: ü Yes ¢ Unclear/Mixed
State
Statute
Covers
Post-Mortem
(Years)
Registration System
Famous / Commercial
Value Required
Common Law Rights
Recognized
Name
Image
Signature
Voice
Likeness
Other
2
Wisconsin
WIS. STAT. §
995.50
90
ü
ü
Right of Publicity
91
Right of Privacy
Misappropriation
92
Wyoming
N/A
Unclear
93
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
Endnotes
1
"Much"of"the"information"herein"is"adapted"from"Prof."Jennifer"E."Rothman’s"work.""See#Jennifer"E."Rothman,"Rothman’s#
Roadmap#to#the#Right#of#Publicity,"https://www.rightofpublicityroadmap.com"(last"visited"Mar."4,"2019).""
2
"Includes"such"things"as"gestures,"mannerisms,"distinctiv e"appearance,"etc.""
3
"While"nothing"in"the"statute"requires"the"plaintiff"to"be"famous"or"to"have"commercially"exploited"their"name"or"image,"case"
law"from"before"adoption"of"th e"statute"required"a"demonstration"of"a"“unique"quality"o r"value"in"the"[plaintiff’s]"likeness[]"."."."
that"would"result"in"commercial"profit"to"[the"defendant].”""Sc hifano#v.#Greene#Ct y.#Greyhound#Park,#Inc.,"624"So."2d"178,"181"
(Ala."1993)."
4
"Alabama"recognized"a"right"of"privacy"and"the"tort"of "misappropriation"prior"to"passage"of"the"statutory"right"of"publicity.""
There"has"not"yet"been"any"case"law"on"whether"these"continue"to"be"available"in"light"of"the"statutory"regime.""See# Jennifer"E."
Rothman,"Rothman’s#Roadmap#to#the#Right#of#Publicity,"https://www.rightofpublicityroadmap.com/law/alabama"(last"visited"
Mar."4,"2019).#"
5
"At"least"one"federal"district"court"has"held"that"Alaska"would"likely"recognize"this"tort.""Se e#Doyle#v.#Harper#Collin s#Publishers,#
Inc.,"No."3:05-cv-0300,"2006"WL"8438639,"at"*3"(D."Alaska"May"31,"2006)"(order"on"motion"to"dismiss)."""
6
"Arizona’s"statutory"right"of"publicity"law"protects"only"soldiers.""
7
"Enforceable"down"to"grandchildren."
8
#See,#e.g.,#In#re#Estate#of# Reynolds,"327"P.3d"213,"216"(Ariz."Ct."App.""2014).""
9
"See#Reed#v.#Real#Detective#Pub.#Co.,"162"P.2d"133,"13738"(Ariz."1945)"(adopting"Restatement"version"of"right"of"privacy)."
10
"Prior"to"passage"of"the"statute,"Arkansas"recognized"the"tort"of"misappropriation"under"its"right"of"privacy"doctrine.""See,#e.g.,#
Olan#Mills,#Inc.#of#Tex.#v.#Dodd,"353"S.W.2d"22,"24"(Ark."1962);"Stanley#v.#Gen.#Media"Commc’ns,#Inc.,"149"F."Supp."2d"701,"706"
(W.D."Ark."2001).""The"statute"is"silent"on"whether"or"not"such"common"law"causes"of"action"are"preempted,"and"there"is"not"
yet"any"case"law"on" the" matter.""
11
"See,#e.g.,#White#v.#Samsung#Elecs.#Am.,#Inc.,"971"F.2d"1395,"139799"(9th"Cir."1992)."
12
"See#KNB#Enters.#v.#Matthews,"78"Cal."App."4th"362,"36667"(Cal."Ct."App."2000)"(noting"that"Section"3344"“complements"the"
common"law"tort"of"appropriation”)."
13
"Requires"that"the"personality’s"name,"voice,"signature,"photograph,"or"likeness"have"commercial"value"as"measured"at"the"
time"of "his"or"her"death,"regardless"of"exploitation"during"life."
14
"See,#e.g.,#Joe#Dicke rson#&#A ssocs.,#LLC#v.#Dittmar,"34"P.3d"995,"1001"(Colo."2001)."""
15
#See#Goodrich#v.#Waterbury#Republican-Am.,#Inc.,"448"A.2d"1317,"1328"(Conn."1982).""One"federal"court"has"indicated"that"
Connecticut" might"recognize"a"common"law"right"of"publicity,"as "well.""See#Jim#Henson#Prods.,#Inc.#v.#John#T.#Brad y#&#Assocs.,"867"
F."Supp."175,"189" (S.D.N.Y."1994)."
16
"See#Barbieri#v.#News-Journal#Co.,"189"A.2d"773,"774"(Del."1963)."""
17
"See#Vassiliades#v.#Garfinckel’s,#B rooks#Bro s.,"492"A.2d"580,"587"(D.C."1985)."""
18
"The"statute"expressly"states"that"it"does"not"preempt"claims"under"the"common"law"right"of"privacy.""FLA."STAT."§"540.08(7)"
(1967).""Florida"has"long"recognized"the"tort"of"misappropriation"under"the"right"of"privacy.""See,#e.g.,#Cason#v.#Baskin,"20"So."2d"
243"(Fla."1944)."
19
"See#Martin#Luther#King,#Jr.,#Ctr.#for#Soc.#Change,#Inc.#v.#Am.#Heritage#Prods.,#Inc.,"296"S.E.2d"697,"70003"(Ga."1982).""
20
"See#Bullard#v.#MRA#Holding,#LLC,"740"S.E.2d"622,"62526"(Ga."2013)."
21
"Claims"to"apply"to" all"individuals,"regardless"of"whether"or"not"they"ever"resided"o r"were"dom iciled"in"Hawaii.""See#HAW."REV."
STAT."§"482P-2"(2009)."
22
"Registration"of"a"license"or"assignment"interest"can"rebut"presumption"that"a"living"person"has"the"right"to"license"or"assign"
their"publicity"rights.""See#HAW."REV."STAT."§"482P-8"(2009)."
23
"Hawaii"provides"broader"protection"for"“person alities”"than"for"average"individuals.""A"claim"for"violation"of"a"“deceased"
personality”"must"have"demonstrated"commercial"value"at"the"time"of "death.""See#HAW."REV."STAT."§"482P-1"(2009)."
24
"See#Fergerstrom#v.#Hawaiian#Ocean#View#Estates,"441"P.2d"141,"143"(Haw."1968)."
25
"See,#e.g.,#Hoskins#v.#Howa rd,"971"P.2d"1135,"1140"(Ida ho"1998)."
26
"Illinois"previously"recognized"a"common"law"right"of"privacymisappropriation.""The"statutory"language"explicitly"
preempts"a"common"law"right"of"publicity,"and"several"appellate"courts"have"held"that"such"preemption"likely"extends"to"the"
common"law"right"of"privacymisappropriation.""See,#e.g .,"Trannel#v.#Praire#Ridge#Media,#Inc.,"987"N.E.2d"923,"928"(Ill."App."Ct."
2013);"Blair#v.#Nev.#Landing#P’ship,"859"N.E.2d"1188,"1192"(Ill."App."Ct."2006);"Maremont#v.#Susan#Fredman#Design#Grp.,#Ltd.,"
772"F."Supp.2d"967,"972"(N.D."Ill."2011).""But#see#Petty#v.#Chrysler #Corp.,"799"N.E.2d"432,"44142"(Ill."App."Ct."2003)."
27
"Indian a’s"first"right"of"publicity"law"was"passed"in"1994"and"codified"at"IND."CODE"§"32-13-1-8.""In"2002,"Indiana"repealed"the"
statue"and"recodified"it"at"IND."CODE"§"32-36-1-1"et#seq.""See"2002"Ind."Acts"595,"672."
28
"See,#e.g.,#Felsher#v.#Univ.#of#Evansville,"755"N.E.2d"589,"593"(Ind."2001)."
29
"See,#e.g.,#Bremmer#v.#Journal-Tribune#Pub.#Co.,"76"N.W.2d"762,"765"(Iowa"1956).""At"least"one"federal"court"has"held"that"Iowa"
would"likely"recog nize"a"common"law"right"of"publicity.""See#Sharp-Richardson#v.#Boyds#Collection,#Ltd.,"No."C"96-0334,"1999"WL"
33656875,"at"*15"(N.D."Iowa"Sept."30,"1999)."
30
"See#Kunz#v.#Allen,"172"P."532"(Kan."1918)."
31
"The"Kentucky"statute"requires"that"the"person"whose"right"of"publicity"is"being"asserted"be"a"“public"figure."
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
32
"The"Kentucky"Supreme"Court"has"implied"that"the"common"law"right"of"publicity"and"common"law"right"of"privacy
misappropriation"may"not"be"preempted"by"the"statute.""See# Montgomery#v.#Montgomery,"60"S.W.3d"524"(Ky."2001).""One"
federal"court"has"found"that"common"law"rights"remain.""See#Thornton#v.#W.#&#S.#Fin.#Grp.#Beneflex#Plan,"797"F."Supp."2d"796,"
813-14"(W.D."Ky."2011)."
33
"Louisiana’s"statutory"right"of"publicity"p rotects"only"soldiers.""A"bill"to"provide"a"post-mortem"right"of"publicity"for"
commercial"use s"of"an"individual’s"name,"voice,"signature,"photograph"or"likeness"was"introduced"in"the"Louisiana"legislature"
in"2017,"but"did"not"pass"both"houses.""Se e#Allen"Toussaint"Legacy"Act,"H.B."415,"2017"Reg."Sess."(La."2017).""
34
"The"Louisiana"statute"is"silent"as"to"duration."
35
"See,#e.g.,#Tatum#v.#New#Or leans#Aviation#Bd.,"102"So."3d"144"(La."Ct."App."2012)."
36
"See,#e.g.,#Nelson#v.#Me.#Times,"373"A.2d"1221,"1223"(Me."1977)."
37
"See#Carr#v.#Watkins,"177"A.2d"841"(Md."1962) .""Several"Maryland"cases"reject"claims"for"violation"of"the"right"of"pri vacy"when"
the"pla i ntiff"cannot"demonstrate"possession"of"a"commercially"va luable"identity.""See,#e.g.,#Lawrence#v.#A.S.#Abell#Co.,"475"A.2d"
448,"453"(Md."1984)."
38
"A"bill"was"introduced"most"recently"in"2014"to"add"explicit"post-mortem"rights.""See#S."2022,"188th"General"Court"(Mass."
2014)."
39
"While"nothing"in"the"statute"requires"the"plaintiff"to"be"famous"or"to"have"commercially"exploited"their"name"or"image,"the"
Massachusetts"Supreme"Judicial"Court"has"read"such"a"requirement"into"the"statute.""See#Tropeano#v.#Atl.#Monthly,#Co.,"400"
N.E.2d,"847,"850"(Mass."1980)."
40
"No"court"has"ruled"on"whether"Massachusetts"recognizes"either"a"common"law"right"of"publicity"nor"a"common"law"right"of"
privacymisappropriation"in"addition"to"the"statutory"protections."
41
"See#Rosa#and#Raymond#Parks#Inst.#for#Self-Dev.#v.#Target#Corp.,"812"F.3d"824,"830"(11th"Cir."2016).""
42
"See#Pallas#v.#Crowley-Milner#&#Co.,"54"N.W.2d"595,"596"(Mich."1952)."
43
"Bills"were"introduced"in"the"89th"Legisl ature"after"the"passin g" of"Princ e"in"2016,"but"did"no t"clear"either"cha mber"o f"the"
legislature.""See#Personal"Rights"in"Names"Can"Endure"(PRINCE)"Act,"SF"3609,"89th"Leg."(Minn."2016)."
44
"See#Ventura#v.#Titan#Sports,#Inc.,"65"F.3d"725,"730"(8th"Cir."1995)"(“We"believe"that"the"Minnesota"Supreme"Court"would"
recognize"the"tort"of"violation"of"publicity"rights.”)."
45
"See#Lake#v.#Wal-Mart#Stores,#Inc.,"582"N.W.2d"231,"23335"(Minn."1998)."
46
"See#Candebat#v.#Flan agan,"487"So."2d"207,"209"(Miss."1986)."
47
"See,#e.g.,#Doe#v.#TCI#Cablevision,"110"S.W.3d"363,"368"(Mo."2003)."
48
"See#id."at"368."
49
"See#Welsh#v.#Pritchard,"241"P.2d"816,"819"(Mont."1952).""
50
"Note"that"Nebraska’s"statute"is"styled"as"a"statutory"right"of"privacy,"which"includ es"a"cause"of"action"for"exploitation"of"a"
person"for"advertising"or"commercial"purpos es."
51
"Only"the"right"of"publicity"( e xploitation"of"a"person’s"name"or"likeness)"is"posthumous.""The "statute"does"not"specify"the "
duration"of"the"posthumous"right,"but"states"that"the"right"can"be"asserted"by"the"deceased’s"“surviving"spouse,"if"any,"or"by"the"
personal"representative.”""See#NEB."REV."STAT.§"20-208"(1989).""
52
"Prior"to"enactment"of"the"statute,"Nebraska"recogniz ed"neither"a"co m mon"law"right"of"publicity"nor"a"common"law"right"of"
privacymisappropriation.""See,#e.g.,#Carson#v.#Nat'l#Bank#of#Commerce#Trust#&#Sav.,"501"F.2d"1082,"1084"(8th"Cir."1974);"
Schoneweis#v.#Dando,"435"N.W.2d"666,"669"(Neb."1989)."
53
"See#PETA#v.#Bobby#Berosini,#Ltd.,"895"P.2d"1269,"1283"(Nev."1995),"overruled#on#other#grounds#by#City#of#Las#Vegas#Downtown#
Redevelopment#Agency# v.#Hecht,#940"P.2d"134,"138"(Nev."1997).#
54
"See,#e.g.,#Remsburg# v.#Docusearch,#Inc.,"816"A.2d"1001,"1009"(N.H."2003).""At"least"one"federal"court"ha s"styled" New"
Hampsh ire’s"appropriation"tort"under"the"right"o f"privacy"as"a"“right"of"publ icity.”""Doe#v.#Friendfinder#Network,#Inc.,"540"F."
Supp."2d"288,"303"(D.N.H."2008)."
55
"See#Palme r#v.#Schonhorn#Enters.,#Inc.,"232"A.2d"458,"459"( N.J."Super."Ct."Ch."Div."1967).""Federal"courts"have"held"that"New"
Jersey"would"recognize"a"right"of"publicity.""See ,#e.g.,#Hart#v.# Elec.#Arts.#Inc.,"717"F.3d"141,"15051"(3d"Cir."2013);"Estate#of#
Presley#v.#Russen,"513"F."Supp."1339,"1354"(D.N.J."1981)."
56
"See,#e.g.,"Moore#v.#Sun#Publ’g#Corp.,"881"P.2d"735,"743"(N.M."1994)."
57
"See,#e.g.,#Hubbard# v.#Journal#Publ’g#Co.,"368"P.2d"147,"148"(N.M."1964)."
58
"New"York"also"has"a "criminal"right"of"privacy"statute.""See"N.Y."CIV."RIGHTS"LAW"§"50"(1909).""Bills"were"introduced"in"the"
201718"session"to"provide"a"posthumous"right"of"publicity.""See"A."08155,"201718"Leg."Sess."(N.Y."2017)"and"S."05857,"2017
18"Leg."Sess."(N.Y."2017 )."
59
"The"New"York"statute"is"styled"as"a"right"of"privacy"statute."
60
"New"York"courts"have"held"that"§§"50"and"51"provide"the"sole"remedy"for"right"of"misappropriation"cases,"and"that"claims"
under"the"common"law"rights"of"privacy"and"publicity"are"preempted.""See,#e.g.,#Stephano#v.#News#Grp.#Publ’ns,"Inc.,"474"N.E.2d"
580,"584"(N.Y."1984);#Messenger#ex#rel.#Messenger#v.#Gruner#&#Jahr#Printing#and#Publg,"727"N.E.2d"549,"551"(N.Y."2000)."
61
"See,#e.g.,#Hall#v.#Post,"372"S.E.2d"711,"718"(N.C."1988)."
62
"The"North"Dakota"Supreme"Court"has"declined"to"rule"on"whether"North"Dakota"recognizes"a"common"law"right"to"privacy.""
See#Am.#Mut.#Life#Ins.#Co.#v.#Jordan,"315"N.W.2d"290"( N.D."1982)."
63
"The"statute"protects"“an"individual’s"name,"voice,"signature,"photograph,"image,"likeness,"or"distinctive"appearance,"if"any"of"
these"aspects"have"commercial"value.”""OHIO"REV."CODE"§"2741.01(A)"(1999)."""
U.S. Copyright Office Authors, Attribution, and Integrity
64
"See"Zacchini#v.#Scripps-Howard#Broadcasting#Co.,"351"N.E.2d"454"(Ohio"1976),"rev'd#on#other#grounds,"433"U.S."562"(1977).""
The"statute"explicitly"does"not"preempt"common"law"claims.""See"OHIO"REV. "CODE"§"2741.08"(1999)."""
65
"See#Zacchini#v.#Scripps-Howard#Broad.# Co.,"351"N.E.2d"454"(Ohio"1976)#rev'd#on#other#grounds,"433"U.S."562"(1977)."
66
"Oklahoma"has"separate"statutes"providing"criminal"penalties"for"certain"violations"of"the"right"of"publicity.""See"OKLA."STAT."
tit."21"§§"839.1,"839.1A"(1985)."
67
"Rights"are"limited"to"“any"natural"person"whose"name,"voice,"signature,"photograph,"or"likeness"has"commercial"value"at"the "
time"of "his"or"her"death,"whether"or"not"during"the"lifetime"of"that"natural"pe r son"the"person"used"his"or"her"name,"voice,"
sign ature,"photograph,"or"likeness"on"or"in"products,"merchandise"or"goods,"or"for"purposes"of"advertising"or"selling,"or"
solicitatio n"of"purchase"of,"products ,"merchandise,"goods,"or"services.”"OKLA."STAT."tit."12"§"1448(H)"(1985)."
68
"See#Anderson#v.#Fisher#Broad.#Cos.,"712"P.2d"803,"80809(Ore."1986)."""
69
"See#id."at"80607."""
70
"See#Henry#v.#Cherry#&#Webb,"73"A."97,"109"(R.I."1909)."
71
"Section"9-1-28.1"is"styled"as"a"codification"of"the"right"of"privacy,"and"includes"the"tort"of"misappropriation.""
72
"See#Henry#v.#Cherry#&#Webb,"73"A."97,"109"(R.I."1909)."
73
"See#Gignilliat#v.#Gignilliat,#Savitz#&#Bettis#L.L.P.,"684"S.E.2d"756,"759"(S.C."2009)."""
74
"See#id."at"759.""
75
"The"initial"term"of"protection"is"10"years"after"death,"and"an"exclusive"right"to"commercial"exploitation"su rvives"thereafter"
until"terminated"upon"proof"of"two"years"of"non-use.""See#TENN."CODE"§"47-25-1104"(1984)."
76
"See#State#ex#rel.#Elvi s#Presley#Intern.#Mem’l#Found.#v.#Cro well,"733"S.W.2d"89,"97"(Tenn."Ct."App."1987).""At"least"one"fede ral"
court"has"found"common"law"right"of"publicity"claims"preempted,"although"the"court"did"not"address"the"effect"of"TENN."CODE"§"
47-25-1106(e),"which"states"that"the"statute’s"remedies"are"cumulative"to"other"remedies"available"by"law.""See#Marshall#v.#
ESPN,"668"Fed."Appx."155,"157"(6th"Cir."2016)."
77
"See#West#v.#Media#Gen.#Convergence,#Inc.,"53"S.W.3d"640,"645"(Tenn."2001).""
78
"A"claim"is"available"where"the"deceased’s"“name,"voice,"signature,"photograph,"or"likeness"has"commercial"value"at"the"time"
of"his"or"her"death"or"comes"to"have"commercial"value"after"that"time.”""TEX."PROP."CODE"§"26.003(2)"(1987).""
79
"See#Kimbrough# v.#Coca-Cola/USA,"521"S.W.2d"719,"722"(Tex."Civ."App."1975)."
80
"See#Express#One#Intern.,#Inc.#v.#Steinbeck,"53"S.W.3d"895,"900"(Tex."App."2001)."
81
"Utah"also"has"a"criminal"right"of"publicity"statute.""See"UTAH"COD E"§"76-9-407"(1981)."
82
"See#Cox#v.#Hatch,"761"P.2d"556,"563"(Utah"1988).""At"least"one"federal"court"ha s"held"that"Utah"would"recognize" a"common"
law"right"of"publicity,"as"well.""See#Natures#Way#Prods.#v.#Nature-Pharma,#Inc.,"736"F."Supp."245,"251"(D."Utah"1990)."
83
"See#Staruski#v.#Cont’l#Tel.#Co.#of#Vt.,"581"A.2d"266,"268"(Vt."1990).""The"court"speculated"that"there"might"be"a"separate"cause"
of"action"under"the"right"of"publicity"where"t he"plaintiff"is"famous"and"h as"a"nam e"or"likeness"with"commercial"value.""Id.#at"
269.""
84
"Virginia"also"has"a"criminal"right"of"publicity"statute.""See"VA."CODE"§"18.2-216.1"(1950)."
85
"While"the"statute"does"not"expressly"preempt"common"law"claims,"the"Supreme"Court"of"Virginia"has"found"that"the"statute"
had"the"effect"of"preempting"such"claims.""See#WLJA-TV#v.#Levin,"564"S.E.2d"383,"395"(Va."2002)."
86
"See#State#ex#rel.#La#Follette#v.#Hinkle,"229"P."317,"319"(Wash."1924);"Lewis#v. #Physicians#and#Dentists#Credit#Bureau,"177"P .2d"
896,"899"(Wash."1947)."
87
"See,#e.g.,#Reid# v.#Pierce#Co.,"961"P.2d"333,"339"(Wa sh."1998).""
88
"See#Curran#v.#Amazon.com,#Inc.,"No."2:070354,"2008"WL"472433,"at"*4"(S.D.W."Va."2008)."
89
"See#Crump#v.#Beckley#Newspapers,#Inc.,"320"S.E.2d"70,"84"(W."Va."1983)."
90
"The"Wisconsin"statute"is"styled"as"a"codification"of"the"right"of"privacy,"and"includes"the"tort"of"misappropriation."
91
#See"Hirsch#v.#S.C.#Johnson#&#Son,#Inc.,"280"N.W.2d"129,"13738"(Wis."1979)." "
92
"See#id."at"133.""
93
"A"recent"decision"of"the"Supreme"Court"of"Wyoming"adopted"the"right"of"privacy"as"set"out"in"the"Restatement"(Second)"of"
Torts,"but"the"tort"at"issue"was"intrusion"upon"seclusion.""See"Howard#v.#Aspen#Way#Ente rs.#Inc.,"406"P.3d"1271,"1273"(Wyo."
2017)."
u.s. copyright office · library of congress · 101 independence avenue se · washington, dc 20559 · www.copyright.gov