The Online Library of Liberty
A Project Of Liberty Fund, Inc.
Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract and
Discourses [1761]
The Online Library Of Liberty
This E-Book (PDF format) is published by Liberty Fund, Inc., a private,
non-profit, educational foundation established in 1960 to encourage study of the ideal
of a society of free and responsible individuals. 2010 was the 50th anniversary year of
the founding of Liberty Fund.
It is part of the Online Library of Liberty web site http://oll.libertyfund.org, which
was established in 2004 in order to further the educational goals of Liberty Fund, Inc.
To find out more about the author or title, to use the site's powerful search engine, to
see other titles in other formats (HTML, facsimile PDF), or to make use of the
hundreds of essays, educational aids, and study guides, please visit the OLL web site.
This title is also part of the Portable Library of Liberty DVD which contains over
1,000 books and quotes about liberty and power, and is available free of charge upon
request.
The cuneiform inscription that appears in the logo and serves as a design element in
all Liberty Fund books and web sites is the earliest-known written appearance of the
word “freedom” (amagi), or “liberty.” It is taken from a clay document written about
2300 B.C. in the Sumerian city-state of Lagash, in present day Iraq.
To find out more about Liberty Fund, Inc., or the Online Library of Liberty Project,
please contact the Director at [email protected].
LIBERTY FUND, INC.
8335 Allison Pointe Trail, Suite 300
Indianapolis, Indiana 46250-1684
Edition Used:
The Social Contract and Discourses by Jean-Jacques Rousseau, translated with an
Introduction by G.D. H. Cole (London and Toronto: J.M. Dent and Sons, 1923).
Author: Jean-Jacques Rousseau
Editor: G.D.H. Cole
About This Title:
This 1913 edition of Rousseau’s works includes the famous Social Contract as well as
3 discourses on Arts and Sciences, the Origin of Inequality, and Political Economy.
Rousseau’s writings inspired liberals and non-liberals alike which makes him rather
controversial in the history of political thought.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
2
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
About Liberty Fund:
Liberty Fund, Inc. is a private, educational foundation established to encourage the
study of the ideal of a society of free and responsible individuals.
Copyright Information:
The text is in the public domain.
Fair Use Statement:
This material is put online to further the educational goals of Liberty Fund, Inc.
Unless otherwise stated in the Copyright Information section above, this material may
be used freely for educational and academic purposes. It may not be used in any way
for profit.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
3
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Table Of Contents
Introduction
The Social Contract Or Principles of Political Right
Foreword
Book I
Chapter I: Subject of the First Book
Chapter II: The First Societies
Chapter III: The Right of the Strongest
Chapter IV: Slavery
Chapter V: That We Must Always Go Back to a First Convention
Chapter VI: The Social Compact
Chapter VII: The Sovereign
Chapter VIII: The Civil State
Chapter IX: Real Property
Book Ii
Chapter I: That Sovereignty Is Inalienable
Chapter II: That Sovereignty Is Indivisible
Chapter III: Whether the General Will Is Fallible
Chapter IV: The Limits of the Sovereign Power
Chapter V: The Right of Life and Death
Chapter VI: Law
Chapter VII: The Legislator
Chapter VIII: The People
Chapter IX: The People ( Continued )
Chapter X: The People ( Continued )
Chapter XI: The Various Systems of Legislation
Chapter XII: The Division of the Laws
Book Iii
Chapter I: Government In General
Chapter II: The Constituent Principle In the Various Forms of Government
Chapter III: The Division of Governments
Chapter IV: Democracy
Chapter V: Aristocracy
Chapter VI: Monarchy
Chapter VII: Mixed Governments
Chapter VIII: That All Forms of Government Do Not Suit All Countries
Chapter IX: The Marks of a Good Government
Chapter X: The Abuse of Government and Its Tendency to Degenerate
Chapter XI: The Death of the Body Politic
Chapter XII: How the Sovereign Authority Maintains Itself
Chapter XIII: The Same ( Continued )
Chapter XIV: The Same ( Continued )
Chapter XV: Deputies Or Representatives
Chapter XVI: That the Institution of Government Is Not a Contract
Chapter XVII: The Institution of Government
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
4
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Chapter XVIII: How to Check the Usurpations of Government
Book Iv
Chapter I: That the General Will Is Indestructible
Chapter II: Voting
Chapter III: Elections
Chapter IV: The Roman Comitia
Chapter V: The Tribunate
Chapter VI: The Dictatorship
Chapter VII: The Censorship
Chapter VIII: Civil Religion
Chapter IX: Conclusion
A Discourse Which Won the Prize At the Academy of Dijon In 1750, On This
Question Proposed By the Academy: Has the Restoration of the Arts and
Sciences Had a Purifying Effect Upon Morals ?
A Discourse On the Moral Effects of the Arts and Sciences Decipimur Specie
Recti. — Horace.
The First Part
The Second Part
A Discourse On a Subject Proposed By the Academy of Dijon: What Is the
Origin of Inequality Among Men, and Is It Authorised By Natural Law ?
A Discourse On Political Economy
this is no. 660 ofEVERYMAN’S LIBRARY.the publishers will be pleased to send freely
to all applicants a list of the published and projected volumes arranged under the
following sections:
travel (illegible) science (illegible) fiction theology & philosophy history (illegible)
classical for young people essays (illegible) oratory poetry & drama biography
reference romance
the ordinary edition is bound in cloth with gilt design and coloured top. there is also a
library edition in reinforced cloth
London: J. M. DENT & SONS Ltd.
New York: E. P. DUTTON & CO.
How charming is divine philosophy
milton
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
5
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
INTRODUCTION
For the study of the great writers and thinkers of the past, historical imagination is the
first necessity. Without mentally referring to the environment in which they lived, we
cannot hope to penetrate below the inessential and temporary to the absolute and
permanent value of their thought. Theory, no less than action, is subject to these
necessities; the form in which men cast their speculations, no less than the ways in
which they behave, are the result of the habits of thought and action which they find
around them. Great men make, indeed, individual contributions to the knowledge of
their times; but they can never transcend the age in which they live. The questions
they try to answer will always be those their contemporaries are asking; their
statement of fundamental problems will always be relative to the traditional
statements that have been handed down to them. When they are stating what is most
startlingly new, they will be most likely to put it in an old-fashioned form, and to use
the inadequate ideas and formulæ of tradition to express the deeper truths towards
which they are feeling their way. They will be most the children of their age, when
they are rising most above it.
Rousseau has suffered as much as any one from critics without a sense of history. He
has been cried up and cried down by democrats and oppressors with an equal lack of
understanding and imagination. His name, a hundred and fifty years after the
publication of the Social Contract, is still a controversial watchword and a party cry.
He is accepted as one of the greatest writers France has produced; but even now men
are inclined, as political bias prompts them, to accept or reject his political doctrines
as a whole, without sifting them or attempting to understand and discriminate. He is
still revered or hated as the author who, above all others, inspired the French
Revolution.
At the present day, his works possess a double significance. They are important
historically, alike as giving us an insight into the mind of the eighteenth century, and
for the actual influence they have had on the course of events in Europe. Certainly no
other writer of the time has exercised such an influence as his. He may fairly be called
the parent of the romantic movement in art, letters and life; he affected profoundly the
German romantics and Goethe himself; he set the fashion of a new introspection
which has permeated nineteenth century literature; he began modern educational
theory; and, above all, in political thought he represents the passage from a traditional
theory rooted in the Middle Ages to the modern philosophy of the State. His influence
on Kant’s moral philosophy and on Hegel’s philosophy of Right are two sides of the
same fundamental contribution to modern thought. He is, in fact, the great forerunner
of German and English Idealism.
It would not be possible, in the course of a short introduction, to deal both with the
positive content of Rousseau’s thought and with the actual influence he has had on
practical affairs. The statesmen of the French Revolution, from Robespierre
downwards, were throughout profoundly affected by the study of his works. Though
they seem often to have misunderstood him, they had on the whole studied him with
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
6
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
the attention he demands. In the nineteenth century, men continued to appeal to
Rousseau, without, as a rule, knowing him well or penetrating deeply into his
meaning. “The Social Contract,” says M. Dreyfus-Brisac, “is the book of all books
that is most talked of and least read.” But with the great revival of interest in political
philosophy there has come a desire for the better understanding of Rousseau’s work.
He is again being studied more as a thinker and less as an ally or an opponent; there is
more eagerness to sift the true from the false, and to seek in the Social Contract the
“principles of political right,” rather than the great revolutionary’s ipse dixit in favour
of some view about circumstances which he could never have contemplated.
The Social Contract, then, may be regarded either as a document of the French
Revolution, or as one of the greatest books dealing with political philosophy. It is in
the second capacity, as a work of permanent value containing truth, that it finds a
place among the world’s great books. It is in that capacity also that it will be treated in
this introduction. Taking it in this aspect, we have no less need of historical insight
than if we came to it as historians pure and simple. To understand its value we must
grasp its limitations; when the questions it answers seem unnaturally put, we must not
conclude that they are meaningless; we must see if the answer still holds when the
question is put in a more up-to-date form.
First, then, we must always remember that Rousseau is writing in the eighteenth
century, and for the most part in France. Neither the French monarchy nor the
Genevese aristocracy loved outspoken criticism, and Rousseau had always to be very
careful what he said. This may seem a curious statement to make about a man who
suffered continual persecution on account of his subversive doctrines; but, although
Rousseau was one of the most daring writers of his time, he was forced continually to
moderate his language and, as a rule, to confine himself to generalisation instead of
attacking particular abuses. Rousseau’s theory has often been decried as too abstract
and metaphysical. This is in many ways its great strength; but where it is excessively
so, the accident of time is to blame. In the eighteenth century it was, broadly
speaking, safe to generalise and unsafe to particularise. Scepticism and discontent
were the prevailing temper of the intellectual classes, and a short-sighted despotism
held that, as long as they were confined to these, they would do little harm.
Subversive doctrines were only regarded as dangerous when they were so put as to
appeal to the masses; philosophy was regarded as impotent. The intellectuals of the
eighteenth century therefore generalised to their hearts’ content, and as a rule suffered
little for their lèse-majesté: Voltaire is the typical example of such generalisation. The
spirit of the age favoured such methods, and it was therefore natural for Rousseau to
pursue them. But his general remarks had such a way of bearing very obvious
particular applications, and were so obviously inspired by a particular attitude towards
the government of his day, that even philosophy became in his hands unsafe, and he
was attacked for what men read between the lines of his works. It is owing to this
faculty of giving his generalisations content and actuality that Rousseau has become
the father of modern political philosophy. He uses the method of his time only to
transcend it; out of the abstract and general he creates the concrete and universal.
Secondly, we must not forget that Rousseau’s theories are to be studied in a wider
historical environment. If he is the first of modern political theorists, he is also the last
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
7
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
of a long line of Renaissance theorists, who in turn inherit and transform the concepts
of mediæval thought. So many critics have spent so much wasted time in proving that
Rousseau was not original only because they began by identifying originality with
isolation: they studied first the Social Contract by itself, out of relation to earlier
works, and then, having discovered that these earlier works resembled it, decided that
everything it had to say was borrowed. Had they begun their study in a truly historical
spirit, they would have seen that Rousseau’s importance lies just in the new use he
makes of old ideas, in the transition he makes from old to new in the general
conception of politics. No mere innovator could have exercised such an influence or
hit on so much truth. Theory makes no great leaps; it proceeds to new concepts by the
adjustment and renovation of old ones. Just as theological writers on politics, from
Hooker to Bossuet, make use of Biblical terminology and ideas; just as more modern
writers, from Hegel to Herbert Spencer, make use of the concept of evolution,
Rousseau uses the ideas and terms of the Social Contract theory. We should feel,
throughout his work, his struggle to free himself from what is lifeless and outworn in
that theory, while he develops out of it fruitful conceptions that go beyond its scope.
A too rigid literalism in the interpretation of Rousseau’s thought may easily reduce it
to the possession of a merely “historical interest”: if we approach it in a truly
historical spirit, we shall be able to appreciate at once its temporary and its lasting
value, to see how it served his contemporaries, and at the same time to disentangle
from it what may be serviceable to us and for all time.
Rousseau’s Emile, the greatest of all works on education, has already been issued in
this series. In this volume are contained the most important of his political works. Of
these the Social Contract, by far the most significant, is the latest in date. It represents
the maturity of his thought, while the other works only illustrate his development.
Born in 1712, he issued no work of importance till 1750; but he tells us, in the
Confessions, that in 1743, when he was attached to the Embassy at Venice, he had
already conceived the idea of a great work on Political Institutions, “which was to put
the seal on his reputation.” He seems, however, to have made little progress with this
work, until in 1749 he happened to light on the announcement of a prize offered by
the Academy of Dijon for an answer to the question, “Has the progress of the arts and
sciences tended to the purification or to the corruption of morality?” His old ideas
came thronging back, and sick at heart of the life he had been leading among the Paris
lumières, he composed a violent and rhetorical diatribe against civilisation generally.
In the following year, this work, having been awarded the prize by the Academy, was
published by its author. His success was instantaneous; he became at once a famous
man, the “lion” of Parisian literary circles. Refutations of his work were issued by
professors, scribblers, outraged theologians and even by the King of Poland. Rousseau
endeavoured to answer them all, and in the course of argument his thought developed.
From 1750 to the publication of the Social Contract and Emile in 1762 he gradually
evolved his views: in those twelve years he made his unique contribution to political
thought.
The Discourse on the Arts and Sciences, the earliest of the works reproduced in this
volume, is not in itself of very great importance. Rousseau has given his opinion of it
in the Confessions. “Full of warmth and force, it is wholly without logic or order; of
all my works it is the weakest in argument and the least harmonious. But whatever
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
8
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
gifts a man may be born with, he cannot learn the art of writing in a moment.” This
criticism is just. The first Discourse neither is, nor attempts to be, a reasoned or a
balanced production. It is the speech of an advocate, wholly one-sided and arbitrary,
but so obviously and naïvely one-sided, that it is difficult for us to believe in its entire
seriousness. At the most, it is only a rather brilliant but flimsy rhetorical effort, a
sophistical improvisation, but not a serious contribution to thought. Yet it is certain
that this declamation made Rousseau’s name, and established his position as a great
writer in Parisian circles. D’Alembert even devoted the preface of the Encyclopædia
to a refutation. The plan of the first Discourse is essentially simple: it sets out from
the badness, immorality and misery of modern nations, traces all these ills to the
departure from a “natural” state, and then credits the progress of the arts and sciences
with being the cause of that departure. In it, Rousseau is already in possession of his
idea of “nature” as an ideal; but he has at present made no attempt to discriminate, in
what is unnatural, between good and bad. He is merely using a single idea, putting it
as strongly as he can, and neglecting all its limitations. The first Discourse is
important not for any positive doctrine it contains, but as a key to the development of
Rousseau’s mind. Here we see him at the beginning of the long journey which was to
lead on at last to the theory of the Social Contract.
In 1755 appeared the Discourse on the Origin and Foundation of Inequality among
Men, which is the second of the works given in this volume. With this essay,
Rousseau had unsuccessfully competed in 1753 for a second prize offered by the
Academy of Dijon, and he now issued it prefaced by a long Dedication to the
Republic of Geneva. In this work, which Voltaire, in thanking him for a presentation
copy, termed his “second book against the human race,” his style and his ideas have
made a great advance; he is no longer content merely to push a single idea to
extremes: while preserving the broad opposition between the state of nature and the
state of society, which runs through all his work, he is concerned to present a rational
justification of his views and to admit that a little at any rate may be said on the other
side. Moreover, the idea of “nature” has already undergone a great development; it is
no longer an empty opposition to the evils of society; it possesses a positive content.
Thus half the Discourse on Inequality is occupied by an imaginary description of the
state of nature, in which man is shown with ideas limited within the narrowest range,
with little need of his fellows, and little care beyond provision for the necessities of
the moment. Rousseau declares explicitly that he does not suppose the “state of
nature” ever to have existed: it is a pure “idea of reason,” a working concept reached
by abstraction from the “state of society.” The “natural man,” as opposed to “man’s
man,” is man stripped of all that society confers upon him, a creature formed by a
process of abstraction, and never intended for a historical portrait. The conclusion of
the Discourse favours not this purely abstract being, but a state of savagery
intermediate between the “natural” and the “social” conditions, in which men may
preserve the simplicity and the advantages of nature and at the same time secure the
rude comforts and assurances of early society. In one of the long notes appended to
the Discourse, Rousseau further explains his position. He does not wish, he says, that
modern corrupt society should return to a state of nature: corruption has gone too far
for that; he only desires now that men should palliate, by wiser use of the fatal arts,
the mistake of their introduction. He recognises society as inevitable and is already
feeling his way towards a justification of it. The second Discourse represents a second
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
9
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
stage in his political thought: the opposition between the state of nature and the state
of society is still presented in naked contrast; but the picture of the former has already
filled out, and it only remains for Rousseau to take a nearer view of the fundamental
implications of the state of society for his thought to reach maturity.
Rousseau is often blamed, by modern critics, for pursuing in the Discourses a method
apparently that of history, but in reality wholly unhistorical. But it must be
remembered that he himself lays no stress on the historical aspect of his work; he
gives himself out as constructing a purely ideal picture, and not as depicting any
actual stages in human history. The use of false historical concepts is characteristic of
the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, and Rousseau is more to be congratulated on
having escaped from giving them too much importance than criticised for employing
them at all.
It is doubtful whether the Discourse on Political Economy, first printed in the great
Encyclopædia in 1755, was composed before or after the Discourse on Inequality. At
first sight the former seems to be far more in the manner of the Social Contract and to
contain views belonging essentially to Rousseau’s constructive period. It would not,
however, be safe to conclude from this that its date is really later. The Discourse on
Inequality still has about it much of the rhetorical looseness of the prize essay; it aims
not so much at close reasoning as at effective and popular presentation of a case. But,
by reading between the lines, an attentive student can detect in it a great deal of the
positive doctrine afterwards incorporated in the Social Contract. Especially in the
closing section, which lays down the plan of a general treatment of the fundamental
questions of politics, we are already to some extent in the atmosphere of the later
works. It is indeed almost certain that Rousseau never attempted to put into either of
the first two Discourses any of the positive content of his political theory. They were
intended, not as final expositions of his point of view, but as partial and preliminary
studies, in which his aim was far more destructive than constructive. It is clear that in
first conceiving the plan of a work on Political Institutions, Rousseau cannot have
meant to regard all society as in essence bad. It is indeed evident that he meant, from
the first, to study human society and institutions in their rational aspect, and that he
was rather diverted from his main purpose by the Academy of Dijon’s competition
than first induced by it to think about political questions. It need, therefore, cause no
surprise that a work probably written before the Discourse on Inequality should
contain the germs of the theory given in full in the Social Contract. The Discourse on
Political Economy is important as giving the first sketch of the theory of the “General
Will.” It will readily be seen that Rousseau does not mean by “political economy”
exactly what we mean nowadays. He begins with a discussion of the fundamental
nature of the State, and the possibility of reconciling its existence with human liberty,
and goes on with an admirable short study of the principles of taxation. He is thinking
throughout of “political” in the sense of “public” economy, of the State as the public
financier, and not of the conditions governing industry. He conceives the State as a
body aiming at the well-being of all its members and subordinates all his views of
taxation to that end. He who has only necessaries should not be taxed at all;
superfluities should be supertaxed; there should be heavy imposts on every sort of
luxury. The first part of the article is still more interesting. Rousseau begins by
demolishing the exaggerated parallel so often drawn between the State and the family;
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
10
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
he shows that the State is not, and cannot be, patriarchal in nature, and goes on to lay
down his view that its real being consists in the General Will of its members. The
essential features of the Social Contract are present in this Discourse almost as if they
were commonplaces, certainly not as if they were new discoveries on which the
author had just hit by some happy inspiration. There is every temptation, after reading
the Political Economy, to suppose that Rousseau’s political ideas really reached
maturity far earlier than has generally been allowed.
The Social Contract finally appeared, along with Emile, in 1762. This year, therefore,
represents in every respect the culmination of Rousseau’s career. Henceforth, he was
to write only controversial and confessional works; his theories were now developed,
and, simultaneously, he gave to the world his views on the fundamental problems of
politics and education. It is now time to ask what Rousseau’s system, in its maturity,
finally amounted to. The Social Contract contains practically the whole of his
constructive political theory; it requires to be read, for full understanding, in
connection with his other works, especially Emile and the Letters on the Mount
(1764), but in the main it is self-contained and complete. The title sufficiently defines
its scope. It is called The Social Contract or Principles of Political Right, and the
second title explains the first. Rousseau’s object is not to deal, in a general way, like
Montesquieu, with the actual institutions of existing States, but to lay down the
essential principles which must form the basis of every legitimate society. Rousseau
himself, in the fifth book of the Emile, has stated the difference clearly.
“Montesquieu,” he says, “did not intend to treat of the principles of political right; he
was content to treat of the positive right (or law) of established governments; and no
two studies could be more different than these.” Rousseau then conceives his object as
being something very different from that of the Spirit of the Laws, and it is a wilful
error to misconstrue his purpose. When he remarks that “the facts,” the actual history
of political societies, “do not concern him,” he is not contemptuous of facts; he is
merely asserting the sure principle that a fact can in no case give rise to a right. His
desire is to establish society on a basis of pure right, so as at once to disprove his
attack on society generally and to reinforce his criticism of existing societies.
Round this point centres the whole dispute about the methods proper to political
theory. There are, broadly speaking, two schools of political theorists, if we set aside
the psychologists. One school, by collecting facts, aims at reaching broad
generalisations about what actually happens in human societies; the other tries to
penetrate to the universal principles at the root of all human combination. For the
latter purpose facts may be useful, but in themselves they can prove nothing. The
question is not one of fact, but one of right.
Rousseau belongs esentially to this philosophical school. He is not, as his less
philosophic critics seem to suppose, a purely abstract thinker generalising from
imaginary historical instances; he is a concrete thinker trying to get beyond the
inessential and changing to the permanent and invariable basis of human society. Like
Green, he is in search of the principle of political obligation, and beside this quest all
others fall into their place as secondary and derivative. It is required “to find a form of
association able to defend and protect with the whole common force the person and
goods of every associate, and of such a nature that each, uniting himself with all, may
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
11
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
still obey only himself, and remain as free as before. This is the fundamental problem
of which the Social Contract provides the solution.” The problem of political
obligation is seen as including all other political problems, which fall into place in a
system based upon it. How, Rousseau asks, can the will of the State help being for me
a merely external will, imposing itself upon my own? How can the existence of the
State be reconciled with human freedom? How can man, who is born free, rightly
come to be everywhere in chains?
No-one could help understanding the central problem of the Social Contract
immediately, were it not that its doctrines often seem to be strangely formulated. We
have seen that this strangeness is due to Rousseau’s historical position, to his use of
the political concepts current in his own age, and to his natural tendency to build on
the foundations laid by his predecessors. There are a great many people whose idea of
Rousseau consists solely of the first words of the opening chapter of the Social
Contract, “Man is born free, and everywhere he is in chains.” But, they tell you, man
is not born free, even if he is everywhere in chains. Thus at the very outset we are
faced with the great difficulty in appreciating Rousseau. When we should naturally
say “man ought to be free,” or perhaps “man is born for freedom,” he prefers to say
“man is born free,” by which he means exactly the same thing. There is doubtless, in
his way of putting it, an appeal to a “golden age”; but this golden age is admittedly as
imaginary as the freedom to which men are born is bound, for most of them, to be.
Elsewhere Rousseau puts the point much as we might put it ourselves. “Nothing is
more certain than that every man born in slavery is born for slavery. . . . But if there
are slaves by nature, it is because there have been slaves against nature” (Social
Contract, Book I, chap. ii).
We have seen that the contrast between the “state of nature” and the “state of society”
runs through all Rousseau’s work. The Emile is a plea for “natural” education; the
Discourses are a plea for a “naturalisation” of society; the New Héloīse is the
romantic’s appeal for more “nature” in human relationships. What then is the position
of this contrast in Rousseau’s mature political thought? It is clear that the position is
not merely that of the Discourses. In them, he envisaged only the faults of actual
societies; now, he is concerned with the possibility of a rational society. His aim is to
justify the change from “nature” to “society,” although it has left men in chains. He is
in search of the true society, which leaves men “as free as before.” Altogether, the
space occupied by the idea of nature in the Social Contract is very small. It is used of
necessity in the controversial chapters, in which Rousseau is refuting false theories of
social obligation; but when once he has brushed aside the false prophets, he lets the
idea of nature go with them, and concerns himself solely with giving society the
rational sanction he has promised. It becomes clear that, in political matters at any
rate, the “state of nature” is for him only a term of controversy. He has in effect
abandoned, in so far as he ever held it, the theory of a human golden age; and where,
as in the Émile, he makes use of the idea of nature, it is broadened and deepened out
of all recognition. Despite many passages in which the old terminology cleaves to
him, he means by “nature” in this period not the original state of a thing, nor even its
reduction to the simplest terms: he is passing over to the conception of “nature” as
identical with the full development of capacity, with the higher idea of human
freedom. This view may be seen in germ even in the Discourse on Inequality, where,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
12
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
distinguishing selfrespect (amour de soi) from egoism (amour-propre), Rousseau
makes the former, the property of the “natural” man, consist not in the desire for self-
aggrandisement, but in the seeking of satisfaction for reasonable desire accompanied
by benevolence; whereas egoism is the preference of our own interests to those of
others, self-respect merely puts us on an equal footing with our fellows. It is true that
in the Discourse Rousseau is pleading against the development of many human
faculties; but he is equally advocating the fullest development of those he regards as
“natural,” by which he means merely “good.” The “state of society,” as envisaged in
the Social Contract, is no longer in contradiction to the “state of nature” upheld in the
Emile, where indeed the social environment is of the greatest importance, and, though
the pupil is screened from it, he is none the less being trained for it. Indeed the views
given in the Social Contract are summarised in the fifth book of the Emile, and by this
summary the essential unity of Rousseau’s system is emphasised.
Rousseau’s object, then, in the first words of the Social Contract, “is to inquire if, in
the civil order, there can be any sure and certain rule of administration, taking men as
they are and laws as they might be.” Montesquieu took laws as they were, and saw
what sort of men they made: Rousseau, founding his whole system on human
freedom, takes man as the basis, and regards him as giving himself what laws he
pleases. He takes his stand on the nature of human freedom: on this he bases his
whole system, making the will of the members the sole basis of every society.
In working out his theory, Rousseau makes use throughout of three general and, to
some extent, alternative conceptions. These are the Social Contract, Sovereignty and
the General Will. We shall now have to examine each of these in turn.
The Social Contract theory is as old as the sophists of Greece (see Plato, Republic,
Book II and the Gorgias), and as elusive. It has been adapted to the most opposite
points of view, and used, in different forms, on both sides of every question to which
it could conceivably be applied. It is frequent in mediæval writers, a commonplace
with the theorists of the Renaissance, and in the eighteenth century already nearing its
fall before a wider conception. It would be a long, as well as a thankless, task to trace
its history over again: it may be followed best in D. G. Ritchie’s admirable essay on it
in Darwin and Hegel and Other Studies. For us, it is important only to regard it in its
most general aspect, before studying the special use made of it by Rousseau.
Obviously, in one form or another, it is a theory very easily arrived at. Wherever any
form of government apart from the merest tyranny exists, reflection on the basis of the
State cannot but lead to the notion that, in one sense or another, it is based on the
consent, tacit or expressed, past or present, of its members. In this alone, the greater
part of the Social Contract theory is already latent. Add the desire to find actual
justification for a theory in facts, and, especially in an age possessed only of the
haziest historical sense, this doctrine of consent will inevitably be given a historical
setting. If in addition there is a tendency to regard society as something unnatural to
humanity, the tendency will become irresistible. By writers of almost all schools, the
State will be represented as having arisen, in some remote age, out of a compact or, in
more legal phrase, contract between two or more parties. The only class that will be
able to resist the doctrine is that which maintains the divine right of kings, and holds
that all existing governments were imposed on the people by the direct interposition
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
13
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
of God. All who are not prepared to maintain that will be partisans of some form or
other of the Social Contract theory.
It is, therefore, not surprising that we find among its advocates writers of the most
opposite points of view. Barely stated, it is a mere formula, which may be filled in
with any content from absolutism to pure republicanism. And, in the hands of some at
least of its supporters, it turns out to be a weapon that cuts both ways. We shall be in a
better position to judge of its usefulness when we have seen its chief varieties at work.
All Social Contract theories that are at all definite fall under one or other of two
heads. They represent society as based on an original contract either between the
people and the government, or between all the individuals composing the State.
Historically, modern theory passes from the first to the second of these forms.
The doctrine that society is founded on a contract between the people and the
government is of mediæval origin. It was often supported by references to the Old
Testament, which contains a similar view in an unreflective form. It is found in most
of the great political writers of the sixteenth century; in Buchanan, and in the writings
of James I: it persists into the seventeenth in the works of Grotius and Puffendorf.
Grotius is sometimes held to have stated the theory so as to admit both forms of
contract; but it is clear that he is only thinking of the first form as admitting
democratic as well as monarchical government. We find it put very clearly by the
Convention Parliament of 1688, which accuses James II of having “endeavoured to
subvert the constitution of the kingdom by breaking the original contract between
king and people.” While Hobbes, on the side of the royalists, is maintaining the
contract theory in its second form, the Parliamentarian Algernon Sidney adheres to
the idea of a contract between the people and the government.
In this form, the theory clearly admits of opposite interpretations. It may be held that
the people, having given itself up once for all to its rulers, has nothing more to ask of
them, and is bound to submit to any usage they may choose to inflict. This, however,
is not the implication most usually drawn from it. The theory, in this form, originated
with theologians who were also lawyers. Their view of a contract implied mutual
obligations; they regarded the ruler as bound, by its terms, to govern constitutionally.
The old idea that a king must not violate the sacred customs of the realm passes easily
into the doctrine that he must not violate the terms of the original contract between
himself and his people. Just as in the days of the Norman kings, every appeal on the
part of the people for more liberties was couched in the form of a demand that the
customs of the “good old times” of Edward the Confessor should be respected, so in
the seventeenth century every act of popular assertion or resistance was stated as an
appeal to the king not to violate the contract. The demand was a good popular cry, and
it seemed to have the theorists behind it. Rousseau gives his refutation of this view,
which he had, in the Discourse on Inequality, maintained in passing, in the sixteenth
chapter of the third book of the Social Contract. (See also Book I, chap. iv, init.) His
attack is really concerned also with the theory of Hobbes, which in some respects
resembles, as we shall see, this first view; but, in form at least, it is directed against
this form of contract. It will be possible to examine it more closely, when the second
view has been considered.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
14
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
The second view, which may be called the Social Contract theory proper, regards
society as originating in, or based on, an agreement between the individuals
composing it. It seems to be found first, rather vaguely, in Richard Hooker’s
Ecclesiastical Polity, from which Locke largely borrowed: and it reappears, in
varying forms, in Milton’s Tenure of Kings and Magistrates, in Hobbes’s Leviathan,
in Locke’s Treatises on Civil Government, and in Rousseau. The best-known instance
of its actual use is by the Pilgrim Fathers on the Mayflower in 1620, in whose
declaration occurs the phrase, “We do solemnly and mutually, in the presence of God
and of one another, covenant and combine ourselves together into a civil body
politic.” The natural implication of this view would seem to be the corollary of
complete popular Sovereignty which Rousseau draws. But before Rousseau’s time it
had been used to support views as diverse as those which rested on the first form. We
saw that, in Grotius’s great work, De Jure Belli et Pacis, it was already possible to
doubt which of the two theories was being advocated. The first theory was,
historically, a means of popular protest against royal aggression. As soon as popular
government was taken into account, the act of contract between people and
government became in effect merely a contract between the individuals composing
the society, and readily passed over into the second form.
The second theory, in its ordinary form, expresses only the view that the people is
everywhere Sovereign, and that, in the phrase of Milton’s treatise, “the power of kings
and magistrates is only derivative.” Before, however, this view had been worked up
into a philosophical theory, it had already been used by Hobbes to support precisely
opposite principles. Hobbes agrees that the original contract is one between all the
individuals composing the State, and that the government is no party to it; but he
regards the people as agreeing, not merely to form a State, but to invest a certain
person or certain persons with the government of it. He agrees that the people is
naturally supreme, but regards it as alienating its Sovereignty by the contract itself,
and delegating its power, wholly and for ever, to the government. As soon, therefore,
as the State is set up, the government becomes for Hobbes the Sovereign; there is no
more question of popular Sovereignty, but only of passive obedience: the people is
bound, by the contract, to obey its ruler, no matter whether he governs well or ill. It
has alienated all its rights to the Sovereign, who is, therefore, absolute master.
Hobbes, living in a time of civil wars, regards the worst government as better than
anarchy, and is, therefore, at pains to find arguments in support of any form of
absolutism. It is easy to pick holes in this system, and to see into what difficulties a
conscientious Hobbist might be led by a revolution. For as soon as the revolutionaries
get the upper hand, he will have to sacrifice one of his principles: he will have to side
against either the actual or the legitimate Sovereign. It is easy also to see that
alienation of liberty, even if possible for an individual, which Rousseau denies, cannot
bind his posterity. But, with all its faults, the view of Hobbes is on the whole
admirably, if ruthlessly, logical, and to it Rousseau owes a great deal.
The special shape given to the second Social Contract theory by Hobbes looks, at first
sight, much like a combination, into a single act, of both the contracts. This, however,
is not the view he adopts. The theory of a contract between government and people
had, as we have seen, been used mainly as a support for popular liberties, a means of
assertion against the government. Hobbes, whose whole aim is to make his
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
15
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
government Sovereign, can only do this by leaving the government outside the
contract: he thus avoids the necessity of submitting it to any obligation whatsoever,
and leaves it absolute and irresponsible. He secures, in fact, not merely a State which
has unbounded rights against the individual, but a determinate authority with the right
to enforce those rights. His theory is not merely Statism (étatisme); it is pure
despotism.
It is clear that, if such a theory is to be upheld, it can stand only by the view, which
Hobbes shares with Grotius, that a man can alienate not merely his own liberty, but
also that of his descendants, and that, consequently, a people as a whole can do the
same. This is the point at which both Locke and Rousseau attack it. Locke, whose aim
is largely to justify the Revolution of 1688, makes government depend, not merely at
its institution, but always, on the consent of the governed, and regards all rulers as
liable to be displaced if they govern tyrannically. He omits, however, to provide any
machinery short of revolution for the expression of popular opinion, and, on the
whole, seems to regard the popular consent as something essentially tacit and
assumed. He regards the State as existing mainly to protect life and property, and is,
in all his assertions of popular rights, so cautious as to reduce them almost to nothing.
It is not till we come to Rousseau that the second form of the contract theory is stated
in its purest and most logical form.
Rousseau sees clearly the necessity, if popular consent in government is to be more
than a name, of giving it some constitutional means of expression. For Locke’s theory
of tacit consent, he substitutes an active agreement periodically renewed. He looks
back with admiration to the city-states of ancient Greece and, in his own day, reserves
his admiration for the Swiss free cities, Berne and, above all, Geneva, his native
place. Seeing in the Europe of his day no case in which representative government
was working at all democratically, he was unable to conceive that means might be
found of giving effect to this active agreement in a nation-state; he therefore held that
self-government was impossible except for a city. He wished to break up the nation-
states of Europe, and create instead federative leagues of independent city-states.
It matters, however, comparatively little, for the appreciation of Rousseau’s political
theory in general, that he failed to become the theorist of the modern State. By taking
the State, which must have, in essentials, everywhere the same basis, at its simplest,
he was able, far better than his predecessors, to bring out the real nature of the “social
tie,” an alternative name which he often uses for the Social Contract. His doctrine of
the underlying principle of political obligation is that of all great modern writers, from
Kant to Mr. Bosanquet. This fundamental unity has been obscured only because
critics have failed to put the Social Contract theory in its proper place in Rousseau’s
system.
This theory was, we have seen, a commonplace. The amount of historical authenticity
assigned to the contract almost universally presupposed varied enormously.
Generally, the weaker a writer’s rational basis, the more he appealed to history—and
invented it. It was, therefore, almost inevitable that Rousseau should cast his theory
into the contractual form. There were, indeed, writers of his time who laughed at the
contract, but they were not writers who constructed a general system of political
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
16
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
philosophy. From Cromwell to Montesquieu and Bentham, it was the practically
minded man, impatient of unactual hypotheses, who refused to accept the idea of
contract. The theorists were as unanimous in its favour as the Victorians were in
favour of the “organic” theory. But we, criticising them in the light of later events, are
in a better position for estimating the position the Social Contract really took in their
political system. We see that Locke’s doctrine of tacit consent made popular control
so unreal that he was forced, if the State was to have any hold, to make his contract
historical and actual, binding posterity for all time, and that he was also led to admit a
quasi-contract between people and government, as a second vindication of popular
liberties. Rousseau, on the other hand, bases no vital argument on the historical nature
of the contract, in which, indeed, he clearly does not believe. “How,” he asks, “did
this change [from nature to society] come about?” And he answers that he does not
know. Moreover, his aim is to find “a sure and legitimate rule of administration,
taking men as they are and laws as they might be”; that is to say, his Social Contract
is something which will be found at work in every legitimate society, but which will
be in abeyance in all forms of despotism. He clearly means by it no more and no less
than the fundamental principle of political association, the basis of the unity which
enables us, in the State, to realise political liberty by giving up lawlessness and
license. The presentation of this doctrine in the quasi-historical form of the Social
Contract theory is due to the accident of the time and place in which Rousseau wrote.
At the same time, the importance of the conception is best to be seen in the hard death
it dies. Though no-one, for a hundred years or so, has thought of regarding it as
historical, it has been found so hard to secure any other phrase explaining as well or
better the basis of political union that, to this day, the phraseology of the contract
theory largely persists. A conception so vital cannot have been barren.
It is indeed, in Rousseau’s own thought, only one of the three different ways in which
the basis of political union is stated, according to the preoccupation of his mind.
When he is thinking quasi-historically, he describes his doctrine as that of the Social
Contract. Modern anthropology, in its attempts to explain the complex by means of
the simple, often strays further from the straight paths of history and reason. In a
semi-legal aspect, using the terminology, if not the standpoint, of jurisprudence, he
restates the same doctrine in the form of popular Sovereignty. This use tends
continually to pass over into the more philosophical form which comes third.
“Sovereignty is the exercise of the general will.” Philosophically, Rousseau’s doctrine
finds its expression in the view that the State is based not on any original convention,
not on any determinate power, but on the living and sustaining rational will of its
members. We have now to examine first Sovereignty and then the General Will,
which is ultimately Rousseau’s guiding conception.
Sovereignty is, first and foremost, a legal term, and it has often been held that its use
in political philosophy merely leads to confusion. In jurisprudence, we are told, it has
the perfectly plain meaning given to it in Austin’s famous definition. The Sovereign is
“a determinate human superior, not in a habit of obedience to a like superior, but
receiving habitual obedience from the bulk of a given society.” Where Sovereignty is
placed is, on this view, a question purely of fact, and never of right. We have only to
seek out the determinate human superior in a given society, and we shall have the
Sovereign. In answer to this theory, it is not enough, though it is a valuable point, to
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
17
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
show that such a determinate superior is rarely to be found. Where, for instance, is the
Sovereign of England or of the British Empire? Is it the King, who is called the
Sovereign? Or is it the Parliament, which is the legislature (for Austin’s Sovereign is
regarded as the source of law)? Or is it the electorate, or the whole mass of the
population, with or without the right of voting? Clearly all these exercise a certain
influence in the making of laws. Or finally, is it now the Cabinet? For Austin, one of
these bodies would be ruled out as indeterminate (the mass of the population) and
another as responsible (the Cabinet). But are we to regard the House of Commons or
those who elect it as forming part of the Sovereign? The search for a determinate
Sovereign may be a valuable legal conception; but it has evidently nothing to do with
political theory.
It is, therefore, essential to distinguish between the legal Sovereign of jurisprudence,
and the political Sovereign of political science and philosophy. Even so, it does not at
once become clear what this political Sovereign may be. Is it the body or bodies of
persons in whom political power in a State actually resides? Is it merely the complex
of actual institutions regarded as embodying the will of the society? This would leave
us still in the realm of mere fact, outside both right and philosophy. The Sovereign, in
the philosophical sense, is neither the nominal Sovereign, nor the legal Sovereign, nor
the political Sovereign of fact and common sense: it is the consequence of the
fundamental bond of union, the restatement of the doctrine of Social Contract, the
foreshadowing of that of General Will. The Sovereign is that body in the State in
which political power ought always to reside, and in which the right to such power
does always reside.
The idea at the back of the philosophical conception of Sovereignty is, therefore,
essentially the same as that we found to underlie the Social Contract theory. It is the
view that the people, whether it can alienate its right or not, is the ultimate director of
its own destinies, the final power from which there is no appeal. In a sense, this is
recognised even by Hobbes, who makes the power of his absolute Sovereign, the
predecessor of Austin’s “determinate human superior,” issue first of all from the
Social Contract, which is essentially a popular act. The difference between Hobbes
and Rousseau on this point is solely that Rousseau regards as inalienable a supreme
power which Hobbes makes the people alienate in its first corporate action. That is to
say, Hobbes in fact accepts the theory of popular supremacy in name only to destroy it
in fact; Rousseau asserts the theory in its only logical form, and is under no
temptation to evade it by means of false historical assumptions. In Locke, a
distinction is already drawn between the legal and the actual Sovereign, which Locke
calls “supreme power”; Rousseau unites the absolute Sovereignty of Hobbes and the
“popular consent” of Locke into the philosophic doctrine of popular Sovereignty,
which has since been the established form of the theory. His final view represents a
return from the perversions of Hobbes to a doctrine already familiar to mediæval and
Renaissance writers; but it is not merely a return. In its passage the view has fallen
into its place in a complete system of political philosophy.
In a second important respect Rousseau differentiates himself from Hobbes. For
Hobbes, the Sovereign is identical with the government. He is so hot for absolutism
largely because he regards revolution, the overthrow of the existing government, as at
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
18
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
the same time the dissolution of the body politic, and a return to complete anarchy or
to the “state of nature.” Rousseau and, to some extent, Locke meet this view by sharp
division between the supreme power and the government. For Rousseau, they are so
clearly distinct that even a completely democratic government is not at the same time
the Sovereign; its members are sovereign only in a different capacity and as a
different corporate body, just as two different societies may exist for different
purposes with exactly the same members. Pure democracy, however, the government
of the State by all the people in every detail, is not, as Rousseau says, a possible
human institution. All governments are really mixed in character; and what we call a
democracy is only a more or less democratic government. Government, therefore, will
always be to some extent in the hands of selected persons. Sovereignty, on the other
hand, is in his view absolute, inalienable, indivisible, and indestructible. It cannot be
limited, abandoned, shared or destroyed. It is an essential part of all social life that the
right to control the destinies of the State belongs in the last resort to the whole people.
There clearly must in the end be somewhere in the society an ultimate court of appeal,
whether determinate or not; but, unless Sovereignty is distinguished from
government, the government, passing under the name of Sovereign, will inevitably be
regarded as absolute. The only way to avoid the conclusions of Hobbes is, therefore,
to establish a clear separation between them.
Rousseau tries to do this by an adaptation of the doctrine of the “three powers.” But
instead of three independent powers sharing the supreme authority, he gives only two,
and makes one of these wholly dependent on the other. He substitutes for the co-
ordination of the legislative, the executive, and the judicial authorities, a system in
which the legislative power, or Sovereign, is always supreme, the executive, or
government, always secondary and derivative, and the judicial power merely a
function of government. This division he makes, naturally, one of will and power. The
government is merely to carry out the decrees, or acts of will, of the Sovereign people.
Just as the human will transfers a command to its members for execution, so the body
politic may give its decisions force by setting up authority which, like the brain, may
command its members. In delegating the power necessary for the execution of its will,
it is abandoning none of its supreme authority. It remains Sovereign, and can at any
moment recall the grants it has made. Government, therefore, exists only at the
Sovereign’s pleasure, and is always revocable by the sovereign will.
It will be seen, when we come to discuss the nature of the General Will, that this
doctrine really contains the most valuable part of Rousseau’s theory. Here, we are
concerned rather with its limitations. The distinction between legislative and
executive functions is in practice very hard to draw. In Rousseau’s case, it is further
complicated by the presence of a second distinction. The legislative power, the
Sovereign, is concerned only with what is general, the executive only with what is
particular. This distinction, the full force of which can only be seen in connection with
the General Will, means roughly that a matter is general when it concerns the whole
community equally, and makes no mention of any particular class; as soon as it refers
to any class or person, it becomes particular, and can no longer form the subject
matter of an act of Sovereignty. However just this distinction may seem in the
abstract, it is clear that its effect is to place all the power in the hands of the executive:
modern legislation is almost always concerned with particular classes and interests. It
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
19
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
is not, therefore, a long step from the view of Rousseau to the modern theory of
democratic government, in which the people has little power beyond that of removing
its rulers if they displease it. As long, however, as we confine our view to the city-
state of which Rousseau is thinking, his distinction is capable of preserving for the
people a greater actual exercise of will. A city can often generalise where a nation
must particularise.
It is in the third book of the Social Contract, where Rousseau is discussing the
problem of government, that it is most essential to remember that his discussion has in
view mainly the city-state and not the nation. Broadly put, his principle of
government is that democracy is possible only in small States, aristocracy in those of
medium extent, and monarchy in great States (Book III, chap. iii). In considering this
view, we have to take into account two things. First, he rejects representative
government; will being, in his theory, inalienable, representative Sovereignty is
impossible. But, as he regards all general acts as functions of Sovereignty, this means
that no general act can be within the competence of a representative assembly. In
judging this theory, we must take into account all the circumstances of Rousseau’s
time. France, Geneva and England were the three States he took most into account. In
France, representative government was practically non-existent; in Geneva, it was
only partially necessary; in England, it was a mockery, used to support a corrupt
oligarchy against a debased monarchy. Rousseau may well be pardoned for not taking
the ordinary modern view of it. Nor indeed is it, even in the modern world, so
satisfactory an instrument of the popular will that we can afford wholly to discard his
criticism. It is one of the problems of the day to find some means of securing effective
popular control over a weakened Parliament and a despotic Cabinet.
The second factor is the immense development of local government. It seemed to
Rousseau that, in the nation-state, all authority must necessarily pass, as it had in
France, to the central power. Devolution was hardly dreamed of; and Rousseau saw
the only means of securing effective popular government in a federal system, starting
from the small unit as Sovereign. The nineteenth century has proved the falsehood of
much of his theory of government; but there are still many wise comments and fruitful
suggestions to be found in the third book of the Social Contract and in the treatise on
the Government of Poland, as well as in his adaptation and criticism of the
Polysynodie of the Abbé de Saint-Pierre, a scheme of local government for France,
born out of its due time.
The point in Rousseau’s theory of Sovereignty that offers most difficulty is his view
(Book II, chap. vii) that, for every State, a Legislator is necessary. We shall
understand the section only by realising that the legislator is, in fact, in Rousseau’s
system, the spirit of institutions personified; his place, in a developed society, is taken
by the whole complex of social custom, organisation and tradition that has grown up
with the State. This is made clearer by the fact that the legislator is not to exercise
legislative power; he is merely to submit his suggestions for popular approval. Thus
Rousseau recognises that, in the case of institutions and traditions as elsewhere, will,
and not force, is the basis of the State.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
20
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
This may be seen in his treatment of law as a whole (Book II, chap. vi), which
deserves very careful attention. He defines laws as “acts of the general will,” and,
agreeing with Montesquieu in making law the “condition of civil association,” goes
beyond him only in tracing it more definitely to its origin in an act of will. The Social
Contract renders law necessary, and at the same time makes it quite clear that laws
can proceed only from the body of citizens who have constituted the State.
“Doubtless,” says Rousseau, “there is a universal justice emanating from reason
alone; but this justice, to be admitted among us, must be mutual. Humbly speaking, in
default of natural sanctions, the laws of justice are ineffective among men.” Of the
law which set up among men this reign of mutual justice the General Will is the
source.
We thus come at last to the General Will, the most disputed, and certainly the most
fundamental, of all Rousseau’s political concepts. No critic of the Social Contract has
found it easy to say either what precisely its author meant by it, or what is its final
value for political philosophy. The difficulty is increased because Rousseau himself
sometimes halts in the sense which he assigns to it, and even seems to suggest by it
two different ideas. Of its broad meaning, however, there can be no doubt. The effect
of the Social Contract is the creation of a new individual. When it has taken place, “at
once, in place of the individual personality of each contracting party, the act of
association creates a moral and collective body, composed of as many members as the
assembly contains voters, and receiving from the act its unity, its common identity
(moi commun), its life and its will” (Book I, chap. vi). The same doctrine had been
stated earlier, in the Political Economy, without the historical setting. “The body
politic is also a moral being, possessed of a will, and this general will, which tends
always to the preservation and welfare of the whole and of every part, and is the
source of the laws, constitutes for all the members of the State, in their relations to
one another and to it, the rule of what is just or unjust.” It will be seen at once that the
second statement, which could easily be fortified by others from the Social Contract,
says more than the first. It is not apparent that the common will, created by the
institution of society, need “tend always to the welfare of the whole.” Is not the
common will at least as fallible as the will of a single individual? May it not equally
be led away from its true interests to the pursuit of pleasure or of something which is
really harmful to it? And, if the whole society may vote what conduces to the
momentary pleasure of all the members and at the same time to the lasting damage of
the State as a whole, is it not still more likely that some of the members will try to
secure their private interests in opposition to those of the whole and of others? All
these questions, and others like them, have been asked by critics of the conception of
the General Will.
Two main points are involved, to one of which Rousseau gives a clear and definite
answer. “There is often,” he says, “a great deal of difference between the will of all
and the general will; the latter takes account only of the common interest, while the
former takes private interest into account, and is no more than a sum of particular
wills.” “The agreement of all interests is formed by opposition to that of each” (Book
II, chap. iii). It is indeed possible for a citizen, when an issue is presented to him, to
vote not for the good of the State, but for his own good; but, in such a case, his vote,
from the point of view of the General Will, is merely negligible. But “does it follow
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
21
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
that the general will is exterminated or corrupted? Not at all: it is always constant,
unalterable, and pure; but it is subordinated to other wills which encroach upon its
sphere. . . . The fault [each man] commits [in detaching his interest from the common
interest] is that of changing the state of the question, and answering something
different from what he is asked. Instead of saying by his vote ‘It is to the advantage of
the State,’ he says, ‘It is to the advantage of this or that man or party that this or that
view should prevail.’ Thus the law of public order in assemblies is not so much to
maintain in them the general will as to secure that the question be always put to it, and
the answer always given by it” (Book IV, chap. i). These passages, with many others
that may be found in the text, make it quite clear that by the General Will Rousseau
means something quite distinct from the Will of All, with which it should never have
been confused. The only excuse for such confusion lies in his view that when, in a
city-state, all particular associations are avoided, votes guided by individual self-
interest will always cancel one another, so that majority voting will always result in
the General Will. This is clearly not the case, and in this respect we may charge him
with pushing the democratic argument too far. The point, however, can be better dealt
with at a later stage. Rousseau makes no pretence that the mere voice of a majority is
infallible; he only says, at the most, that, given his ideal conditions, it would be so.
The second main point raised by critics of the General Will is whether in defining it as
a will directed solely to the common interest, Rousseau means to exclude acts of
public immorality and short-sightedness. He answers the questions in different ways.
First, an act of public immorality would be merely an unanimous instance of
selfishness, different in no particular from similar acts less unanimous, and therefore
forming no part of a General Will. Secondly, a mere ignorance of our own and the
State’s good, entirely unprompted by selfish desires, does not make our will anti-
social or individual. “The general will is always right and tends to the public
advantage; but it does not follow that the deliberations of the people are always
equally correct. Our will is always for our own good, but we do not always see what
that is: the people is never corrupted, but it is often deceived, and on such occasions
only does it seem to will what is bad” (Book II, chap. iii). It is impossible to acquit
Rousseau in some of the passages in which he treats of the General Will, of something
worse than obscurity—positive contradiction. It is probable, indeed, that he never
quite succeeded in getting his view clear in his own mind; there is nearly always, in
his treatment of it, a certain amount of muddle and fluctuation. These difficulties the
student must be left to worry out for himself; it is only possible to present, in outline,
what Rousseau meant to convey.
The treatment of the General Will in the Political Economy is brief and lucid, and
furnishes the best guide to his meaning. The definition of it in this work, which has
already been quoted, is followed by a short account of the nature of general wills as a
whole. “Every political society is composed of other smaller societies of various
kinds, each of which has its interest and rules of conduct; but those societies which
everybody perceives, because they have an external or authorised form, are not the
only ones that actually exist in the State: all individuals who are united by a common
interest compose as many others, either temporary or permanent, whose influence is
none the less real because it is less apparent. . . . The influence of all these tacit or
formal associations causes by the influence of their will as many modifications of the
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
22
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
public will. The will of these particular societies has always two relations; for the
members of the association, it is a general will; for the great society, it is a particular
will; and it is often right with regard to the first object and wrong as to the second.
The most general will is always the most just, and the voice of the people is, in fact,
the voice of God.”
The General Will, Rousseau continues in substance, is always for the common good;
but it is sometimes divided into smaller general wills, which are wrong in relation to
it. The supremacy of the great General Will is “the first principle of public economy
and the fundamental rule of government.”
In this passage, which differs only in clearness and simplicity from others in the
Social Contract itself, it is easy to see how far Rousseau had in his mind a perfectly
definite idea. Every association of several persons creates a new common will; every
association of a permanent character has already a “personality” of its own, and in
consequence a “general” will; the State, the highest known form of association, is a
fully developed moral and collective being with a common will which is, in the
highest sense yet known to us, general. All such wills are general only for the
members of the associations which exercise them; for outsiders, or rather for other
associations, they are purely particular wills. This applies even to the State; “for, in
relation to what is outside it, the State becomes a simple being, an individual” (Social
Contract, Book I, chap. vii). In certain passages in the Social Contract, in his
criticism of the Abbé de Saint-Pierre’s Project of Perpetual Peace, and in the second
chapter of the original draft of the Social Contract, Rousseau takes into account the
possibility of a still higher individual, “the federation of the world.” In the Political
Economy, thinking of the nation-state, he affirms what in the Social Contract (Book
II, chap. iii) he denies of the city, and recognises that the life of a nation is made up of
the whole complex of its institutions, and that the existence of lesser general wills is
not necessarily a menace to the General Will of the State. In the Social Contract, he
only treats of these lesser wills in relation to the government, which, he shows, has a
will of its own, general for its members, but particular for the State as a whole (Book
III, chap. ii). This governmental will he there prefers to call corporate will, and by
this name it will be convenient to distinguish the lesser general wills from the General
Will of the State that is over them all.
So far, there is no great difficulty; but in discussing the infallibility of the General
Will we are on more dangerous ground. Rousseau’s treatment here clearly oscillates
between regarding it as a purely ideal conception, to which human institutions can
only approximate, and holding it to be realised actually in every republican State, i. e.
wherever the people is the Sovereign in fact as well as in right. Book IV, chap. ii is
the most startling passage expressing the latter view. “When in the popular assembly a
law is proposed, what the people is asked is not exactly whether it accepts or rejects
the proposal, but whether it is in conformity with the general will, which is its will. . .
. When, therefore, the opinion that is contrary to my own prevails, this proves neither
more nor less than that I was mistaken, and that what I thought to be the general will
was not so.” On his own principles laid down elsewhere, Rousseau would have to
admit that it proves nothing of the sort, except in so far as the other voters have been
guided by the general interest. Though he sometimes affirms the opposite, there is no
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
23
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
security on his principles that the will of the majority will be the General Will. At the
most it can only be said that there is a greater chance of its being general than of the
will of any selected class of persons not being led away by corporate interests. The
justification of democracy is not that it is always right, even in intention, but that it is
more general than any other kind of supreme power.
Fundamentally, however, the doctrine of the General Will is independent of these
contradictions. Apart from Kant’s narrow and rigid logic, it is essentially one with his
doctrine of the autonomy of the will. Kant takes Rousseau’s political theory, and
applies it to ethics as a whole. The germ of this application is already found in
Rousseau’s own work; for he protests more than once against attempts to treat moral
and political philosophy apart, as distinct studies, and asserts their absolute unity. This
is brought out clearly in the Social Contract (Book I, chap. viii), where he is speaking
of the change brought about by the establishment of society. “The passage from the
state of nature to the civil state produces a very remarkable change in man, by
substituting justice for instinct in his conduct, and giving his actions the morality they
had hitherto lacked. . . . What man loses by the social contract is his natural liberty
and an unlimited right to everything he tries to get and succeeds in getting; what he
gains is civil liberty . . . which is limited by the general will. . . . We might, over and
above all this, add to what man acquires in the civil state moral liberty, which alone
makes him truly master of himself; for the mere impulse of appetite is slavery, while
obedience to a law which we prescribe to ourselves is liberty.
This one chapter contains the gist of the Kantian moral philosophy, and makes it quite
clear that Rousseau perceived its application to ethics as well as to politics. The
morality of our acts consists in their being directed in accordance with universal law;
acts in which we are guided merely by our passions are not moral. Further, man can
only possess freedom when his whole being is unified in the pursuit of a single end;
and, as his whole being can be unified only in pursuit of a rational end, which alone
excludes contradiction, only moral acts, only men directing their lives by universal
law, are free. In Kantian language, the will is autonomous (i. e. prescribes to itself its
own law) only when it is directed to a universal end; when it is guided by selfish
passions, or particular considerations, it is heteronomous (i. e. receives its law from
something external to itself), and in bondage. Rousseau, as he says (Book I, chap.
viii), was not directly concerned with the ethical sense of the word “liberty,” and Kant
was, therefore, left to develop the doctrine into a system; but the phrases of this
chapter prove false the view that the doctrine of a Real Will arises first in connection
with politics, and is only transferred thence to moral philosophy. Rousseau bases his
political doctrine throughout on his view of human freedom; it is because man is a
free agent capable of being determined by a universal law prescribed by himself that
the State is in like manner capable of realising the General Will, that is, of prescribing
to itself and its members a similar universal law.
The General Will, then, is the application of human freedom to political institutions.
Before the value of this conception can be determined, there is a criticism to be met.
The freedom which is realised in the General Will, we are told, is the freedom of the
State as a whole; but the State exists to secure individual freedom for its members. A
free State may be tyrannical; a despot may allow his subjects every freedom. What
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
24
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
guarantee is there that the State, in freeing itself, will not enslave its members? This
criticism has been made with such regularity that it has to be answered in some detail.
“The problem is to find a form of association which will defend and protect with the
whole common force the person and goods of each associate, and in which each,
while uniting himself with all, may still obey himself alone, and remain as free as
before.” “The clauses of the contract . . . are everywhere the same and everywhere
tacitly admitted and recognised. . . . These clauses, properly understood, may be
reduced to one—the total alienation of each associate, together with all his rights, to
the whole community . . .; for, if the individuals retained certain rights, as there would
be no common superior to decide between them and the public, each, being on one
point his own judge, would ask to be so on all, and the state of nature would continue”
(Book I, chap. vi). Rousseau sees clearly that it is impossible to place any limits upon
the power of the State; when the people combine into a State, they must in the end
submit to be guided in all things by the will of the effective majority. Limited
Sovereignty is a contradiction in terms; the Sovereign has a right to all that reason
allows it, and as soon as reason demands that the State shall interfere, no appeal to
individual rights can be made. What is best for the State must be suffered by the
individual. This, however, is very far from meaning that the ruling power ought, or
has the moral right, to interfere in every particular case. Rousseau has been subjected
to much foolish criticism because, after upholding the State’s absolute supremacy, he
goes on (Book II, chap. iv) to speak of “the limits of the sovereign power.” There is
no contradiction whatsoever. Wherever State intervention is for the best, the State has
a right to intervene; but it has no moral right, though it must have a legal right, to
intervene where it is not for the best. The General Will, being always in the right, will
intervene only when intervention is proper. “The Sovereign,” therefore, “cannot
impose upon its subjects any fetters that are useless to the community, nor can it even
wish to do so.” As, however, the infallibility of the General Will is not enough to
make the State infallible, there still remains an objection. Since the General Will
cannot always be arrived at, who is to judge whether an act of intervention is
justified? Rousseau’s answer fails to satisfy many of his critics. “Each man alienates,
I admit, by the social compact, only such part of his powers, goods and liberty as it is
important for the community to control; but it must also be granted that the Sovereign
is sole judge of what is important.” This, we are told, is mere State tyranny over
again. But how is it possible to avoid such a conclusion? Rousseau has already given
his reasons for objecting to a limited Sovereignty (Book I, chap. vi): it follows
absolutely that we must take the best machinery we can find for the execution of the
State’s functions. No doubt the machinery will be imperfect; but we can only try to
get as near the General Will as possible, without hoping to realise it fully.
The answer, therefore, to the critics who hold that, in securing civil liberty Rousseau
has sacrificed the individual may be put after this fashion. Liberty is not a merely
negative conception; it does not consist solely in the absence of restraint. The purest
individualist, Herbert Spencer for example, would grant that a certain amount of State
interference is necessary to secure liberty; but as soon as this idea of securing liberty
is admitted in the smallest degree, the whole idea has undergone profound
modification. It can no longer be claimed that every interference on the part of the
State lessens the liberty of the individual; the “liberty-fund” theory is as untenable as
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
25
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
that of the “wages-fund”: the members of a State may be more free when all are
restrained from doing one another mutual damage than when any one is left “free” to
enslave another or be himself enslaved. This principle once admitted, the precise
amount of State interference that is necessary to secure freedom will be always a
matter for particular discussion; every case must be decided on its own merits, and, in
right, the Sovereign will be omnipotent, or subject only to the law of reason.
It has often been held that Rousseau cannot really have inspired the French
Revolution because this view is totally inconsistent with the “rights of man,” which
the revolutionaries so fervently proclaimed. If every right is alienated in the Social
Contract, what sense can there be in talking of “natural rights” afterwards? This,
however, is to misrepresent Rousseau’s position. The rights of man as they are
preached by the modern individualist, are not the rights of which Rousseau and the
revolutionaries were thinking. We have seen that the theory of the Social Contract is
founded on human freedom: this freedom carries with it, in Rousseau’s view, the
guarantee of its own permanence; it is inalienable and indestructible. When, therefore,
government becomes despotic, it has no more right over its subjects than the master
has over his slave (Book I, chap. iv); the question is then purely one of might. In such
cases, appeal may be made either to the terms of the Social Contract, or, putting the
same idea another way, to the “natural right” of human freedom. This natural right is
in no sense inconsistent with the complete alienation supposed in the Contract; for the
Contract itself reposes on it and guarantees its maintenance. The Sovereign must,
therefore, treat all its members alike; but, so long as it does this, it remains
omnipotent. If it leaves the general for the particular, and treats one man better than
another, it ceases to be Sovereign; but equality is already presupposed in the terms of
the Contract.
It is more profitable to attack Rousseau for his facile identification of the interests of
each of the citizens with those of all; but here, too, most of the critics have abused
their opportunity. He does not maintain that there can be no opposition between a
man’s particular interests and the General Will as present in him; on the contrary, he
explicitly and consistently affirms the presence of such opposition (Book I, chap. vii).
What he asserts is, first, that the Sovereign, as such, cannot have any interest contrary
to the interest of the citizens as a whole—that is obvious; and, secondly, that it cannot
have an interest contrary to that of any individual. The second point Rousseau proves
by showing that the omnipotence of the Sovereign is essential to the preservation of
society, which in turn is necessary for the individual. His argument, however, really
rests on the fundamental character of the General Will. He would admit that, in any
actual State, the apparent interest of the many might often conflict with that of the
few; but he would contend that the real interest of State and individual alike, being
subject to universal law, could not be such as to conflict with any other real interest.
The interest of the State, in so far as it is directed by the General Will, must be the
interest of every individual, in so far as he is guided by his real will, that is, in so far
as he is acting universally, rationally and autonomously.
Thus the justification of Rousseau’s theory of liberty returns to the point from which
it set out—the omnipotence of the real will in State and individual. It is in this sense
that he speaks of man in the State as “forced to be free” by the General Will, much as
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
26
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Kant might speak of a man’s lower nature as forced to be free by the universal
mandate of his higher, more real and more rational will. It is in this recognition of the
State as a moral being, with powers of determination similar to the powers of the
individual mind, that the significance of the General Will ultimately lies. Even,
however, among those who have recognised its meaning, there are some who deny its
value as a conception of political philosophy. If, they say, the General Will is not the
Will of All, if it cannot be arrived at by a majority vote or by any system of voting
whatsoever, then it is nothing; it is a mere abstraction, neither general, nor a will. This
is, of course, precisely the criticism to which Kant’s “real will” is often subjected.
Clearly, it must be granted at once that the General Will does not form the whole
actual content of the will of every citizen. Regarded as actual, it must always be
qualified by “in so far as” or its equivalent. This, however, is so far from destroying
the value of the conception that therein lies its whole value. In seeking the universal
basis of society, we are not seeking anything that is wholly actualised in any State,
though we must be seeking something which exists, more or less perfectly, in every
State.
The point of the Social Contract theory, as Rousseau states it, is that legitimate society
exists by the consent of the people, and acts by popular will. Active will, and not
force or even mere consent, is the basis of the “republican” State, which can only
possess this character because individual wills are not really self-sufficient and
separate, but complementary and interdependent. The answer to the question “Why
ought I to obey the General Will?” is that the General Will exists in me and not
outside me. I am “obeying only myself,” as Rousseau says. The State is not a mere
accident of human history, a mere device for the protection of life and property; it
responds to a fundamental need of human nature, and is rooted in the character of the
individuals who compose it. The whole complex of human institutions is not a mere
artificial structure; it is the expression of the mutual dependence and fellowship of
men. If it means anything, the theory of the General Will means that the State is
natural, and the “state of nature” an abstraction. Without this basis of will and natural
need, no society could for a moment subsist; the State exists and claims our obedience
because it is a natural extension of our personality.
The problem, however, still remains of making the General Will, in any particular
State, active and conscious. It is clear that there are States in which visible and
recognised institutions hardly answer in any respect to its requirements. Even in such
States, however, there is a limit to tyranny; deep down, in immemorial customs with
which the despot dare not interfere, the General Will is still active and important. It
does not reside merely in the outward and visible organisation of social institutions, in
that complex of formal associations which we may call the State; its roots go deeper
and its branches spread further. It is realised, in greater or less degree, in the whole
life of the community, in the entire complex of private and public relations which, in
the widest sense, may be called Society. We may recognise it not only in a
Parliament, a Church, a University or a Trade Union, but also in the most intimate
human relationships, and the most trivial, as well as the most vital, social customs.
But, if all these things go to the making of the General Will in every community, the
General Will has, for politics, primarily a narrower sense. The problem here is to
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
27
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
secure its supremacy in the official institutions and public councils of the nation. This
is the question to which Rousseau chiefly addressed himself. Here, too, we shall find
the General Will the best possible conception for the guidance of political endeavour.
For the General Will is realised not when that is done which is best for the
community, but when, in addition, the community as a whole has willed the doing of
it. The General Will demands not only good government, but also self-
government—not only rational conduct, but good-will. This is what some of
Rousseau’s admirers are apt to forget when they use his argument, as he himself was
sometimes inclined to use it, in support of pure aristocracy. Rousseau said that
aristocracy was the best of all governments, but he said also that it was the worst of all
usurpers of Sovereignty. Nor must it be forgotten that he expressly specified elective
aristocracy. There is no General Will unless the people wills the good. General Will
may be embodied in one man willing universally; but it can only be embodied in the
State when the mass of the citizens so wills. The will must be “general” in two senses:
in the sense in which Rousseau used the word, it must be general in its object, i. e.
universal; but it must also be generally held, i. e. common to all or to the majority.1
The General Will is, then, above all a universal and, in the Kantian sense, a “rational”
will. It would be possible to find in Rousseau many more anticipations of the views of
Kant; but it is better here to confine comment to an important difference between
them. It is surprising to find in Kant, the originator of modern “intellectualism,” and
in Rousseau, the great apostle of “sentiment,” an essentially similar view on the
nature and function of the will. Their views, however, present a difference; for,
whereas the moving force of Kant’s moral imperative is purely “rational,” Rousseau
finds the sanction of his General Will in human feeling itself. As we can see from a
passage in the original draft of the Social Contract, the General Will remains purely
rational. “No-one will dispute that the General Will is in each individual a pure act of
the understanding, which reasons while the passions are silent on what a man may
demand of his neighbour and on what his neighbour has a right to demand of him.”
The will remains purely rational, but Rousseau feels that it needs an external motive
power. “If natural law,” he writes, “were written only on the tablets of human reason
it would be incapable of guiding the greater part of our actions; but it is also graven
on the heart of man in characters that cannot be effaced, and it is there it speaks to
him more strongly than all the precepts of the philosophers” (from an unfinished
essay on The State of War). The nature of this guiding sentiment is explained in the
Discourse on Inequality (p. 197, note 2), where egoism (amour-propre) is contrasted
with self-respect (amour de soi). Naturally, Rousseau holds, man does not want
everything for himself, and nothing for others. “Egoism” and “altruism” are both one-
sided qualities arising out of the perversion of man’s “natural goodness.” “Man is
born good,” that is, man’s nature really makes him desire only to be treated as one
among others, to share equally. This natural love of equality (amour de soi) includes
love of others as well as love of self, and egoism, loving one’s self at the expense of
others, is an unnatural and perverted condition. The “rational” precepts of the General
Will, therefore, find an echo in the heart of the “natural” man, and, if we can only
secure the human being against perversion by existing societies, the General Will can
be made actual.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
28
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
This is the meeting-point of Rousseau’s educational with his political theory. His
view as a whole can be studied only by taking together the Social Contract and the
Emile as explained by the Letters on the Mount and other works. The fundamental
dogma of the natural goodness of man finds no place directly in the Social Contract;
but it lurks behind the whole of his political theory, and is indeed, throughout, his
master-conception. His educational, his religious, his political and his ethical ideas are
all inspired by a single consistent attitude. Here we have been attending only to his
political theory; in the volume which is to follow, containing the Letters on the Mount
and other works, some attempt will be made to draw the various threads together and
estimate his work as a whole. The political works, however, can be read separately,
and the Social Contract itself is still by far the best of all text-books of political
philosophy. Rousseau’s political influence, so far from being dead, is every day
increasing; and as new generations and new classes of men come to the study of his
work, his conceptions, often hazy and undeveloped, but nearly always of lasting
value, will assuredly form the basis of a new political philosophy, in which they will
be taken up and transformed. This new philosophy is the work of the future; but,
rooted upon the conception of Rousseau, it will stretch far back into the past. Of our
time, it will be for all time; its solutions will be at once relatively permanent and
ceaselessly progressive.
G. D. H. Cole.
A NOTE ON BOOKS
There are few good books in English on Rousseau’s politics. By far the best treatment
is to be found in Mr. Bernard Bosanquet’s Philosophical Theory of the State.
Viscount Morley’s Rousseau is a good life, but is not of much use as a criticism of
views; Mr. W. Boyd’s The Educational Theory of Rousseau contains some fairly good
chapters on the political views. D. G. Ritchie’s Darwin and Hegel includes an
admirable essay on The Social Contract Theory and another on Sovereignty. The
English translation of Professor Gran’s Rousseau is an interesting biography.
In French, there is a good cheap edition of Rousseau’s complete works published by
Hachette in thirteen volumes. M. Dreyfus-Brisac’s great edition of the Contrat Social
is indispensable, and there is a good small edition with notes by M. Georges
Beaulavon. M. Faguet’s study of Rousseau in his Dix-huitième siècle—études
littéraires and his Politique comparée de Montesquieu, Voltaire et Rousseau are
useful, though I am seldom in agreement with them. M. Henri Rodet’s Le Contrat
Social et les idées politiques de J. J. Rousseau is useful, if not inspired, and there are
interesting works by MM. Chuquet, Fabre and Lemaitre. The French translation of
Professor Höffding’s little volume on Rousseau: sa vie et sa philosophie is admirable.
Miss Foxley’s translation of the Emile, especially of Book V, should be studied in
connection with the Social Contract. A companion volume, containing the Letters on
the Mount and other works, will be issued shortly.
G. D. H. C.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
29
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Principal Works: Article in the Mercure in answer to one entitled Si le monde que
nous habitons est une sphère ou une sphéroïde, 1738; Le Verger de Mme. de Warens,
1739; Sur la musique moderne, 1743; Si le rétablissement des Sciences et des Arts a
contribué à épurer les Mœurs, prize essay, 1750, translated by R. Wynne, 1752, by
anonymous author, 1760, by H. Smithers, 1818; Devin du Village (opera), 1753,
translated by C. Burney, 1766; Narcisse, ou Amant de lui-même, 1753; Lettre sur la
musique Française, 1753; Sur l’origine de l’inégalité parmi les hommes, 1755;
Discours sur deux principes avancés par Rameau, 1755; Sur l’économie politique,
1758; Letter to d’Alembert on his article Genève in the Encyclopédie, 1758, translated
1759; Lettres à Voltaire, 1759; Julie, ou la nouvelle Héloïse, first published under the
title of Lettres de deux amants, habitants d’une petite ville au pied des Alpes, etc.,
1761; Contrat Social, or Principes du droit politique, 1762; Emile, ou De l’Education,
1762; Lettre à Christophe de Beaumont, Archevêque de Paris, 1763; Allée de Silvie
(poem), 1763; Lettres écrites de la Montagne, 1764; De l’imitation théâtrale, 1764;
Dictionnaire de musique, 1767, translated by W. Waring, 1779; Lettres sur son exil du
Canton de Berne, 1770.
Posthumous Works: Emile et Sophie, 1780; Les consolations des misères de ma vie,
1781; Considérations sur le gouvernement de Pologne, 1782; Les Confessions, and
Rêveries du Promeneur Solitaire, 4 vols., 1782–9; Nouveau Dédale, 1801; La
Botanique de J. J. Rousseau, 1805; translated, with additional letters, by T. Martyn,
1785, 7th edition, 1807; Testament de J. J. Rousseau, 1820.
Translations: Héloïse (Eloisa), 1761, with a sequel found after the author’s death,
1784, 1795, 1810; Emile, by Nugent, 1763; anonymous translator the same year;
abridged and annotated by W. H. Payne, 1893; Emile et Sophie, by Nugent, 1765 (?),
by the translator of Eloisa, 1767; Contrat Social, 1764, 1791, in vol. iii. of Political
Classics, 1795; 1840 (?), by R. M. Harrington, with Introduction by E. L. Walter,
1893; by H. J. Tozer 1895, 1902, 1905; Confessions, 2 vols., 1783; 1796–90, 1861,
1891 (Masterpieces of Foreign Authors), abridged from 1896 edition, with preface by
G. J. Holyoake, 1857; complete translation (privately printed), 2 vols., 1896; with
Introduction by Hesketh Milis (Sisley Books), 1907; the second part, with a new
collection of letters, 3 vols., 1791.
Works: 1764 (6 vols.); 1769 (11 vols.); 1774 (London, 9 vols.); 1782, etc. (17 vols.);
1790 (33 vols.); 1790 (30 vols., or 35); 1788–93 (39 vols.); 1793–1800 (Didot, 18
vols.), and later editions from this same firm; Musset-Pathay, 1823–6.
Miscellaneous Works: 5 vols., 1767.
Posthumous Works: 1782, 1783; Œuvres inédites (Musset-Pathay), 1825, 1833;
Fragments inédits, etc., by A. de Bougy, 1853; Œuvres et Correspondance inédites
(Streckeisen-Moultou), 1861; Fragments inédits; Recherches biographiques et
littéraires, A. Jansen, 1882.
Works translated from the French, 10 vols., 1773–74.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
30
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Letters: Sur différents Sujets, 5 vols., 1749–53; Lettres nouvelles sur le motif de sa
retraite à la Campagne, adressées à M. de Malesherbes, 1780; Nouvelles lettres, 1789;
Lettres au citoyen Lenieps, etc., 1793 (?); Correspondance originale et inédite avec
Mme. Latour de Tranqueville et M. du Peyrou, 2 vols., 1803; Lettres inédites à Mme.
d’Epinay (see Memoirs of Mme. d’Epinay), 1818; Lettres de Voltaire et de Rousseau
à C. J. Panckoucke, 1828; Lettres inédites à M. M. Rey, 1858; Lettres à Mme. Dupin
(in Le Portefeuille de Mme. Dupin), 1884; Lettres inédites (correspondence with
Mme. Roy de Latour), published by H. de Rothschild, with preface by L. Claretie,
1892; Lettres (between Rousseau and “Henriette”), published by H. Buffenoir, 1902;
Correspondance avec Léonard Usteri, 1910.
Translations: Original letters to M. de Malesherbes, d’Alembert, Mme. la M. de
Luxembourg, etc., 1799, 1820; Eighteen letters to Mme. d’Houdetot, October
1757–March 1758, 1905.
Life, etc.: J. H. Fuessli, Remarks on the Writings and Conduct of Jean Jacques
Rousseau, 1767; Stäel-Holsteim (Baroness de Rocco), Letters on the Work and
Character of Jean Jacques Rousseau (translation), 1789, 1814; J. Morley, Rousseau,
1873, 1886; H. G. Graham, Rousseau (Foreign Classics for English Readers), 1882;
T. Davidson, Rousseau and Education according to Nature (Great Educators), vol. ix.,
1898; J. Texte, Jean Jacques Rousseau and the Cosmopolitan Spirit in Literature, etc.
(translation), 1899; H. H. Hudson, Rousseau and Naturalism in Life and Thought
(World’s Epoch Makers), 1903; F. Macdonald, Jean Jacques Rousseau, a new
criticism, 1906; J. C. Collins, Voltaire, Montesquieu, and Rousseau in England, 1908.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
31
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
THE SOCIAL CONTRACT Or PRINCIPLES OF POLITICAL
RIGHT
Fœderis æquas Dicamus leges. (Vergil, Æneid XI.)
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
32
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
FOREWORD
This little treatise is part of a longer work which I began years ago without realising
my limitations, and long since abandoned. Of the various fragments that might have
been extracted from what I wrote, this is the most considerable, and, I think, the least
unworthy of being offered to the public. The rest no longer exists.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
33
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
BOOK I
I mean to inquire if, in the civil order, there can be any sure and legitimate rule of
administration, men being taken as they are and laws as they might be. In this inquiry
I shall endeavour always to unite what right sanctions with what is prescribed by
interest, in order that justice and utility may in no case be divided.
I enter upon my task without proving the importance of the subject. I shall be asked if
I am a prince or a legislator, to write on politics. I answer that I am neither, and that is
why I do so. If I were a prince or a legislator, I should not waste time in saying what
wants doing; I should do it, or hold my peace.
As I was born a citizen of a free State, and a member of the Sovereign, I feel that,
however feeble the influence my voice can have on public affairs, the right of voting
on them makes it my duty to study them: and I am happy, when I reflect upon
governments, to find my inquiries always furnish me with new reasons for loving that
of my own country.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
34
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER I
Subject Of The First Book
Man is born free; and everywhere he is in chains. One thinks himself the master of
others, and still remains a greater slave than they. How did this change come about? I
do not know. What can make it legitimate? That question I think I can answer.
If I took into account only force, and the effects derived from it, I should say: “As
long as a people is compelled to obey, and obeys, it does well; as soon as it can shake
off the yoke, and shakes it off, it does still better; for, regaining its liberty by the same
right as took it away, either it is justified in resuming it, or there was no justification
for those who took it away.” But the social order is a sacred right which is the basis of
all other rights. Nevertheless, this right does not come from nature, and must therefore
be founded on conventions. Before coming to that, I have to prove what I have just
asserted.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
35
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER II
The First Societies
The most ancient of all societies, and the only one that is natural, is the family: and
even so the children remain attached to the father only so long as they need him for
their preservation. As soon as this need ceases, the natural bond is dissolved. The
children, released from the obedience they owed to the father, and the father, released
from the care he owed his children, return equally to independence. If they remain
united, they continue so no longer naturally, but voluntarily; and the family itself is
then maintained only by convention.
This common liberty results from the nature of man. His first law is to provide for his
own preservation, his first cares are those which he owes to himself; and, as soon as
he reaches years of discretion, he is the sole judge of the proper means of preserving
himself, and consequently becomes his own master.
The family then may be called the first model of political societies: the ruler
corresponds to the father, and the people to the children; and all, being born free and
equal, alienate their liberty only for their own advantage. The whole difference is that,
in the family, the love of the father for his children repays him for the care he takes of
them, while, in the State, the pleasure of commanding takes the place of the love
which the chief cannot have for the peoples under him.
Grotius denies that all human power is established in favour of the governed, and
quotes slavery as an example. His usual method of reasoning is constantly to establish
right by fact.1 It would be possible to employ a more logical method, but none could
be more favourable to tyrants.
It is then, according to Grotius, doubtful whether the human race belongs to a hundred
men, or that hundred men to the human race: and, throughout his book, he seems to
incline to the former alternative, which is also the view of Hobbes. On this showing,
the human species is divided into so many herds of cattle, each with its ruler, who
keeps guard over them for the purpose of devouring them.
As a shepherd is of a nature superior to that of his flock, the shepherds of men, i. e.
their rulers, are of a nature superior to that of the peoples under them. Thus, Philo tells
us, the Emperor Caligula reasoned, concluding equally well either that kings were
gods, or that men were beasts.
The reasoning of Caligula agrees with that of Hobbes and Grotius. Aristotle, before
any of them, had said that men are by no means equal naturally, but that some are
born for slavery, and others for dominion.
Aristotle was right; but he took the effect for the cause. Nothing can be more certain
than that every man born in slavery is born for slavery. Slaves lose everything in their
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
36
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
chains, even the desire of escaping from them: they love their servitude, as the
comrades of Ulysses loved their brutish condition.2 If then there are slaves by nature,
it is because there have been slaves against nature. Force made the first slaves, and
their cowardice perpetuated the condition.
I have said nothing of King Adam, or Emperor Noah, father of the three great
monarchs who shared out the universe, like the children of Saturn, whom some
scholars have recognised in them. I trust to getting due thanks for my moderation; for,
being a direct descendant of one of these princes, perhaps of the eldest branch, how
do I know that a verification of titles might not leave me the legitimate king of the
human race? In any case, there can be no doubt that Adam was sovereign of the
world, as Robinson Crusoe was of his island, as long as he was its only inhabitant;
and this empire had the advantage that the monarch, safe on his throne, had no
rebellions, wars, or conspirators to fear.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
37
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER III
The Right Of The Strongest
The strongest is never strong enough to be always the master, unless he transforms
strength into right, and obedience into duty. Hence the right of the strongest, which,
though to all seeming meant ironically, is really laid down as a fundamental principle.
But are we never to have an explanation of this phrase? Force is a physical power, and
I fail to see what moral effect it can have. To yield to force is an act of necessity, not
of will—at the most, an act of prudence. In what sense can it be a duty?
Suppose for a moment that this so-called “right” exists. I maintain that the sole result
is a mass of inexplicable nonsense. For, if force creates right, the effect changes with
the cause: every force that is greater than the first succeeds to its right. As soon as it is
possible to disobey with impunity, disobedience is legitimate; and, the strongest being
always in the right, the only thing that matters is to act so as to become the strongest.
But what kind of right is that which perishes when force fails? If we must obey
perforce, there is no need to obey because we ought; and if we are not forced to obey,
we are under no obligation to do so. Clearly, the word “right” adds nothing to force:
in this connection, it means absolutely nothing.
Obey the powers that be. If this means yield to force, it is a good precept, but
superfluous: I can answer for its never being violated. All power comes from God, I
admit; but so does all sickness: does that mean that we are forbidden to call in the
doctor? A brigand surprises me at the edge of a wood: must I not merely surrender my
purse on compulsion; but, even if I could withhold it, am I in conscience bound to
give it up? For certainly the pistol he holds is also a power.
Let us then admit that force does not create right, and that we are obliged to obey only
legitimate powers. In that case, my original question recurs.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
38
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER IV
Slavery
Since no man has a natural authority over his fellow, and force creates no right, we
must conclude that conventions form the basis of all legitimate authority among men.
If an individual, says Grotius, can alienate his liberty and make himself the slave of a
master, why could not a whole people do the same and make itself subject to a king?
There are in this passage plenty of ambiguous words which would need explaining;
but let us confine ourselves to the word alienate. To alienate is to give or to sell. Now,
a man who becomes the slave of another does not give himself; he sells himself, at the
least for his subsistence: but for what does a people sell itself? A king is so far from
furnishing his subjects with their subsistence that he gets his own only from them;
and, according to Rabelais, kings do not live on nothing. Do subjects then give their
persons on condition that the king takes their goods also? I fail to see what they have
left to preserve.
It will be said that the despot assures his subjects civil tranquillity. Granted; but what
do they gain, if the wars his ambition brings down upon them, his insatiable avidity,
and the vexatious conduct of his ministers press harder on them than their own
dissensions would have done? What do they gain, if the very tranquillity they enjoy is
one of their miseries? Tranquillity is found also in dungeons; but is that enough to
make them desirable places to live in? The Greeks imprisoned in the cave of the
Cyclops lived there very tranquilly, while they were awaiting their turn to be
devoured.
To say that a man gives himself gratuitously, is to say what is absurd and
inconceivable; such an act is null and illegitimate, from the mere fact that he who
does it is out of his mind. To say the same of a whole people is to suppose a people of
madmen; and madness creates no right.
Even if each man could alienate himself, he could not alienate his children: they are
born men and free; their liberty belongs to them, and no one but they has the right to
dispose of it. Before they come to years of discretion, the father can, in their name, lay
down conditions for their preservation and well-being, but he cannot give them
irrevocably and without conditions: such a gift is contrary to the ends of nature, and
exceeds the rights of paternity. It would therefore be necessary, in order to legitimise
an arbitrary government, that in every generation the people should be in a position to
accept or reject it; but, were this so, the government would be no longer arbitrary.
To renounce liberty is to renounce being a man, to surrender the rights of humanity
and even its duties. For him who renounces everything no indemnity is possible. Such
a renunciation is incompatible with man’s nature; to remove all liberty from his will is
to remove all morality from his acts. Finally, it is an empty and contradictory
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
39
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
convention that sets up, on the one side, absolute authority, and, on the other,
unlimited obedience. Is it not clear that we can be under no obligation to a person
from whom we have the right to exact everything? Does not this condition alone, in
the absence of equivalence or exchange, in itself involve the nullity of the act? For
what right can my slave have against me, when all that he has belongs to me, and, his
right being mine, this right of mine against myself is a phrase devoid of meaning?
Grotius and the rest find in war another origin for the so-called right of slavery. The
victor having, as they hold, the right of killing the vanquished, the latter can buy back
his life at the price of his liberty; and this convention is the more legitimate because it
is to the advantage of both parties.
But it is clear that this supposed right to kill the conquered is by no means deducible
from the state of war. Men, from the mere fact that, while they are living in their
primitive independence, they have no mutual relations stable enough to constitute
either the state of peace or the state of war, cannot be naturally enemies. War is
constituted by a relation between things, and not between persons; and, as the state of
war cannot arise out of simple personal relations, but only out of real relations, private
war, or war of man with man, can exist neither in the state of nature, where there is no
constant property, nor in the social state, where everything is under the authority of
the laws.
Individual combats, duels and encounters, are acts which cannot constitute a state;
while the private wars, authorised by the Establishments of Louis IX, King of France,
and suspended by the Peace of God, are abuses of feudalism, in itself an absurd
system if ever there was one, and contrary to the principles of natural right and to all
good polity.
War then is a relation, not between man and man, but between State and State, and
individuals are enemies only accidentally, not as men, nor even as citizens,1 but as
soldiers; not as members of their country, but as its defenders. Finally, each State can
have for enemies only other States, and not men; for between things disparate in
nature there can be no real relation.
Furthermore, this principle is in conformity with the established rules of all times and
the constant practice of all civilised peoples. Declarations of war are intimations less
to powers than to their subjects. The foreigner, whether king, individual, or people,
who robs, kills or detains the subjects, without declaring war on the prince, is not an
enemy, but a brigand. Even in real war, a just prince, while laying hands, in the
enemy’s country, on all that belongs to the public, respects the lives and goods of
individuals: he respects rights on which his own are founded. The object of the war
being the destruction of the hostile State, the other side has a right to kill its defenders,
while they are bearing arms; but as soon as they lay them down and surrender, they
cease to be enemies or instruments of the enemy, and become once more merely men,
whose life no one has any right to take. Sometimes it is possible to kill the State
without killing a single one of its members; and war gives no right which is not
necessary to the gaining of its object. These principles are not those of Grotius: they
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
40
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
are not based on the authority of poets, but derived from the nature of reality and
based on reason.
The right of conquest has no foundation other than the right of the strongest. If war
does not give the conqueror the right to massacre the conquered peoples, the right to
enslave them cannot be based upon a right which does not exist. No one has a right to
kill an enemy except when he cannot make him a slave, and the right to enslave him
cannot therefore be derived from the right to kill him. It is accordingly an unfair
exchange to make him buy at the price of his liberty his life, over which the victor
holds no right. Is it not clear that there is a vicious circle in founding the right of life
and death on the right of slavery, and the right of slavery on the right of life and
death?
Even if we assume this terrible right to kill everybody, I maintain that a slave made in
war, or a conquered people, is under no obligation to a master, except to obey him as
far as he is compelled to do so. By taking an equivalent for his life, the victor has not
done him a favour; instead of killing him without profit, he has killed him usefully. So
far then is he from acquiring over him any authority in addition to that of force, that
the state of war continues to subsist between them: their mutual relation is the effect
of it, and the usage of the right of war does not imply a treaty of peace. A convention
has indeed been made; but this convention, so far from destroying the state of war,
presupposes its continuance.
So, from whatever aspect we regard the question, the right of slavery is null and void,
not only as being illegitimate, but also because it is absurd and meaningless. The
words slave and right contradict each other, and are mutually exclusive. It will always
be equally foolish for a man to say to a man or to a people: “I make with you a
convention wholly at your expense and wholly to my advantage; I shall keep it as
long as I like, and you will keep it as long as I like.”
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
41
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER V
That We Must Always Go Back To A First Convention
Even if I granted all that I have been refuting, the friends of despotism would be no
better off. There will always be a great difference between subduing a multitude and
ruling a society. Even if scattered individuals were successively enslaved by one man,
however numerous they might be, I still see no more than a master and his slaves, and
certainly not a people and its ruler; I see what may be termed an aggregation, but not
an association; there is as yet neither public good nor body politic. The man in
question, even if he has enslaved half the world, is still only an individual; his interest,
apart from that of others, is still a purely private interest. If this same man comes to
die, his empire, after him, remains scattered and without unity, as an oak falls and
dissolves into a heap of ashes when the fire has consumed it.
A people, says Grotius, can give itself to a king. Then, according to Grotius, a people
is a people before it gives itself. The gift is itself a civil act, and implies public
deliberation. It would be better, before examining the act by which a people gives
itself to a king, to examine that by which it has become a people; for this act, being
necessarily prior to the other, is the true foundation of society.
Indeed, if there were no prior convention, where, unless the election were unanimous,
would be the obligation on the minority to submit to the choice of the majority? How
have a hundred men who wish for a master the right to vote on behalf of ten who do
not? The law of majority voting is itself something established by convention, and
presupposes unanimity, on one occasion at least.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
42
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER VI
The Social Compact
I suppose men to have reached the point at which the obstacles in the way of their
preservation in the state of nature show their power of resistance to be greater than the
resources at the disposal of each individual for his maintenance in that state. That
primitive condition can then subsist no longer; and the human race would perish
unless it changed its manner of existence.
But, as men cannot engender new forces, but only unite and direct existing ones, they
have no other means of preserving themselves than the formation, by aggregation, of
a sum of forces great enough to overcome the resistance. These they have to bring
into play by means of a single motive power, and cause to act in concert.
This sum of forces can arise only where several persons come together: but, as the
force and liberty of each man are the chief instruments of his self-preservation, how
can he pledge them without harming his own interests, and neglecting the care he
owes to himself? This difficulty, in its bearing on my present subject, may be stated in
the following terms—
“The problem is to find a form of association which will defend and protect with the
whole common force the person and goods of each associate, and in which each,
while uniting himself with all, may still obey himself alone, and remain as free as
before.” This is the fundamental problem of which the Social Contract provides the
solution.
The clauses of this contract are so determined by the nature of the act that the slightest
modification would make them vain and ineffective; so that, although they have
perhaps never been formally set forth, they are everywhere the same and everywhere
tacitly admitted and recognised, until, on the violation of the social compact, each
regains his original rights and resumes his natural liberty, while losing the
conventional liberty in favour of which he renounced it.
These clauses, properly understood, may be reduced to one—the total alienation of
each associate, together with all his rights, to the whole community; for, in the first
place, as each gives himself absolutely, the conditions are the same for all; and, this
being so, no one has any interest in making them burdensome to others.
Moreover, the alienation being without reserve, the union is as perfect as it can be,
and no associate has anything more to demand: for, if the individuals retained certain
rights, as there would be no common superior to decide between them and the public,
each, being on one point his own judge, would ask to be so on all; the state of nature
would thus continue, and the association would necessarily become inoperative or
tyrannical.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
43
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Finally, each man, in giving himself to all, gives himself to nobody; and as there is no
associate over whom he does not acquire the same right as he yields others over
himself, he gains an equivalent for everything he loses, and an increase of force for
the preservation of what he has.
If then we discard from the social compact what is not of its essence, we shall find
that it reduces itself to the following terms—
Each of us puts his person and all his power in common under the supreme direction
of the general will, and, in our corporate capacity, we receive each member as an
indivisible part of the whole.
At once, in place of the individual personality of each contracting party, this act of
association creates a moral and collective body, composed of as many members as the
assembly contains votes, and receiving from this act its unity, its common identity, its
life and its will. This public person, so formed by the union of all other persons,
formerly took the name of city,1 and now takes that of Republic or body politic; it is
called by its members State when passive, Sovereign when active, and Power when
compared with others like itself. Those who are associated in it take collectively the
name of people, and severally are called citizens, as sharing in the sovereign power,
and subjects, as being under the laws of the State. But these terms are often confused
and taken one for another: it is enough to know how to distinguish them when they
are being used with precision.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
44
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER VII
The Sovereign
This formula shows us that the act of association comprises a mutual undertaking
between the public and the individuals, and that each individual, in making a contract,
as we may say, with himself, is bound in a double capacity; as a member of the
Sovereign he is bound to the individuals, and as a member of the State to the
Sovereign. But the maxim of civil right, that no one is bound by undertakings made to
himself, does not apply in this case; for there is a great difference between incurring
an obligation to yourself and incurring one to a whole of which you form a part.
Attention must further be called to the fact that public deliberation, while competent
to bind all the subjects to the Sovereign, because of the two different capacities in
which each of them may be regarded, cannot, for the opposite reason, bind the
Sovereign to itself; and that it is consequently against the nature of the body politic
for the Sovereign to impose on itself a law which it cannot infringe. Being able to
regard itself in only one capacity, it is in the position of an individual who makes a
contract with himself; and this makes it clear that there neither is nor can be any kind
of fundamental law binding on the body of the people—not even the social contract
itself. This does not mean that the body politic cannot enter into undertakings with
others, provided the contract is not infringed by them; for in relation to what is
external to it, it becomes a simple being, an individual.
But the body politic or the Sovereign, drawing its being wholly from the sanctity of
the contract, can never bind itself, even to an outsider, to do anything derogatory to
the original act, for instance, to alienate any part of itself, or to submit to another
Sovereign. Violation of the act by which it exists would be self-annihilation; and that
which is itself nothing can create nothing.
As soon as this multitude is so united in one body, it is impossible to offend against
one of the members without attacking the body, and still more to offend against the
body without the members resenting it. Duty and interest therefore equally oblige the
two contracting parties to give each other help; and the same men should seek to
combine, in their double capacity, all the advantages dependent upon that capacity.
Again, the Sovereign, being formed wholly of the individuals who compose it, neither
has nor can have any interest contrary to theirs; and consequently the sovereign power
need give no guarantee to its subjects, because it is impossible for the body to wish to
hurt all its members. We shall also see later on that it cannot hurt any in particular.
The Sovereign, merely by virtue of what it is, is always what it should be.
This, however, is not the case with the relation of the subjects to the Sovereign,
which, despite the common interest, would have no security that they would fulfil
their undertakings, unless it found means to assure itself of their fidelity.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
45
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
In fact, each individual, as a man, may have a particular will contrary or dissimilar to
the general will which he has as a citizen. His particular interest may speak to him
quite differently from the common interest: his absolute and naturally independent
existence may make him look upon what he owes to the common cause as a
gratuitous contribution, the loss of which will do less harm to others than the payment
of it is burdensome to himself; and, regarding the moral person which constitutes the
State as a persona ficta, because not a man, he may wish to enjoy the rights of
citizenship without being ready to fulfil the duties of a subject. The continuance of
such an injustice could not but prove the undoing of the body politic.
In order then that the social compact may not be an empty formula, it tacitly includes
the undertaking, which alone can give force to the rest, that whoever refuses to obey
the general will shall be compelled to do so by the whole body. This means nothing
less than that he will be forced to be free; for this is the condition which, by giving
each citizen to his country, secures him against all personal dependence. In this lies
the key to the working of the political machine; this alone legitimises civil
undertakings, which, without it, would be absurd, tyrannical, and liable to the most
frightful abuses.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
46
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER VIII
The Civil State
The passage from the state of nature to the civil state produces a very remarkable
change in man, by substituting justice for instinct in his conduct, and giving his
actions the morality they had formerly lacked. Then only, when the voice of duty
takes the place of physical impulses and right of appetite, does man, who so far had
considered only himself, find that he is forced to act on different principles, and to
consult his reason before listening to his inclinations. Although, in this state, he
deprives himself of some advantages which he got from nature, he gains in return
others so great, his faculties are so stimulated and developed, his ideas so extended,
his feelings so ennobled, and his whole soul so uplifted, that, did not the abuses of this
new condition often degrade him below that which he left, he would be bound to bless
continually the happy moment which took him from it for ever, and, instead of a
stupid and unimaginative animal, made him an intelligent being and a man.
Let us draw up the whole account in terms easily commensurable. What man loses by
the social contract is his natural liberty and an unlimited right to everything he tries to
get and succeeds in getting; what he gains is civil liberty and the proprietorship of all
he possesses. If we are to avoid mistake in weighing one against the other, we must
clearly distinguish natural liberty, which is bounded only by the strength of the
individual, from civil liberty, which is limited by the general will; and possession,
which is merely the effect of force or the right of the first occupier, from property,
which can be founded only on a positive title.
We might, over and above all this, add, to what man acquires in the civil state, moral
liberty, which alone makes him truly master of himself; for the mere impulse of
appetite is slavery, while obedience to a law which we prescribe to ourselves is
liberty. But I have already said too much on this head, and the philosophical meaning
of the word liberty does not now concern us.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
47
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER IX
Real Property
Each member of the community gives himself to it, at the moment of its foundation,
just as he is, with all the resources at his command, including the goods he possesses.
This act does not make possession, in changing hands, change its nature, and become
property in the hands of the Sovereign; but, as the forces of the city are incomparably
greater than those of an individual, public possession is also, in fact, stronger and
more irrevocable, without being any more legitimate, at any rate from the point of
view of foreigners. For the State, in relation to its members, is master of all their
goods by the social contract, which, within the State, is the basis of all rights; but, in
relation to other powers, it is so only by the right of the first occupier, which it holds
from its members.
The right of the first occupier, though more real than the right of the strongest,
becomes a real right only when the right of property has already been established.
Every man has naturally a right to everything he needs; but the positive act which
makes him proprietor of one thing excludes him from everything else. Having his
share, he ought to keep to it, and can have no further right against the community.
This is why the right of the first occupier, which in the state of nature is so weak,
claims the respect of every man in civil society. In this right we are respecting not so
much what belongs to another as what does not belong to ourselves.
In general, to establish the right of the first occupier over a plot of ground, the
following conditions are necessary: first, the land must not yet be inhabited; secondly,
a man must occupy only the amount he needs for his subsistence; and, in the third
place, possession must be taken, not by an empty ceremony, but by labour and
cultivation, the only sign of proprietorship that should be respected by others, in
default of a legal title.
In granting the right of first occupancy to necessity and labour, are we not really
stretching it as far as it can go? Is it possible to leave such a right unlimited? Is it to be
enough to set foot on a plot of common ground, in order to be able to call yourself at
once the master of it? Is it to be enough that a man has the strength to expel others for
a moment, in order to establish his right to prevent them from ever returning? How
can a man or a people seize an immense territory and keep it from the rest of the
world except by a punishable usurpation, since all others are being robbed, by such an
act, of the place of habitation and the means of subsistence which nature gave them in
common? When Nuñez Balbao, standing on the sea-shore, took possession of the
South Seas and the whole of South America in the name of the crown of Castille, was
that enough to dispossess all their actual inhabitants, and to shut out from them all the
princes of the world? On such a showing, these ceremonies are idly multiplied, and
the Catholic King need only take possession all at once, from his apartment, of the
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
48
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
whole universe, merely making a subsequent reservation about what was already in
the possession of other princes.
We can imagine how the lands of individuals, where they were contiguous and came
to be united, became the public territory, and how the right of Sovereignty, extending
from the subjects over the lands they held, became at once real and personal. The
possessors were thus made more dependent, and the forces at their command used to
guarantee their fidelity. The advantage of this does not seem to have been felt by
ancient monarchs, who called themselves King of the Persians, Scythians, or
Macedonians, and seemed to regard themselves more as rulers of men than as masters
of a country. Those of the present day more cleverly call themselves Kings of France,
Spain, England, etc.: thus holding the land, they are quite confident of holding the
inhabitants.
The peculiar fact about this alienation is that, in taking over the goods of individuals,
the community, so far from despoiling them, only assures them legitimate possession,
and changes usurpation into a true right and enjoyment into proprietorship. Thus the
possessors, being regarded as depositaries of the public good, and having their rights
respected by all the members of the State and maintained against foreign aggression
by all its forces, have, by a cession which benefits both the public and still more
themselves, acquired, so to speak, all that they gave up. This paradox may easily be
explained by the distinction between the rights which the Sovereign and the proprietor
have over the same estate, as we shall see later on.
It may also happen that men begin to unite one with another before they possess
anything, and that, subsequently occupying a tract of country which is enough for all,
they enjoy it in common, or share it out among themselves, either equally or
according to a scale fixed by the Sovereign. However the acquisition be made, the
right which each individual has to his own estate is always subordinate to the right
which the community has over all: without this, there would be neither stability in the
social tie, nor real force in the exercise of Sovereignty.
I shall end this chapter and this book by remarking on a fact on which the whole
social system should rest: i. e. that, instead of destroying natural inequality, the
fundamental compact substitutes, for such physical inequality as nature may have set
up between men, an equality that is moral and legitimate, and that men, who may be
unequal in strength or intelligence, become every one equal by convention and legal
right.1
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
49
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
BOOK II
CHAPTER I
That Sovereignty Is Inalienable
The first and most important deduction from the principles we have so far laid down
is that the general will alone can direct the State according to the object for which it
was instituted, i. e. the common good: for if the clashing of particular interests made
the establishment of societies necessary, the agreement of these very interests made it
possible. The common element in these different interests is what forms the social tie;
and, were there no point of agreement between them all, no society could exist. It is
solely on the basis of this common interest that every society should be governed.
I hold then that Sovereignty, being nothing less than the exercise of the general will,
can never be alienated, and that the Sovereign, who is no less than a collective being,
cannot be represented except by himself: the power indeed may be transmitted, but
not the will.
In reality, if it is not impossible for a particular will to agree on some point with the
general will, it is at least impossible for the agreement to be lasting and constant; for
the particular will tends, by its very nature, to partiality, while the general will tends
to equality. It is even more impossible to have any guarantee of this agreement; for
even if it should always exist, it would be the effect not of art, but of chance. The
Sovereign may indeed say: “I now will actually what this man wills, or at least what
he says he wills”; but it cannot say: “What he wills tomorrow, I too shall will”
because it is absurd for the will to bind itself for the future, nor is it incumbent on any
will to consent to anything that is not for the good of the being who wills. If then the
people promises simply to obey, by that very act it dissolves itself and loses what
makes it a people; the moment a master exists, there is no longer a Sovereign, and
from that moment the body politic has ceased to exist.
This does not mean that the commands of the rulers cannot pass for general wills, so
long as the Sovereign, being free to oppose them, offers no opposition. In such a case,
universal silence is taken to imply the consent of the people. This will be explained
later on.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
50
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER II
That Sovereignty Is Indivisible
Sovereignty, for the same reason as makes it inalienable, is indivisible; for will either
is, or is not, general;1 it is the will either of the body of the people, or only of a part of
it. In the first case, the will, when declared, is an act of Sovereignty and constitutes
law: in the second, it is merely a particular will, or act of magistracy—at the most a
decree.
But our political theorists, unable to divide Sovereignty in principle, divide it
according to its object: into force and will; into legislative power and executive
power; into rights of taxation, justice and war; into internal administration and power
of foreign treaty. Sometimes they confuse all these sections, and sometimes they
distinguish them; they turn the Sovereign into a fantastic being composed of several
connected pieces: it is as if they were making man of several bodies, one with eyes,
one with arms, another with feet, and each with nothing besides. We are told that the
jugglers of Japan dismember a child before the eyes of the spectators; then they throw
all the members into the air one after another, and the child falls down alive and
whole. The conjuring tricks of our political theorists are very like that; they first
dismember the body politic by an illusion worthy of a fair, and then join it together
again we know not how.
This error is due to a lack of exact notions concerning the Sovereign authority, and to
taking for parts of it what are only emanations from it. Thus, for example, the acts of
declaring war and making peace have been regarded as acts of Sovereignty; but this is
not the case, as these acts do not constitute law, but merely the application of a law, a
particular act which decides how the law applies, as we shall see clearly when the idea
attached to the word law has been defined.
If we examined the other divisions in the same manner, we should find that, whenever
Sovereignty seems to be divided, there is an illusion: the rights which are taken as
being part of Sovereignty are really all subordinate, and always imply supreme wills
of which they only sanction the execution.
It would be impossible to estimate the obscurity this lack of exactness has thrown
over the decisions of writers who have dealt with political right, when they have used
the principles laid down by them to pass judgment on the respective rights of kings
and peoples. Every one can see, in Chapters III and IV of the First Book of Grotius,
how the learned man and his translator, Barbeyrac, entangle and tie themselves up in
their own sophistries, for fear of saying too little or too much of what they think, and
so offending the interests they have to conciliate. Grotius, a refugee in France, ill-
content with his own country, and desirous of paying his court to Louis XIII, to whom
his book is dedicated, spares no pains to rob the peoples of all their rights and invest
kings with them by every conceivable artifice. This would also have been much to the
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
51
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
taste of Barbeyrac, who dedicated his translation to George I of England. But
unfortunately the expulsion of James II, which he called his “abdication,” compelled
him to use all reserve, to shuffle and to tergiversate, in order to avoid making William
out a usurper. If these two writers had adopted the true principles, all difficulties
would have been removed, and they would have been always consistent; but it would
have been a sad truth for them to tell, and would have paid court for them to no-one
save the people. Moreover, truth is no road to fortune, and the people dispenses
neither ambassadorships, nor professorships, nor pensions.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
52
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER III
Whether The General Will Is Fallible
It follows from what has gone before that the general will is always right and tends to
the public advantage; but it does not follow that the deliberations of the people are
always equally correct. Our will is always for our own good, but we do not always see
what that is; the people is never corrupted, but it is often deceived, and on such
occasions only does it seem to will what is bad.
There is often a great deal of difference between the will of all and the general will;
the latter considers only the common interest, while the former takes private interest
into account, and is no more than a sum of particular wills: but take away from these
same wills the pluses and minuses that cancel one another,1 and the general will
remains as the sum of the differences.
If, when the people, being furnished with adequate information, held its deliberations,
the citizens had no communication one with another, the grand total of the small
differences would always give the general will, and the decision would always be
good. But when factions arise, and partial associations are formed at the expense of
the great association, the will of each of these associations becomes general in relation
to its members, while it remains particular in relation to the State: it may then be said
that there are no longer as many votes as there are men, but only as many as there are
associations. The differences become less numerous and give a less general result.
Lastly, when one of these associations is so great as to prevail over all the rest, the
result is no longer a sum of small differences, but a single difference; in this case
there is no longer a general will, and the opinion which prevails is purely particular.
It is therefore essential, if the general will is to be able to express itself, that there
should be no partial society within the State, and that each citizen should think only
his own thoughts:1 which was indeed the sublime and unique system established by
the great Lycurgus. But if there are partial societies, it is best to have as many as
possible and to prevent them from being unequal, as was done by Solon, Numa and
Servius. These precautions are the only ones that can guarantee that the general will
shall be always enlightened, and that the people shall in no way deceive itself.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
53
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER IV
The Limits Of The Sovereign Power
If the State is a moral person whose life is in the union of its members, and if the most
important of its cares is the care for its own preservation, it must have a universal and
compelling force, in order to move and dispose each part as may be most
advantageous to the whole. As nature gives each man absolute power over all his
members, the social compact gives the body politic absolute power over all its
members also; and it is this power which, under the direction of the general will,
bears, as I have said, the name of Sovereignty.
But, besides the public person, we have to consider the private persons composing it,
whose life and liberty are naturally independent of it. We are bound then to
distinguish clearly between the respective rights of the citizens and the Sovereign,1
and between the duties the former have to fulfil as subjects, and the natural rights they
should enjoy as men.
Each man alienates, I admit, by the social compact, only such part of his powers,
goods and liberty as it is important for the community to control; but it must also be
granted that the Sovereign is sole judge of what is important.
Every service a citizen can render the State he ought to render as soon as the
Sovereign demands it; but the Sovereign, for its part, cannot impose upon its subjects
any fetters that are useless to the community, nor can it even wish to do so; for no
more by the law of reason than by the law of nature can anything occur without a
cause.
The undertakings which bind us to the social body are obligatory only because they
are mutual; and their nature is such that in fulfilling them we cannot work for others
without working for ourselves. Why is it that the general will is always in the right,
and that all continually will the happiness of each one, unless it is because there is not
a man who does not think of “each” as meaning him, and consider himself in voting
for all? This proves that equality of rights and the idea of justice which such equality
creates originate in the preference each man gives to himself, and accordingly in the
very nature of man. It proves that the general will, to be really such, must be general
in its object as well as its essence; that it must both come from all and apply to all;
and that it loses its natural rectitude when it is directed to some particular and
determinate object, because in such a case we are judging of something foreign to us,
and have no true principle of equity to guide us.
Indeed, as soon as a question of particular fact or right arises on a point not previously
regulated by a general convention, the matter becomes contentious. It is a case in
which the individuals concerned are one party, and the public the other, but in which I
can see neither the law that ought to be followed nor the judge who ought to give the
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
54
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
decision. In such a case, it would be absurd to propose to refer the question to an
express decision of the general will, which can be only the conclusion reached by one
of the parties and in consequence will be, for the other party, merely an external and
particular will, inclined on this occasion to injustice and subject to error. Thus, just as
a particular will cannot stand for the general will, the general will, in turn, changes its
nature, when its object is particular, and, as general, cannot pronounce on a man or a
fact. When, for instance, the people of Athens nominated or displaced its rulers,
decreed honours to one, and imposed penalties on another, and, by a multitude of
particular decrees, exercised all the functions of government indiscriminately, it had
in such cases no longer a general will in the strict sense; it was acting no longer as
Sovereign, but as magistrate. This will seem contrary to current views; but I must be
given time to expound my own.
It should be seen from the foregoing that what makes the will general is less the
number of voters than the common interest uniting them; for, under this system, each
necessarily submits to the conditions he imposes on others: and this admirable
agreement between interest and justice gives to the common deliberations an
equitable character which at once vanishes when any particular question is discussed,
in the absence of a common interest to unite and identify the ruling of the judge with
that of the party.
From whatever side we approach our principle, we reach the same conclusion, that the
social compact sets up among the citizens an equality of such a kind, that they all bind
themselves to observe the same conditions and should therefore all enjoy the same
rights. Thus, from the very nature of the compact, every act of Sovereignty, i. e. every
authentic act of the general will, binds or favours all the citizens equally; so that the
Sovereign recognises only the body of the nation, and draws no distinctions between
those of whom it is made up. What, then, strictly speaking, is an act of Sovereignty? It
is not a convention between a superior and an inferior, but a convention between the
body and each of its members. It is legitimate, because based on the social contract,
and equitable, because common to all; useful, because it can have no other object than
the general good, and stable, because guaranteed by the public force and the supreme
power. So long as the subjects have to submit only to conventions of this sort, they
obey no-one but their own will; and to ask how far the respective rights of the
Sovereign and the citizens extend, is to ask up to what point the latter can enter into
undertakings with themselves, each with all, and all with each.
We can see from this that the sovereign power, absolute, sacred and inviolable as it is,
does not and cannot exceed the limits of general conventions, and that every man may
dispose at will of such goods and liberty as these conventions leave him; so that the
Sovereign never has a right to lay more charges on one subject than on another,
because, in that case, the question becomes particular, and ceases to be within its
competency.
When these distinctions have once been admitted, it is seen to be so untrue that there
is, in the social contract, any real renunciation on the part of the individuals, that the
position in which they find themselves as a result of the contract is really preferable to
that in which they were before. Instead of a renunciation, they have made an
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
55
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
advantageous exchange: instead of an uncertain and precarious way of living they
have got one that is better and more secure; instead of natural independence they have
got liberty, instead of the power to harm others security for themselves, and instead of
their strength, which others might overcome, a right which social union makes
invincible. Their very life, which they have devoted to the State, is by it constantly
protected; and when they risk it in the State’s defence, what more are they doing than
giving back what they have received from it? What are they doing that they would not
do more often and with greater danger in the state of nature, in which they would
inevitably have to fight battles at the peril of their lives in defence of that which is the
means of their preservation? All have indeed to fight when their country needs them;
but then no one has ever to fight for himself. Do we not gain something by running,
on behalf of what gives us our security, only some of the risks we should have to run
for ourselves, as soon as we lost it?
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
56
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER V
The Right Of Life And Death
The question is often asked how individuals, having no right to dispose of their own
lives, can transfer to the Sovereign a right which they do not possess. The difficulty of
answering this question seems to me to lie in its being wrongly stated. Every man has
a right to risk his own life in order to preserve it. Has it ever been said that a man who
throws himself out of the window to escape from a fire is guilty of suicide? Has such
a crime ever been laid to the charge of him who perishes in a storm because, when he
went on board, he knew of the danger?
The social treaty has for its end the preservation of the contracting parties. He who
wills the end wills the means also, and the means must involve some risks, and even
some losses. He who wishes to preserve his life at others’ expense should also, when
it is necessary, be ready to give it up for their sake. Furthermore, the citizen is no
longer the judge of the dangers to which the law desires him to expose himself; and
when the prince says to him: “It is expedient for the State that you should die,” he
ought to die, because it is only on that condition that he has been living in security up
to the present, and because his life is no longer a mere bounty of nature, but a gift
made conditionally by the State.
The death-penalty inflicted upon criminals may be looked on in much the same light:
it is in order that we may not fall victims to an assassin that we consent to die if we
ourselves turn assassins. In this treaty, so far from disposing of our own lives, we
think only of securing them, and it is not to be assumed that any of the parties then
expects to get hanged.
Again, every malefactor, by attacking social rights, becomes on forfeit a rebel and a
traitor to his country; by violating its laws he ceases to be a member of it; he even
makes war upon it. In such a case the preservation of the State is inconsistent with his
own, and one or the other must perish; in putting the guilty to death, we slay not so
much the citizen as an enemy. The trial and the judgment are the proofs that he has
broken the social treaty, and is in consequence no longer a member of the State.
Since, then, he has recognised himself to be such by living there, he must be removed
by exile as a violator of the compact, or by death as a public enemy; for such an
enemy is not a moral person, but merely a man; and in such a case the right of war is
to kill the vanquished.
But, it will be said, the condemnation of a criminal is a particular act. I admit it: but
such condemnation is not a function of the Sovereign; it is a right the Sovereign can
confer without being able itself to exert it. All my ideas are consistent, but I cannot
expound them all at once.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
57
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
We may add that frequent punishments are always a sign of weakness or remissness
on the part of the government. There is not a single ill-doer who could not be turned
to some good. The State has no right to put to death, even for the sake of making an
example, any one whom it can leave alive without danger.
The right of pardoning or exempting the guilty from a penalty imposed by the law and
pronounced by the judge belongs only to the authority which is superior to both judge
and law, i. e. the Sovereign; even its right in this matter is far from clear, and the cases
for exercising it are extremely rare. In a well-governed State, there are few
punishments, not because there are many pardons, but because criminals are rare; it is
when a State is in decay that the multitude of crimes is a guarantee of impunity.
Under the Roman Republic, neither the Senate nor the Consuls ever attempted to
pardon; even the people never did so, though it sometimes revoked its own decision.
Frequent pardons mean that crime will soon need them no longer, and no-one can
help seeing whither that leads. But I feel my heart protesting and restraining my pen;
let us leave these questions to the just man who has never offended, and would
himself stand in no need of pardon.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
58
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER VI
Law
By the social compact we have given the body politic existence and life; we have now
by legislation to give it movement and will. For the original act by which the body is
formed and united still in no respect determines what it ought to do for its
preservation.
What is well and in conformity with order is so by the nature of things and
independently of human conventions. All justice comes from God, who is its sole
source; but if we knew how to receive so high an inspiration, we should need neither
government nor laws. Doubtless, there is a universal justice emanating from reason
alone; but this justice, to be admitted among us, must be mutual. Humanly speaking,
in default of natural sanctions, the laws of justice are ineffective among men: they
merely make for the good of the wicked and the undoing of the just, when the just
man observes them towards everybody and nobody observes them towards him.
Conventions and laws are therefore needed to join rights to duties and refer justice to
its object. In the state of nature, where everything is common, I owe nothing to him
whom I have promised nothing; I recognise as belonging to others only what is of no
use to me. In the state of society all rights are fixed by law, and the case becomes
different.
But what, after all, is a law? As long as we remain satisfied with attaching purely
metaphysical ideas to the word, we shall go on arguing without arriving at an
understanding; and when we have defined a law of nature, we shall be no nearer the
definition of a law of the State.
I have already said that there can be no general will directed to a particular object.
Such an object must be either within or outside the State. If outside, a will which is
alien to it cannot be, in relation to it, general; if within, it is part of the State, and in
that case there arises a relation between whole and part which makes them two
separate beings, of which the part is one, and the whole minus the part the other. But
the whole minus a part cannot be the whole; and while this relation persists, there can
be no whole, but only two unequal parts; and it follows that the will of one is no
longer in any respect general in relation to the other.
But when the whole people decrees for the whole people, it is considering only itself;
and if a relation is then formed, it is between two aspects of the entire object, without
there being any division of the whole. In that case the matter about which the decree
is made is, like the decreeing will, general. This act is what I call a law.
When I say that the object of laws is always general, I mean that law considers
subjects en masse and actions in the abstract, and never a particular person or action.
Thus the law may indeed decree that there shall be privileges, but cannot confer them
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
59
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
on anybody by name. It may set up several classes of citizens, and even lay down the
qualifications for membership of these classes, but it cannot nominate such and such
persons as belonging to them; it may establish a monarchical government and
hereditary succession, but it cannot choose a king, or nominate a royal family. In a
word, no function which has a particular object belongs to the legislative power.
On this view, we at once see that it can no longer be asked whose business it is to
make laws, since they are acts of the general will; nor whether the prince is above the
law, since he is a member of the State; nor whether the law can be unjust, since no
one is unjust to himself; nor how we can be both free and subject to the laws, since
they are but registers of our wills.
We see further that, as the law unites universality of will with universality of object,
what a man, whoever he be, commands of his own motion cannot be a law; and even
what the Sovereign commands with regard to a particular matter is no nearer being a
law, but is a decree, an act, not of sovereignty, but of magistracy.
I therefore give the name ‘Republic’ to every State that is governed by laws, no matter
what the form of its administration may be: for only in such a case does the public
interest govern, and the res publica rank as a reality. Every legitimate government is
republican;1 what government is I will explain later on.
Laws are, properly speaking, only the conditions of civil association. The people,
being subject to the laws, ought to be their author: the conditions of the society ought
to be regulated solely by those who come together to form it. But how are they to
regulate them? Is it to be by common agreement, by a sudden inspiration? Has the
body politic an organ to declare its will? Who can give it the foresight to formulate
and announce its acts in advance? Or how is it to announce them in the hour of need?
How can a blind multitude, which often does not know what it wills, because it rarely
knows what is good for it, carry out for itself so great and difficult an enterprise as a
system of legislation? Of itself the people wills always the good, but of itself it by no
means always sees it. The general will is always in the right, but the judgment which
guides it is not always enlightened. It must be got to see objects as they are, and
sometimes as they ought to appear to it; it must be shown the good road it is in search
of, secured from the seductive influences of individual wills, taught to see times and
spaces as a series, and made to weigh the attractions of present and sensible
advantages against the danger of distant and hidden evils. The individuals see the
good they reject; the public wills the good it does not see. All stand equally in need of
guidance. The former must be compelled to bring their wills into conformity with
their reason; the latter must be taught to know what it wills. If that is done, public
enlightenment leads to the union of understanding and will in the social body: the
parts are made to work exactly together, and the whole is raised to its highest power.
This makes a legislator necessary.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
60
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER VII
The Legislator
In order to discover the rules of society best suited to nations, a superior intelligence
beholding all the passions of men without experiencing any of them would be needed.
This intelligence would have to be wholly unrelated to our nature, while knowing it
through and through; its happiness would have to be independent of us, and yet ready
to occupy itself with ours; and lastly, it would have, in the march of time, to look
forward to a distant glory, and, working in one century, to be able to enjoy in the
next.1 It would take gods to give men laws.
What Caligula argued from the facts, Plato, in the dialogue called the Politicus,
argued in defining the civil or kingly man, on the basis of right. But if great princes
are rare, how much more so are great legislators? The former have only to follow the
pattern which the latter have to lay down. The legislator is the engineer who invents
the machine, the prince merely the mechanic who sets it up and makes it go. “At the
birth of societies,” says Montesquieu, “the rulers of Republics establish institutions,
and afterwards the institutions mould the rulers.”2
He who dares to undertake the making of a people’s institutions ought to feel himself
capable, so to speak, of changing human nature, of transforming each individual, who
is by himself a complete and solitary whole, into part of a greater whole from which
he in a manner receives his life and being; of altering man’s constitution for the
purpose of strengthening it; and of substituting a partial and moral existence for the
physical and independent existence nature has conferred on us all. He must, in a word,
take away from man his own resources and give him instead new ones alien to him,
and incapable of being made use of without the help of other men. The more
completely these natural resources are annihilated, the greater and the more lasting are
those which he acquires, and the more stable and perfect the new institutions; so that
if each citizen is nothing and can do nothing without the rest, and the resources
acquired by the whole are equal or superior to the aggregate of the resources of all the
individuals, it may be said that legislation is at the highest possible point of
perfection.
The legislator occupies in every respect an extraordinary position in the State. If he
should do so by reason of his genius, he does so no less by reason of his office, which
is neither magistracy, nor Sovereignty. This office, which sets up the Republic,
nowhere enters into its constitution; it is an individual and superior function, which
has nothing in common with human empire; for if he who holds command over men
ought not to have command over the laws, he who has command over the laws ought
not any more to have it over men; or else his laws would be the ministers of his
passions and would often merely serve to perpetuate his injustices: his private aims
would inevitably mar the sanctity of his work.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
61
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
When Lycurgus gave laws to his country, he began by resigning the throne. It was the
custom of most Greek towns to entrust the establishment of their laws to foreigners.
The Republics of modern Italy in many cases followed this example; Geneva did the
same and profited by it.1 Rome, when it was most prosperous, suffered a revival of all
the crimes of tyranny, and was brought to the verge of destruction, because it put the
legislative authority and the sovereign power into the same hands.
Nevertheless, the decemvirs themselves never claimed the right to pass any law
merely on their own authority. “Nothing we propose to you,” they said to the people,
“can pass into law without your consent. Romans, be yourselves the authors of the
laws which are to make you happy.”
He, therefore, who draws up the laws has, or should have, no right of legislation, and
the people cannot, even if it wishes, deprive itself of this incommunicable right,
because, according to the fundamental compact, only the general will can bind the
individuals, and there can be no assurance that a particular will is in conformity with
the general will, until it has been put to the free vote of the people. This I have said
already; but it is worth while to repeat it.
Thus in the task of legislation we find together two things which appear to be
incompatible: an enterprise too difficult for human powers, and, for its execution, an
authority that is no authority.
There is a further difficulty that deserves attention. Wise men, if they try to speak
their language to the common herd instead of its own, cannot possibly make
themselves understood. There are a thousand kinds of ideas which it is impossible to
translate into popular language. Conceptions that are too general and objects that are
too remote are equally out of its range: each individual, having no taste for any other
plan of government than that which suits his particular interest, finds it difficult to
realise the advantages he might hope to draw from the continual privations good laws
impose. For a young people to be able to relish sound principles of political theory
and follow the fundamental rules of statecraft, the effect would have to become the
cause; the social spirit, which should be created by these institutions, would have to
preside over their very foundation; and men would have to be before law what they
should become by means of law. The legislator therefore, being unable to appeal to
either force or reason, must have recourse to an authority of a different order, capable
of constraining without violence and persuading without convincing.
This is what has, in all ages, compelled the fathers of nations to have recourse to
divine intervention and credit the gods with their own wisdom, in order that the
peoples, submitting to the laws of the State as to those of nature, and recognising the
same power in the formation of the city as in that of man, might obey freely, and bear
with docility the yoke of the public happiness.
This sublime reason, far above the range of the common herd, is that whose decisions
the legislator puts into the mouth of the immortals, in order to constrain by divine
authority those whom human prudence could not move.1 But it is not anybody who
can make the gods speak, or get himself believed when he proclaims himself their
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
62
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
interpreter. The great soul of the legislator is the only miracle that can prove his
mission. Any man may grave tablets of stone, or buy an oracle, or feign secret
intercourse with some divinity, or train a bird to whisper in his ear, or find other
vulgar ways of imposing on the people. He whose knowledge goes no further may
perhaps gather round him a band of fools; but he will never found an empire, and his
extravagances will quickly perish with him. Idle tricks form a passing tie; only
wisdom can make it lasting. The Judaic law, which still subsists, and that of the child
of Ishmael, which, for ten centuries, has ruled half the world, still proclaim the great
men who laid them down; and, while the pride of philosophy or the blind spirit of
faction sees in them no more than lucky impostures, the true political theorist admires,
in the institutions they set up, the great and powerful genius which presides over
things made to endure.
We should not, with Warburton, conclude from this that politics and religion have
among us a common object, but that, in the first periods of nations, the one is used as
an instrument for the other.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
63
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER VIII
The People
As, before putting up a large building, the architect surveys and sounds the site to see
if it will bear the weight, the wise legislator does not begin by laying down laws good
in themselves, but by investigating the fitness of the people, for which they are
destined, to receive them. Plato refused to legislate for the Arcadians and the
Cyrenæans, because he knew that both peoples were rich and could not put up with
equality; and good laws and bad men were found together in Crete, because Minos
had inflicted discipline on a people already burdened with vice.
A thousand nations have achieved earthly greatness, that could never have endured
good laws; even such as could have endured them could have done so only for a very
brief period of their long history. Most peoples, like most men, are docile only in
youth; as they grow old they become incorrigible. When once customs have become
established and prejudices inveterate, it is dangerous and useless to attempt their
reformation; the people, like the foolish and cowardly patients who rave at sight of the
doctor, can no longer bear that any one should lay hands on its faults to remedy them.
There are indeed times in the history of States when, just as some kinds of illness turn
men’s heads and make them forget the past, periods of violence and revolutions do to
peoples what these crises do to individuals: horror of the past takes the place of
forgetfulness, and the State, set on fire by civil wars, is born again, so to speak, from
its ashes, and takes on anew, fresh from the jaws of death, the vigour of youth. Such
were Sparta at the time of Lycurgus, Rome after the Tarquins, and, in modern times,
Holland and Switzerland after the expulsion of the tyrants.
But such events are rare; they are exceptions, the cause of which is always to be found
in the particular constitution of the State concerned. They cannot even happen twice
to the same people, for it can make itself free as long as it remains barbarous, but not
when the civic impulse has lost its vigour. Then disturbances may destroy it, but
revolutions cannot mend it: it needs a master, and not a liberator. Free peoples, be
mindful of this maxim: “Liberty may be gained, but can never be recovered.”
Youth is not infancy. There is for nations, as for men, a period of youth, or, shall we
say, maturity, before which they should not be made subject to laws; but the maturity
of a people is not always easily recognisable, and, if it is anticipated, the work is
spoilt. One people is amenable to discipline from the beginning; another, not after ten
centuries. Russia will never be really civilised, because it was civilised too soon. Peter
had a genius for imitation; but he lacked true genius, which is creative and makes all
from nothing. He did some good things, but most of what he did was out of place. He
saw that his people was barbarous, but did not see that it was not ripe for civilisation:
he wanted to civilise it when it needed only hardening. His first wish was to make
Germans or Englishmen, when he ought to have been making Russians; and he
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
64
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
prevented his subjects from ever becoming what they might have been by persuading
them that they were what they are not. In this fashion too a French teacher turns out
his pupil to be an infant prodigy, and for the rest of his life to be nothing whatsoever.
The empire of Russia will aspire to conquer Europe, and will itself be conquered. The
Tartars, its subjects or neighbours, will become its masters and ours, by a revolution
which I regard as inevitable. Indeed, all the kings of Europe are working in concert to
hasten its coming.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
65
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER IX
The People (Continued)
As nature has set bounds to the stature of a well-made man, and, outside those limits,
makes nothing but giants or dwarfs, similarly, for the constitution of a State to be at
its best, it is possible to fix limits that will make it neither too large for good
government, nor too small for self-maintenance. In every body politic there is a
maximum strength which it cannot exceed and which it only loses by increasing in
size. Every extension of the social tie means its relaxation; and, generally speaking, a
small State is stronger in proportion than a great one.
A thousand arguments could be advanced in favour of this principle. First, long
distances make administration more difficult, just as a weight becomes heavier at the
end of a longer lever. Administration therefore becomes more and more burdensome
as the distance grows greater; for, in the first place, each city has its own, which is
paid for by the people: each district its own, still paid for by the people: then comes
each province, and then the great governments, satrapies, and vice-royalties, always
costing more the higher you go, and always at the expense of the unfortunate people.
Last of all comes the supreme administration, which eclipses all the rest. All these
overcharges are a continual drain upon the subjects; so far from being better governed
by all these different orders, they are worse governed than if there were only a single
authority over them. In the meantime, there scarce remain resources enough to meet
emergencies; and, when recourse must be had to these, the State is always on the eve
of destruction.
This is not all; not only has the government less vigour and promptitude for securing
the observance of the laws, preventing nuisances, correcting abuses, and guarding
against seditious undertakings begun in distant places; the people has less affection
for its rulers, whom it never sees, for its country, which, to its eyes, seems like the
world, and for its fellow-citizens, most of whom are unknown to it. The same laws
cannot suit so many diverse provinces with different customs, situated in the most
various climates, and incapable of enduring a uniform government. Different laws
lead only to trouble and confusion among peoples which, living under the same rulers
and in constant communication one with another, intermingle and intermarry, and,
coming under the sway of new customs, never know if they can call their very
patrimony their own. Talent is buried, virtue unknown and vice unpunished, among
such a multitude of men who do not know one another, gathered together in one place
at the seat of the central administration. The leaders, overwhelmed with business, see
nothing for themselves; the State is governed by clerks. Finally, the measures which
have to be taken to maintain the general authority, which all these distant officials
wish to escape or to impose upon, absorb all the energy of the public, so that there is
none left for the happiness of the people. There is hardly enough to defend it when
need arises, and thus a body which is too big for its constitution gives way and falls
crushed under its own weight.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
66
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Again, the State must assure itself a safe foundation, if it is to have stability, and to be
able to resist the shocks it cannot help experiencing, as well as the efforts it will be
forced to make for its maintenance; for all peoples have a kind of centrifugal force
that makes them continually act one against another, and tend to aggrandise
themselves at their neighbours’ expense, like the vortices of Descartes. Thus the weak
run the risk of being soon swallowed up; and it is almost impossible for any one to
preserve itself except by putting itself in a state of equilibrium with all, so that the
pressure is on all sides practically equal.
It may therefore be seen that there are reasons for expansion and reasons for
contraction; and it is no small part of the statesman’s skill to hit between them the
mean that is most favourable to the preservation of the State. It may be said that the
reason for expansion, being merely external and relative, ought to be subordinate to
the reasons for contraction, which are internal and absolute. A strong and healthy
constitution is the first thing to look for; and it is better to count on the vigour which
comes of good government than on the resources a great territory furnishes.
It may be added that there have been known States so constituted that the necessity of
making conquests entered into their very constitution, and that, in order to maintain
themselves, they were forced to expand ceaselessly. It may be that they congratulated
themselves greatly on this fortunate necessity, which none the less indicated to them,
along with the limits of their greatness, the inevitable moment of their fall.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
67
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER X
The People (Continued)
A body politic may be measured in two ways—either by the extent of its territory, or
by the number of its people; and there is, between these two measurements, a right
relation which makes the State really great. The men make the State, and the territory
sustains the men; the right relation therefore is that the land should suffice for the
maintenance of the inhabitants, and that there should be as many inhabitants as the
land can maintain. In this proportion lies the maximum strength of a given number of
people; for, if there is too much land, it is troublesome to guard and inadequately
cultivated, produces more than is needed, and soon gives rise to wars of defence; if
there is not enough, the State depends on its neighbours for what it needs over and
above, and this soon gives rise to wars of offence. Every people, to which its situation
gives no choice save that between commerce and war, is weak in itself: it depends on
its neighbours, and on circumstances; its existence can never be more than short and
uncertain. It either conquers others, and changes its situation, or it is conquered and
becomes nothing. Only insignificance or greatness can keep it free.
No fixed relation can be stated between the extent of territory and the population that
are adequate one to the other, both because of the differences in the quality of land, in
its fertility, in the nature of its products, and in the influence of climate, and because
of the different tempers of those who inhabit it; for some in a fertile country consume
little, and others on an ungrateful soil much. The greater or less fecundity of women,
the conditions that are more or less favourable in each country to the growth of
population, and the influence the legislator can hope to exercise by his institutions,
must also be taken into account. The legislator therefore should not go by what he
sees, but by what he foresees; he should stop not so much at the state in which he
actually finds the population, as at that to which it ought naturally to attain. Lastly,
there are countless cases in which the particular local circumstances demand or allow
the acquisition of a greater territory than seems necessary. Thus, expansion will be
great in a mountainous country, where the natural products, i. e. woods and pastures,
need less labour, where we know from experience that women are more fertile than in
the plains, and where a great expanse of slope affords only a small level tract that can
be counted on for vegetation. On the other hand, contraction is possible on the coast,
even in lands of rocks and nearly barren sands, because there fishing makes up to a
great extent for the lack of land-produce, because the inhabitants have to congregate
together more in order to repel pirates, and further because it is easier to unburden the
country of its superfluous inhabitants by means of colonies.
To these conditions of law-giving must be added one other which, though it cannot
take the place of the rest, renders them all useless when it is absent. This is the
enjoyment of peace and plenty; for the moment at which a State sets its house in order
is, like the moment when a battalion is forming up, that when its body is least capable
of offering resistance and easiest to destroy. A better resistance could be made at a
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
68
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
time of absolute disorganisation than at a moment of fermentation, when each is
occupied with his own position and not with the danger. If war, famine, or sedition
arises at this time of crisis, the State will inevitably be overthrown.
Not that many governments have not been set up during such storms; but in such
cases these governments are themselves the State’s destroyers. Usurpers always bring
about or select troublous times to get passed, under cover of the public terror,
destructive laws, which the people would never adopt in cold blood. The moment
chosen is one of the surest means of distinguishing the work of the legislator from that
of the tyrant.
What people, then, is a fit subject for legislation? One which, already bound by some
unity of origin, interest, or convention, has never yet felt the real yoke of law; one that
has neither customs nor superstitions deeply ingrained, one which stands in no fear of
being overwhelmed by sudden invasion; one which, without entering into its
neighbours’ quarrels, can resist each of them singlehanded, or get the help of one to
repel another; one in which every member may be known by every other, and there is
no need to lay on any man burdens too heavy for a man to bear; one which can do
without other peoples, and without which all others can do;1 one which is neither rich
nor poor, but self-sufficient; and, lastly, one which unites the consistency of an
ancient people with the docility of a new one. Legislation is made difficult less by
what it is necessary to build up than by what has to be destroyed; and what makes
success so rare is the impossibility of finding natural simplicity together with social
requirements. All these conditions are indeed rarely found united, and therefore few
States have good constitutions.
There is still in Europe one country capable of being given laws—Corsica. The valour
and persistency with which that brave people has regained and defended its liberty
well deserves that some wise man should teach it how to preserve what it has won. I
have a feeling that some day that little island will astonish Europe.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
69
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER XI
The Various Systems Of Legislation
If we ask in what precisely consists the greatest good of all, which should be the end
of every system of legislation, we shall find it reduce itself to two main objects,
liberty and equality—liberty, because all particular dependence means so much force
taken from the body of the State, and equality, because liberty cannot exist without it.
I have already defined civil liberty; by equality, we should understand, not that the
degrees of power and riches are to be absolutely identical for everybody; but that
power shall never be great enough for violence, and shall always be exercised by
virtue of rank and law; and that, in respect of riches, no citizen shall ever be wealthy
enough to buy another, and none poor enough to be forced to sell himself:1 which
implies, on the part of the great, moderation in goods and position, and, on the side of
the common sort, moderation in avarice and covetousness.
Such equality, we are told, is an unpractical ideal that cannot actually exist. But if its
abuse is inevitable, does it follow that we should not at least make regulations
concerning it? It is precisely because the force of circumstances tends continually to
destroy equality that the force of legislation should always tend to its maintenance.
But these general objects of every good legislative system need modifying in every
country in accordance with the local situation and the temper of the inhabitants; and
these circumstances should determine, in each case, the particular system of
institutions which is best, not perhaps in itself, but for the State for which it is
destined. If, for instance, the soil is barren and unproductive, or the land too crowded
for its inhabitants, the people should turn to industry and the crafts, and exchange
what they produce for the commodities they lack. If, on the other hand, a people
dwells in rich plains and fertile slopes, or, in a good land, lacks inhabitants, it should
give all its attention to agriculture, which causes men to multiply, and should drive
out the crafts, which would only result in depopulation, by grouping in a few localities
the few inhabitants there are.1 If a nation dwells on an extensive and convenient
coast-line, let it cover the sea with ships and foster commerce and navigation. It will
have a life that will be short and glorious. If, on its coasts, the sea washes nothing but
almost inaccessible rocks, let it remain barbarous and ichthyophagous: it will have a
quieter, perhaps a better, and certainly a happier life. In a word, besides the principles
that are common to all, every nation has in itself something that gives them a
particular application, and makes its legislation peculiarly its own. Thus, among the
Jews long ago and more recently among the Arabs, the chief object was religion,
among the Athenians letters, at Carthage and Tyre commerce, at Rhodes shipping, at
Sparta war, at Rome virtue. The author of The Spirit of the Laws has shown with
many examples by what art the legislator directs the constitution towards each of
these objects.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
70
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
What makes the constitution of a State really solid and lasting is the due observance
of what is proper, so that the natural relations are always in agreement with the laws
on every point, and law only serves, so to speak, to assure, accompany and rectify
them. But if the legislator mistakes his object and adopts a principle other than
circumstances naturally direct; if his principle makes for servitude while they make
for liberty, or if it makes for riches, while they make for populousness, or if it makes
for peace, while they make for conquest—the laws will insensibly lose their influence,
the constitution will alter, and the State will have no rest from trouble till it is either
destroyed or changed, and nature has resumed her invincible sway.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
71
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER XII
The Division Of The Laws
If the whole is to be set in order, and the commonwealth put into the best possible
shape, there are various relations to be considered. First, there is the action of the
complete body upon itself, the relation of the whole to the whole, of the Sovereign to
the State; and this relation, as we shall see, is made up of the relations of the
intermediate terms.
The laws which regulate this relation bear the name of political laws, and are also
called fundamental laws, not without reason if they are wise. For, if there is, in each
State, only one good system, the people that is in possession of it should hold fast to
this; but if the established order is bad, why should laws that prevent men from being
good be regarded as fundamental? Besides, in any case, a people is always in a
position to change its laws, however good; for, if it choose to do itself harm, who can
have a right to stop it?
The second relation is that of the members one to another, or to the body as a whole;
and this relation should be in the first respect as unimportant, and in the second as
important, as possible. Each citizen would then be perfectly independent of all the
rest, and at the same time very dependent on the city; which is brought about always
by the same means, as the strength of the State can alone secure the liberty of its
members. From this second relation arise civil laws.
We may consider also a third kind of relation between the individual and the law, a
relation of disobedience to its penalty. This gives rise to the setting up of criminal
laws, which, at bottom, are less a particular class of law than the sanction behind all
the rest.
Along with these three kinds of law goes a fourth, most important of all, which is not
graven on tablets of marble or brass, but on the hearts of the citizens. This forms the
real constitution of the State, takes on every day new powers, when other laws decay
or die out, restores them or takes their place, keeps a people in the ways in which it
was meant to go, and insensibly replaces authority by the force of habit. I am
speaking of morality, of custom, above all of public opinion; a power unknown to
political thinkers, on which none the less success in everything else depends. With
this the great legislator concerns himself in secret, though he seems to confine himself
to particular regulations; for these are only the arc of the arch, while manners and
morals, slower to arise, form in the end its immovable keystone.
Among the different classes of laws, the political, which determine the form of the
government, are alone relevant to my subject.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
72
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
BOOK III
Before speaking of the different forms of government, let us try to fix the exact sense
of the word, which has not yet been very clearly explained.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
73
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER I
Government In General
I warn the reader that this chapter requires careful reading, and that I am unable to
make myself clear to those who refuse to be attentive.
Every free action is produced by the concurrence of two causes; one moral, i. e. the
will which determines the act; the other physical, i. e. the power which executes it.
When I walk towards an object, it is necessary first that I should will to go there, and,
in the second place, that my feet should carry me. If a paralytic wills to run and an
active man wills not to, they will both stay where they are. The body politic has the
same motive powers; here too force and will are distinguished, will under the name of
legislative power and force under that of executive power. Without their concurrence,
nothing is, or should be, done.
We have seen that the legislative power belongs to the people, and can belong to it
alone. It may, on the other hand, readily be seen, from the principles laid down above,
that the executive power cannot belong to the generality as legislature or Sovereign,
because it consists wholly of particular acts which fall outside the competency of the
law, and consequently of the Sovereign, whose acts must always be laws.
The public force therefore needs an agent of its own to bind it together and set it to
work under the direction of the general will, to serve as a means of communication
between the State and the Sovereign, and to do for the collective person more or less
what the union of soul and body does for man. Here we have what is, in the State, the
basis of government, often wrongly confused with the Sovereign, whose minister it is.
What then is government? An intermediate body set up between the subjects and the
Sovereign, to secure their mutual correspondence, charged with the execution of the
laws and the maintenance of liberty, both civil and political.
The members of this body are called magistrates or kings, that is to say governors,
and the whole body bears the name prince.1 Thus those who hold that the act, by
which a people puts itself under a prince, is not a contract, are certainly right. It is
simply and solely a commission, an employment, in which the rulers, mere officials of
the Sovereign, exercise in their own name the power of which it makes them
depositaries. This power it can limit, modify or recover at pleasure; for the alienation
of such a right is incompatible with the nature of the social body, and contrary to the
end of association.
I call then government, or supreme administration, the legitimate exercise of the
executive power, and prince or magistrate the man or the body entrusted with that
administration.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
74
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
In government reside the intermediate forces whose relations make up that of the
whole to the whole, or of the Sovereign to the State. This last relation may be
represented as that between the extreme terms of a continuous proportion, which has
government as its mean proportional. The government gets from the Sovereign the
orders it gives the people, and, for the State to be properly balanced, there must, when
everything is reckoned in, be equality between the product or power of the
government taken in itself, and the product or power of the citizens, who are on the
one hand sovereign and on the other subject.
Furthermore, none of these three terms can be altered without the equality being
instantly destroyed. If the Sovereign desires to govern, or the magistrate to give laws,
or if the subjects refuse to obey, disorder takes the place of regularity, force and will
no longer act together, and the State is dissolved and falls into despotism or anarchy.
Lastly, as there is only one mean proportional between each relation, there is also only
one good government possible for a State. But, as countless events may change the
relations of a people, not only may different governments be good for different
peoples, but also for the same people at different times.
In attempting to give some idea of the various relations that may hold between these
two extreme terms, I shall take as an example the number of a people, which is the
most easily expressible.
Suppose the State is composed of ten thousand citizens. The Sovereign can only be
considered collectively and as a body; but each member, as being a subject, is
regarded as an individual: thus the Sovereign is to the subject as ten thousand to one,
i. e. each member of the State has as his share only a ten-thousandth part of the
sovereign authority, although he is wholly under its control. If the people numbers a
hundred thousand, the condition of the subject undergoes no change, and each equally
is under the whole authority of the laws, while his vote, being reduced to one hundred
thousandth part, has ten times less influence in drawing them up. The subject
therefore remaining always a unit, the relation between him and the Sovereign
increases with the number of the citizens. From this it follows that, the larger the
State, the less the liberty.
When I say the relation increases, I mean that it grows more unequal. Thus the greater
it is in the geometrical sense, the less relation there is in the ordinary sense of the
word. In the former sense, the relation, considered according to quantity, is expressed
by the quotient; in the latter, considered according to identity, it is reckoned by
similarity.
Now, the less relation the particular wills have to the general will, that is, morals and
manners to laws, the more should the repressive force be increased. The government,
then, to be good, should be proportionately stronger as the people is more numerous.
On the other hand, as the growth of the State gives the depositaries of the public
authority more temptations and chances of abusing their power, the greater the force
with which the government ought to be endowed for keeping the people in hand, the
greater too should be the force at the disposal of the Sovereign for keeping the
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
75
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
government in hand. I am speaking, not of absolute force, but of the relative force of
the different parts of the State.
It follows from this double relation that the continuous proportion between the
Sovereign, the prince and the people, is by no means an arbitrary idea, but a necessary
consequence of the nature of the body politic. It follows further that, one of the
extreme terms, viz. the people, as subject, being fixed and represented by unity,
whenever the duplicate ratio increases or diminishes, the simple ratio does the same,
and is changed accordingly. From this we see that there is not a single unique and
absolute form of government, but as many governments differing in nature as there
are States differing in size.
If, ridiculing this system, any one were to say that, in order to find the mean
proportional and give form to the body of the government, it is only necessary,
according to me, to find the square root of the number of the people, I should answer
that I am here taking this number only as an instance; that the relations of which I am
speaking are not measured by the number of men alone, but generally by the amount
of action, which is a combination of a multitude of causes; and that, further, if, to save
words, I borrow for a moment the terms of geometry, I am none the less well aware
that moral quantities do not allow of geometrical accuracy.
The government is on a small scale what the body politic which includes it is on a
great one. It is a moral person endowed with certain faculties, active like the
Sovereign and passive like the State, and capable of being resolved into other similar
relations. This accordingly gives rise to a new proportion, within which there is yet
another, according to the arrangement of the magistracies, till an indivisible middle
term is reached, i. e. a single ruler or supreme magistrate, who may be represented, in
the midst of this progression, as the unity between the fractional and the ordinal
series.
Without encumbering ourselves with this multiplication of terms, let us rest content
with regarding government as a new body within the State, distinct from the people
and the Sovereign, and intermediate between them.
There is between these two bodies this essential difference, that the State exists by
itself, and the government only through the Sovereign. Thus the dominant will of the
prince is, or should be, nothing but the general will or the law; his force is only the
public force concentrated in his hands, and, as soon as he tries to base any absolute
and independent act on his own authority, the tie that binds the whole together begins
to be loosened. If finally the prince should come to have a particular will more active
than the will of the Sovereign, and should employ the public force in his hands in
obedience to this particular will, there would be, so to speak, two Sovereigns, one
rightful and the other actual, the social union would evaporate instantly, and the body
politic would be dissolved.
However, in order that the government may have a true existence and a real life
distinguishing it from the body of the State, and in order that all its members may be
able to act in concert and fulfil the end for which it was set up, it must have a
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
76
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
particular personality, a sensibility common to its members, and a force and will of its
own making for its preservation. This particular existence implies assemblies,
councils, power of deliberation and decision, rights, titles, and privileges belonging
exclusively to the prince and making the office of magistrate more honourable in
proportion as it is more troublesome. The difficulties lie in the manner of so ordering
this subordinate whole within the whole, that it in no way alters the general
constitution by affirmation of its own, and always distinguishes the particular force it
possesses, which is destined to aid in its preservation, from the public force, which is
destined to the preservation of the State; and, in a word, is always ready to sacrifice
the government to the people, and never to sacrifice the people to the government.
Furthermore, although the artificial body of the government is the work of another
artificial body, and has, we may say, only a borrowed and subordinate life, this does
not prevent it from being able to act with more or less vigour or promptitude, or from
being, so to speak, in more or less robust health. Finally, without departing directly
from the end for which it was instituted, it may deviate more or less from it, according
to the manner of its constitution.
From all these differences arise the various relations which the government ought to
bear to the body of the State, according to the accidental and particular relations by
which the State itself is modified, for often the government that is best in itself will
become the most pernicious, if the relations in which it stands have altered according
to the defects of the body politic to which it belongs.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
77
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER II
The Constituent Principle In The Various Forms Of Government
To set forth the general cause of the above differences, we must here distinguish
between government and its principle, as we did before between the State and the
Sovereign.
The body of the magistrate may be composed of a greater or a less number of
members. We said that the relation of the Sovereign to the subjects was greater in
proportion as the people was more numerous, and, by a clear analogy, we may say the
same of the relation of the government to the magistrates.
But the total force of the government, being always that of the State, is invariable; so
that, the more of this force it expends on its own members, the less it has left to
employ on the whole people.
The more numerous the magistrates, therefore, the weaker the government. This
principle being fundamental, we must do our best to make it clear.
In the person of the magistrate we can distinguish three essentially different wills:
first, the private will of the individual, tending only to his personal advantage;
secondly, the common will of the magistrates, which is relative solely to the
advantage of the prince, and may be called corporate will, being general in relation to
the government, and particular in relation to the State, of which the government forms
part; and, in the third place, the will of the people or the sovereign will, which is
general both in relation to the State regarded as the whole, and to the government
regarded as a part of the whole.
In a perfect act of legislation, the individual or particular will should be at zero; the
corporate will belonging to the government should occupy a very subordinate
position; and, consequently, the general or sovereign will should always predominate
and should be the sole guide of all the rest.
According to the natural order, on the other hand, these different wills become more
active in proportion as they are concentrated. Thus, the general will is always the
weakest, the corporate will second, and the individual will strongest of all: so that, in
the government, each member is first of all himself, then a magistrate, and then a
citizen—in an order exactly the reverse of what the social system requires.
This granted, if the whole government is in the hands of one man, the particular and
the corporate will are wholly united, and consequently the latter is at its highest
possible degree of intensity. But, as the use to which the force is put depends on the
degree reached by the will, and as the absolute force of the government is invariable,
it follows that the most active government is that of one man.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
78
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Suppose, on the other hand, we unite the government with the legislative authority,
and make the Sovereign prince also, and all the citizens so many magistrates: then the
corporate will, being confounded with the general will, can possess no greater activity
than that will, and must leave the particular will as strong as it can possibly be. Thus,
the government, having always the same absolute force, will be at the lowest point of
its relative force or activity.
These relations are incontestable, and there are other considerations which still further
confirm them. We can see, for instance, that each magistrate is more active in the
body to which he belongs than each citizen in that to which he belongs, and that
consequently the particular will has much more influence on the acts of the
government than on those of the Sovereign; for each magistrate is almost always
charged with some governmental function, while each citizen, taken singly, exercises
no function of Sovereignty. Furthermore, the bigger the State grows, the more its real
force increases, though not in direct proportion to its growth; but, the State remaining
the same, the number of magistrates may increase to any extent, without the
government gaining any greater real force; for its force is that of the State, the
dimension of which remains equal. Thus the relative force or activity of the
government decreases, while its absolute or real force cannot increase.
Moreover, it is a certainty that promptitude in execution diminishes as more people
are put in charge of it: where prudence is made too much of, not enough is made of
fortune; opportunity is let slip, and deliberation results in the loss of its object.
I have just proved that the government grows remiss in proportion as the number of
the magistrates increases; and I previously proved that, the more numerous the people,
the greater should be the repressive force. From this it follows that the relation of the
magistrates to the government should vary inversely to the relation of the subjects to
the Sovereign; that is to say, the larger the State, the more should the government be
tightened, so that the number of the rulers diminish in proportion to the increase of
that of the people.
It should be added that I am here speaking of the relative strength of the government,
and not of its rectitude: for, on the other hand, the more numerous the magistracy, the
nearer the corporate will comes to the general will; while, under a single magistrate,
the corporate will is, as I said, merely a particular will. Thus, what may be gained on
one side is lost on the other, and the art of the legislator is to know how to fix the
point at which the force and the will of the government, which are always in inverse
proportion, meet in the relation that is most to the advantage of the State.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
79
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER III
The Division Of Governments
We saw in the last chapter what causes the various kinds or forms of government to
be distinguished according to the number of the members composing them: it remains
in this to discover how the division is made.
In the first place, the Sovereign may commit the charge of the government to the
whole people or to the majority of the people, so that more citizens are magistrates
than are mere private individuals. This form of government is called democracy.
Or it may restrict the government to a small number, so that there are more private
citizens than magistrates; and this is named aristocracy.
Lastly, it may concentrate the whole government in the hands of a single magistrate
from whom all others hold their power. This third form is the most usual, and is called
monarchy, or royal government.
It should be remarked that all these forms, or at least the first two, admit of degree,
and even of very wide differences; for democracy may include the whole people, or
may be restricted to half. Aristocracy, in its turn, may be restricted indefinitely from
half the people down to the smallest possible number. Even royalty is susceptible of a
measure of distribution. Sparta always had two kings, as its constitution provided; and
the Roman Empire saw as many as eight emperors at once, without it being possible
to say that the Empire was split up. Thus there is a point at which each form of
government passes into the next, and it becomes clear that, under three comprehensive
denominations, government is really susceptible of as many diverse forms as the State
has citizens.
There are even more: for, as the government may also, in certain aspects, be
subdivided into other parts, one administered in one fashion and one in another, the
combination of the three forms may result in a multitude of mixed forms, each of
which admits of multiplication by all the simple forms.
There has been at all times much dispute concerning the best form of government,
without consideration of the fact that each is in some cases the best, and in others the
worst.
If, in the different States, the number of supreme magistrates should be in inverse
ratio to the number of citizens, it follows that, generally, democratic government suits
small States, aristocratic government those of middle size, and monarchy great ones.
This rule is immediately deducible from the principle laid down. But it is impossible
to count the innumerable circumstances which may furnish exceptions.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
80
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER IV
Democracy
He who makes the law knows better than any one else how it should be executed and
interpreted. It seems then impossible to have a better constitution than that in which
the executive and legislative powers are united; but this very fact renders the
government in certain respects inadequate, because things which should be
distinguished are confounded, and the prince and the Sovereign, being the same
person, form, so to speak, no more than a government without government.
It is not good for him who makes the laws to execute them, or for the body of the
people to turn its attention away from a general standpoint and devote it to particular
objects. Nothing is more dangerous than the influence of private interests in public
affairs, and the abuse of the laws by the government is a less evil than the corruption
of the legislator, which is the inevitable sequel to a particular standpoint. In such a
case, the State being altered in substance, all reformation becomes impossible. A
people that would never misuse governmental powers would never misuse
independence; a people that would always govern well would not need to be
governed.
If we take the term in the strict sense, there never has been a real democracy, and
there never will be. It is against the natural order for the many to govern and the few
to be governed. It is unimaginable that the people should remain continually
assembled to devote their time to public affairs, and it is clear that they cannot set up
commissions for that purpose without the form of administration being changed.
In fact, I can confidently lay down as a principle that, when the functions of
government are shared by several tribunals, the less numerous sooner or later acquire
the greatest authority, if only because they are in a position to expedite affairs, and
power thus naturally comes into their hands.
Besides, how many conditions that are difficult to unite does such a government
presuppose! First, a very small State, where the people can readily be got together and
where each citizen can with ease know all the rest; secondly, great simplicity of
manners, to prevent business from multiplying and raising thorny problems; next, a
large measure of equality in rank and fortune, without which equality of rights and
authority cannot long subsist; lastly, little or no luxury—for luxury either comes of
riches or makes them necessary; it corrupts at once rich and poor, the rich by
possession and the poor by covetousness; it sells the country to softness and vanity,
and takes away from the State all its citizens, to make them slaves one to another, and
one and all to public opinion.
This is why a famous writer has made virtue the fundamental principle of Republics;
for all these conditions could not exist without virtue. But, for want of the necessary
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
81
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
distinctions, that great thinker was often inexact, and sometimes obscure, and did not
see that, the sovereign authority being everywhere the same, the same principle
should be found in every well-constituted State, in a greater or less degree, it is true,
according to the form of the government.
It may be added that there is no government so subject to civil wars and intestine
agitations as democratic or popular government, because there is none which has so
strong and continual a tendency to change to another form, or which demands more
vigilance and courage for its maintenance as it is. Under such a constitution above all,
the citizen should arm himself with strength and constancy, and say, every day of his
life, what a virtuous Count Palatine1 said in the Diet of Poland: Malo periculosam
libertatem quam quietum servitium.
Were there a people of gods, their government would be democratic. So perfect a
government is not for men.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
82
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER V
Aristocracy
We have here two quite distinct moral persons, the government and the Sovereign,
and in consequence two general wills, one general in relation to all the citizens, the
other only for the members of the administration. Thus, although the government may
regulate its internal policy as it pleases, it can never speak to the people save in the
name of the Sovereign, that is, of the people itself, a fact which must not be forgotten.
The first societies governed themselves aristocratically. The heads of families took
counsel together on public affairs. The young bowed without question to the authority
of experience. Hence such names as priests, elders, senate, and gerontes. The savages
of North America govern themselves in this way even now, and their government is
admirable.
But, in proportion as artificial inequality produced by institutions became
predominant over natural inequality, riches or power1 were put before age, and
aristocracy became elective. Finally, the transmission of the father’s power along with
his goods to his children, by creating patrician families, made government hereditary,
and there came to be senators of twenty.
There are then three sorts of aristocracy—natural, elective and hereditary. The first is
only for simple peoples; the third is the worst of all governments; the second is the
best, and is aristocracy properly so called.
Besides the advantage that lies in the distinction between the two powers, it presents
that of its members being chosen; for, in popular government, all the citizens are born
magistrates; but here magistracy is confined to a few, who become such only by
election.2 By this means uprightness, understanding, experience and all other claims
to pre-eminence and public esteem become so many further guarantees of wise
government.
Moreover, assemblies are more easily held, affairs better discussed and carried out
with more order and diligence, and the credit of the State is better sustained abroad by
venerable senators than by a multitude that is unknown or despised.
In a word, it is the best and most natural arrangement that the wisest should govern
the many, when it is assured that they will govern for its profit, and not for their own.
There is no need to multiply instruments, or get twenty thousand men to do what a
hundred picked men can do even better. But it must not be forgotten that corporate
interest here begins to direct the public power less under the regulation of the general
will, and that a further inevitable propensity takes away from the laws part of the
executive power.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
83
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
If we are to speak of what is individually desirable, neither should the State be so
small, nor a people so simple and upright, that the execution of the laws follows
immediately from the public will, as it does in a good democracy. Nor should the
nation be so great that the rulers have to scatter in order to govern it and are able to
play the Sovereign each in his own department, and, beginning by making themselves
independent, end by becoming masters.
But if aristocracy does not demand all the virtues needed by popular government, it
demands others which are peculiar to itself; for instance, moderation on the side of the
rich and contentment on that of the poor; for it seems that thorough-going equality
would be out of place, as it was not found even at Sparta.
Furthermore, if this form of government carries with it a certain inequality of fortune,
this is justifiable in order that as a rule the administration of public affairs may be
entrusted to those who are most able to give them their whole time, but not, as
Aristotle maintains, in order that the rich may always be put first. On the contrary, it
is of importance that an opposite choice should occasionally teach the people that the
deserts of men offer claims to pre-eminence more important than those of riches.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
84
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER VI
Monarchy
So far, we have considered the prince as a moral and collective person, unified by the
force of the laws, and the depositary in the State of the executive power. We have
now to consider this power when it is gathered together into the hands of a natural
person, a real man, who alone has the right to dispose of it in accordance with the
laws. Such a person is called a monarch or king.
In contrast with other forms of administration, in which a collective being stands for
an individual, in this form an individual stands for a collective being; so that the moral
unity that constitutes the prince is at the same time a physical unity, and all the
qualities, which in the other case are only with difficulty brought together by the law,
are found naturally united.
Thus the will of the people, the will of the prince, the public force of the State, and the
particular force of the government, all answer to a single motive power; all the springs
of the machine are in the same hands, the whole moves towards the same end; there
are no conflicting movements to cancel one another, and no kind of constitution can
be imagined in which a less amount of effort produces a more considerable amount of
action. Archimedes, seated quietly on the bank and easily drawing a great vessel
afloat, stands to my mind for a skilful monarch, governing vast states from his study,
and moving everything while he seems himself unmoved.
But if no government is more vigorous than this, there is also none in which the
particular will holds more sway and rules the rest more easily. Everything moves
towards the same end indeed, but this end is by no means that of the public happiness,
and even the force of the administration constantly shows itself prejudicial to the
State.
Kings desire to be absolute, and men are always crying out to them from afar that the
best means of being so is to get themselves loved by their people. This precept is all
very well, and even in some respects very true. Unfortunately, it will always be
derided at court. The power which comes of a people’s love is no doubt the greatest;
but it is precarious and conditional, and princes will never rest content with it. The
best kings desire to be in a position to be wicked, if they please, without forfeiting
their mastery: political sermonisers may tell them to their hearts’ content that, the
people’s strength being their own, their first interest is that the people should be
prosperous, numerous and formidable; they are well aware that this is untrue. Their
first personal interest is that the people should be weak, wretched, and unable to resist
them. I admit that, provided the subjects remained always in submission, the prince’s
interest would indeed be that it should be powerful, in order that its power, being his
own, might make him formidable to his neighbours; but, this interest being merely
secondary and subordinate, and strength being incompatible with submission, princes
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
85
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
naturally give the preference always to the principle that is more to their immediate
advantage. This is what Samuel put strongly before the Hebrews, and what
Macchiavelli has clearly shown. He professed to teach kings; but it was the people he
really taught. His Prince is the book of Republicans.1
We found, on general grounds, that monarchy is suitable only for great States, and
this is confirmed when we examine it in itself. The more numerous the public
administration, the smaller becomes the relation between the prince and the subjects,
and the nearer it comes to equality, so that in democracy the ratio is unity, or absolute
equality. Again, as the government is restricted in numbers the ratio increases and
reaches its maximum when the government is in the hands of a single person. There is
then too great a distance between prince and people, and the State lacks a bond of
union. To form such a bond, there must be intermediate orders, and princes,
personages and nobility to compose them. But no such things suit a small State, to
which all class differences mean ruin.
If, however, it is hard for a great State to be well governed, it is much harder for it to
be so by a single man; and every one knows what happens when kings substitute
others for themselves.
An essential and inevitable defect, which will always rank monarchical below
republican government, is that in a republic the public voice hardly ever raises to the
highest positions men who are not enlightened and capable, and such as to fill them
with honour; while in monarchies those who rise to the top are most often merely
petty blunderers, petty swindlers, and petty intriguers, whose petty talents cause them
to get into the highest positions at Court, but, as soon as they have got there, serve
only to make their ineptitude clear to the public. The people is far less often mistaken
in its choice than the prince; and a man of real worth among the king’s ministers is
almost as rare as a fool at the head of a republican government. Thus, when, by some
fortunate chance, one of these born governors takes the helm of State in some
monarchy that has been nearly overwhelmed by swarms of ‘gentlemanly’
administrators, there is nothing but amazement at the resources he discovers, and his
coming marks an era in his country’s history.
For a monarchical State to have a chance of being well governed, its population and
extent must be proportionate to the abilities of its governor. It is easier to conquer than
to rule. With a long enough lever, the world could be moved with a single finger; to
sustain it needs the shoulders of Hercules. However small a State may be, the prince
is hardly ever big enough for it. When, on the other hand, it happens that the State is
too small for its ruler, in these rare cases too it is ill governed, because the ruler,
constantly pursuing his great designs, forgets the interests of the people, and makes it
no less wretched by misusing the talents he has, than a ruler of less capacity would
make it for want of those he had not. A kingdom should, so to speak, expand or
contract with each reign, according to the prince’s capabilities; but, the abilities of a
senate being more constant in quantity, the State can then have permanent frontiers
without the administration suffering.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
86
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
The disadvantage that is most felt in monarchical government is the want of the
continuous succession which, in both the other forms, provides an unbroken bond of
union. When one king dies, another is needed; elections leave dangerous intervals and
are full of storms; and unless the citizens are disinterested and upright to a degree
which very seldom goes with this kind of government, intrigue and corruption
abound. He to whom the State has sold itself can hardly help selling it in his turn and
repaying himself, at the expense of the weak, the money the powerful have wrung
from him. Under such an administration, venality sooner or later spreads through
every part, and peace so enjoyed under a king is worse than the disorders of an
interregnum.
What has been done to prevent these evils? Crowns have been made hereditary in
certain families, and an order of succession has been set up, to prevent disputes from
arising on the death of kings. That is to say, the disadvantages of regency have been
put in place of those of election, apparent tranquillity has been preferred to wise
administration, and men have chosen rather to risk having children, monstrosities, or
imbeciles as rulers to having disputes over the choice of good kings. It has not been
taken into account that, in so exposing ourselves to the risks this possibility entails,
we are setting almost all the chances against us. There was sound sense in what the
younger Dionysius said to his father, who reproached him for doing some shameful
deed by asking, “Did I set you the example?” “No,” answered his son, “but your
father was not king.”
Everything conspires to take away from a man who is set in authority over others the
sense of justice and reason. Much trouble, we are told, is taken to teach young princes
the art of reigning; but their education seems to do them no good. It would be better to
begin by teaching them the art of obeying. The greatest kings whose praises history
tells were not brought up to reign: reigning is a science we are never so far from
possessing as when we have learnt too much of it, and one we acquire better by
obeying than by commanding. “Nam utilissimus idem ac brevissimus bonarum
malarumque rerum delectus cogitare quid aut nolueris sub alio principe, aut
volueris.”1
One result of this lack of coherence is the inconstancy of royal government, which,
regulated now on one scheme and now on another, according to the character of the
reigning prince or those who reign for him, cannot for long have a fixed object or a
consistent policy—and this variability, not found in the other forms of government,
where the prince is always the same, causes the State to be always shifting from
principle to principle and from project to project. Thus we may say that generally, if a
court is more subtle in intrigue, there is more wisdom in a senate, and Republics
advance towards their ends by more consistent and better considered policies; while
every revolution in a royal ministry creates a revolution in the State; for the principle
common to all ministers and nearly all kings is to do in every respect the reverse of
what was done by their predecessors.
This incoherence further clears up a sophism that is very familiar to royalist political
writers; not only is civil government likened to domestic government, and the prince
to the father of a family—this error has already been refuted—but the prince is also
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
87
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
freely credited with all the virtues he ought to possess, and is supposed to be always
what he should be. This supposition once made, royal, government is clearly
preferable to all others, because it is incontestably the strongest, and, to be the best
also, wants only a corporate will more in conformity with the general will.
But if, according to Plato,1 the “king by nature” is such a rarity, how often will nature
and fortune conspire to give him a crown? And, if royal education necessarily
corrupts those who receive it, what is to be hoped from a series of men brought up to
reign? It is, then, wanton self-deception to confuse royal government with
government by a good king. To see such government as it is in itself, we must
consider it as it is under princes who are incompetent or wicked: for either they will
come to the throne wicked or incompetent, or the throne will make them so.
These difficulties have not escaped our writers, who, all the same, are not troubled by
them. The remedy, they say, is to obey without a murmur: God sends bad kings in His
wrath, and they must be borne as the scourges of Heaven. Such talk is doubtless
edifying; but it would be more in place in a pulpit than in a political book. What are
we to think of a doctor who promises miracles, and whose whole art is to exhort the
sufferer to patience? We know for ourselves that we must put up with a bad
government when it is there; the question is how to find a good one.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
88
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER VII
Mixed Governments
Strictly speaking, there is no such thing as a simple government. An isolated ruler
must have subordinate magistrates; a popular government must have a head. There is
therefore, in the distribution of the executive power, always a gradation from the
greater to the lesser number, with the difference that sometimes the greater number is
dependent on the smaller, and sometimes the smaller on the greater.
Sometimes the distribution is equal, when either the constituent parts are in mutual
dependence, as in the government of England, or the authority of each section is
independent, but imperfect, as in Poland. This last form is bad; for it secures no unity
in the government, and the State is left without a bond of union.
Is a simple or a mixed government the better? Political writers are always debating the
question, which must be answered as we have already answered a question about all
forms of government.
Simple government is better in itself, just because it is simple. But when the executive
power is not sufficiently dependent upon the legislative power, i. e. when the prince is
more closely related to the Sovereign than the people to the prince, this lack of
proportion must be cured by the division of the government; for all the parts have then
no less authority over the subjects, while their division makes them all together less
strong against the Sovereign.
The same disadvantage is also prevented by the appointment of intermediate
magistrates, who leave the government entire, and have the effect only of balancing
the two powers and maintaining their respective rights. Government is then not
mixed, but moderated.
The opposite disadvantages may be similarly cured, and, when the government is too
lax, tribunals may be set up to concentrate it. This is done in all democracies. In the
first case, the government is divided to make it weak; in the second, to make it strong:
for the maxima of both strength and weakness are found in simple governments, while
the mixed forms result in a mean strength.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
89
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER VIII
That All Forms Of Government Do Not Suit All Countries
Liberty, not being a fruit of all climates, is not within the reach of all peoples. The
more this principle, laid down by Montesquieu, is considered, the more its truth is
felt; the more it is combated, the more chance is given to confirm it by new proofs.
In all the governments that there are, the public person consumes without producing.
Whence then does it get what it consumes? From the labour of its members. The
necessities of the public are supplied out of the superfluities of individuals. It follows
that the civil State can subsist only so long as men’s labour brings them a return
greater than their needs.
The amount of this excess is not the same in all countries. In some it is considerable,
in others middling, in yet others nil, in some even negative. The relation of product to
subsistence depends on the fertility of the climate, on the sort of labour the land
demands, on the nature of its products, on the strength of its inhabitants, on the greater
or less consumption they find necessary, and on several further considerations of
which the whole relation is made up.
On the other side, all governments are not of the same nature: some are less voracious
than others, and the differences between them are based on this second principle, that
the further from their source the public contributions are removed, the more
burdensome they become. The charge should be measured not by the amount of the
impositions, but by the path they have to travel in order to get back to those from
whom they came. When the circulation is prompt and well-established, it does not
matter whether much or little is paid; the people is always rich and, financially
speaking, all is well. On the contrary, however little the people gives, if that little does
not return to it, it is soon exhausted by giving continually: the State is then never rich,
and the people is always a people of beggars.
It follows that, the more the distance between people and government increases, the
more burdensome tribute becomes: thus, in a democracy, the people bears the least
charge; in an aristocracy, a greater charge; and, in monarchy, the weight becomes
heaviest. Monarchy therefore suits only wealthy nations; aristocracy, States of
middling size and wealth; and democracy, States that are small and poor.
In fact, the more we reflect, the more we find the difference between free and
monarchical States to be this: in the former, everything is used for the public
advantage; in the latter, the public forces and those of individuals are affected by each
other, and either increases as the other grows weak; finally, instead of governing
subjects to make them happy, despotism makes them wretched in order to govern
them.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
90
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
We find then, in every climate, natural causes according to which the form of
government which it requires can be assigned, and we can even say what sort of
inhabitants it should have.
Unfriendly and barren lands, where the product does not repay the labour, should
remain desert and uncultivated, or peopled only by savages; lands where men’s labour
brings in no more than the exact minimum necessary to subsistence should be
inhabited by barbarous peoples: in such places all polity is impossible. Lands where
the surplus of product over labour is only middling are suitable for free peoples; those
in which the soil is abundant and fertile and gives a great product for a little labour
call for monarchical government, in order that the surplus of superfluities among the
subjects may be consumed by the luxury of the prince: for it is better for this excess to
be absorbed by the government than dissipated among the individuals. I am aware that
there are exceptions; but these exceptions themselves confirm the rule, in that sooner
or later they produce revolutions which restore things to the natural order.
General laws should always be distinguished from individual causes that may modify
their effects. If all the South were covered with Republics and all the North with
despotic States, it would be none the less true that, in point of climate, despotism is
suitable to hot countries, barbarism to cold countries, and good polity to temperate
regions. I see also that, the principle being granted, there may be disputes on its
application; it may be said that there are cold countries that are very fertile, and
tropical countries that are very unproductive. But this difficulty exists only for those
who do not consider the question in all its aspects. We must, as I have already said,
take labour, strength, consumption, etc., into account.
Take two tracts of equal extent, one of which brings in five and the other ten. If the
inhabitants of the first consume four and those of the second nine, the surplus of the
first product will be a fifth and that of the second a tenth. The ratio of these two
surpluses will then be inverse to that of the products, and the tract which produces
only five will give a surplus double that of the tract which produces ten.
But there is no question of a double product, and I think no one would put the fertility
of cold countries, as a general rule, on an equality with that of hot ones. Let us,
however, suppose this equality to exist: let us, if you will, regard England as on the
same level as Sicily, and Poland as Egypt—further south, we shall have Africa and
the Indies; further north, nothing at all. To get this equality of product, what a
difference there must be in tillage: in Sicily, there is only need to scratch the ground;
in England, how men must toil! But, where more hands are needed to get the same
product, the superfluity must necessarily be less.
Consider, besides, that the same number of men consume much less in hot countries.
The climate requires sobriety for the sake of health; and Europeans who try to live
there as they would at home all perish of dysentery and indigestion. “We are,” says
Chardin, “carnivorous animals, wolves, in comparison with the Asiatics. Some
attribute the sobriety of the Persians to the fact that their country is less cultivated; but
it is my belief that their country abounds less in commodities because the inhabitants
need less. If their frugality,” he goes on, “were the effect of the nakedness of the land,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
91
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
only the poor would eat little; but everybody does so. Again, less or more would be
eaten in various provinces, according to the land’s fertility; but the same sobriety is
found throughout the kingdom. They are very proud of their manner of life, saying
that you have only to look at their hue to recognise how far it excels that of the
Christians. In fact, the Persians are of an even hue; their skins are fair, fine and
smooth; while the hue of their subjects, the Armenians, who live after the European
fashion, is rough and blotchy, and their bodies are gross and unwieldy.”
The nearer you get to the equator, the less people live on. Meat they hardly touch;
rice, maize, curcur, millet and cassava are their ordinary food. There are in the Indies
millions of men whose subsistence does not cost a halfpenny a day. Even in Europe
we find considerable differences of appetite between Northern and Southern peoples.
A Spaniard will live for a week on a German’s dinner. In the countries in which men
are more voracious, luxury therefore turns in the direction of consumption. In
England, luxury appears in a well-filled table; in Italy, you feast on sugar and flowers.
Luxury in clothes shows similar differences. In climates in which the changes of
season are prompt and violent, men have better and simpler clothes; where they clothe
themselves only for adornment, what is striking is more thought of than what is
useful; clothes themselves are then a luxury. At Naples, you may see daily walking in
the Pausilippeum men in gold-embroidered upper garments and nothing else. It is the
same with buildings; magnificence is the sole consideration where there is nothing to
fear from the air. In Paris and London, you desire to be lodged warmly and
comfortably; in Madrid, you have superb salons, but not a window that closes, and
you go to bed in a mere hole.
In hot countries foods are much more substantial and succulent; and the third
difference cannot but have an influence on the second. Why are so many vegetables
eaten in Italy? Because there they are good, nutritious and excellent in taste. In
France, where they are nourished only on water, they are far from nutritious and are
thought nothing of at table. They take up all the same no less ground, and cost at least
as much pains to cultivate. It is a proved fact that the wheat of Barbary, in other
respects inferior to that of France, yields much more flour, and that the wheat of
France in turn yields more than that of northern countries; from which it may be
inferred that a like gradation in the same direction, from equator to pole, is found
generally. But is it not an obvious disadvantage for an equal product to contain less
nourishment?
To all these points may be added another, which at once depends on and strengthens
them. Hot countries need inhabitants less than cold countries, and can support more of
them. There is thus a double surplus, which is all to the advantage of despotism. The
greater the territory occupied by a fixed number of inhabitants, the more difficult
revolt becomes, because rapid or secret concerted action is impossible, and the
government can easily unmask projects and cut communications; but the more a
numerous people is gathered together, the less can the government usurp the
Sovereign’s place: the people’s leaders can deliberate as safely in their houses as the
prince in council, and the crowd gathers as rapidly in the squares as the prince’s
troops in their quarters. The advantage of tyrannical government therefore lies in
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
92
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
acting at great distances. With the help of the rallying-points it establishes, its
strength, like that of the lever,1 grows with distance. The strength of the people, on
the other hand, acts only when concentrated: when spread abroad, it evaporates and is
lost, like powder scattered on the ground, which catches fire only grain by grain. The
least populous countries are thus the fittest for tyranny: fierce animals reign only in
deserts.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
93
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER IX
The Marks Of A Good Government
The question “What absolutely is the best government?” is unanswerable as well as
indeterminate; or rather, there are as many good answers as there are possible
combinations in the absolute and relative situations of all nations.
But if it is asked by what sign we may know that a given people is well or ill
governed, that is another matter, and the question, being one of fact, admits of an
answer.
It is not, however, answered, because every-one wants to answer it in his own way.
Subjects extol public tranquillity, citizens individual liberty; the one class prefers
security of possessions, the other that of person; the one regards as the best
government that which is most severe, the other maintains that the mildest is the best;
the one wants crimes punished, the other wants them prevented; the one wants the
State to be feared by its neighbours, the other prefers that it should be ignored; the one
is content if money circulates, the other demands that the people shall have bread.
Even if an agreement were come to on these and similar points, should we have got
any further? As moral qualities do not admit of exact measurement, agreement about
the mark does not mean agreement about the valuation.
For my part, I am continually astonished that a mark so simple is not recognised, or
that men are of so bad faith as not to admit it. What is the end of political association?
The preservation and prosperity of its members. And what is the surest mark of their
preservation and prosperity? Their numbers and population. Seek then nowhere else
this mark that is in dispute. The rest being equal, the government under which,
without external aids, without naturalisation or colonies, the citizens increase and
multiply most, is beyond question the best. The government under which a people
wanes and diminishes is the worst. Calculators, it is left for you to count, to measure,
to compare.1
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
94
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER X
The Abuse Of Government And Its Tendency To Degenerate
As the particular will acts constantly in opposition to the general will, the government
continually exerts itself against the Sovereignty. The greater this exertion becomes,
the more the constitution changes; and, as there is in this case no other corporate will
to create an equilibrium by resisting the will of the prince, sooner or later the prince
must inevitably suppress the Sovereign and break the social treaty. This is the
unavoidable and inherent defect which, from the very birth of the body politic, tends
ceaselessly to destroy it, as age and death end by destroying the human body.
There are two general courses by which government degenerates: i. e. when it
undergoes contraction, or when the State is dissolved.
Government undergoes contraction when it passes from the many to the few, that is,
from democracy to aristocracy, and from aristocracy to royalty. To do so is its natural
propensity.1 If it took the backward course from the few to the many, it could be said
that it was relaxed; by this inverse sequence is impossible.
Indeed, governments never change their form except when their energy is exhausted
and leaves them too weak to keep what they have. If a government at once extended
its sphere and relaxed its stringency, its force would become absolutely nil, and it
would persist still less. It is therefore necessary to wind up the spring and tighten the
hold as it gives way: or else the State it sustains will come to grief.
The dissolution of the State may come about in either of two ways.
First, when the prince ceases to administer the State in accordance with the laws, and
usurps the Sovereign power. A remarkable change then occurs: not the government,
but the State, undergoes contraction; I mean that the great State is dissolved, and
another is formed within it, composed solely of the members of the government,
which becomes for the rest of the people merely master and tyrant. So that the
moment the government usurps the Sovereignty, the social compact is broken, and all
private citizens recover by right their natural liberty, and are forced, but not bound, to
obey.
The same thing happens when the members of the government severally usurp the
power they should exercise only as a body; this is as great an infraction of the laws,
and results in even greater disorders. There are then, so to speak, as many princes as
there are magistrates, and the State, no less divided than the government, either
perishes or changes its form.
When the State is dissolved, the abuse of government, whatever it is, bears the
common name of anarchy. To distinguish, democracy degenerates into ochlocracy,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
95
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
and aristocracy into oligarchy; and I would add that royalty degenerates into tyranny;
but this last word is ambiguous and needs explanation.
In vulgar usage, a tyrant is a king who governs violently and without regard for justice
and law. In the exact sense, a tyrant is an individual who arrogates to himself the royal
authority without having a right to it. This is how the Greeks understood the word
“tyrant”: they applied it indifferently to good and bad princes whose authority was not
legitimate.1Tyrant and usurper are thus perfectly synonymous terms.
In order that I may give different things different names, I call him who usurps the
royal authority a tyrant, and him who usurps the sovereign power a despot. The tyrant
is he who thrusts himself in contrary to the laws to govern in accordance with the
laws; the despot is he who sets himself above the laws themselves. Thus the tyrant
cannot be a despot, but the despot is always a tyrant.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
96
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER XI
The Death Of The Body Politic
Such is the natural and inevitable tendency of the best constituted governments. If
Sparta and Rome perished, what State can hope to endure for ever? If we would set up
a long-lived form of government, let us not even dream of making it eternal. If we are
to succeed, we must not attempt the impossible, or flatter ourselves that we are
endowing the work of man with a stability of which human conditions do not permit.
The body politic, as well as the human body, begins to die as soon as it is born, and
carries in itself the causes of its destruction. But both may have a constitution that is
more or less robust and suited to preserve them a longer or a shorter time. The
constitution of man is the work of nature; that of the State the work of art. It is not in
men’s power to prolong their own lives; but it is for them to prolong as much as
possible the life of the State, by giving it the best possible constitution. The best
constituted State will have an end; but it will end later than any other, unless some
unforeseen accident brings about its untimely destruction.
The life-principle of the body politic lies in the sovereign authority. The legislative
power is the heart of the State; the executive power is its brain, which causes the
movement of all the parts. The brain may become paralysed and the individual still
live. A man may remain an imbecile and live; but as soon as the heart ceases to
perform its functions, the animal is dead.
The State subsists by means not of the laws, but of the legislative power. Yesterday’s
law is not binding to-day; but silence is taken for tacit consent, and the Sovereign is
held to confirm incessantly the laws it does not abrogate as it might. All that it has
once declared itself to will it wills always, unless it revokes its declaration.
Why then is so much respect paid to old laws? For this very reason. We must believe
that nothing but the excellence of old acts of will can have preserved them so long: if
the Sovereign had not recognised them as throughout salutary, it would have revoked
them a thousand times. This is why, so far from growing weak, the laws continually
gain new strength in any well constituted State; the precedent of antiquity makes them
daily more venerable: while wherever the laws grow weak as they become old, this
proves that there is no longer a legislative power, and that the State is dead.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
97
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER XII
How The Sovereign Authority Maintains Itself
The Sovereign, having no force other than the legislative power, acts only by means
of the laws; and the laws being solely the authentic acts of the general will, the
Sovereign cannot act save when the people is assembled. The people in assembly, I
shall be told, is a mere chimera. It is so to-day, but two thousand years ago it was not
so. Has man’s nature changed?
The bounds of possibility, in moral matters, are less narrow than we imagine: it is our
weaknesses, our vices and our prejudices that confine them. Base souls have no belief
in great men; vile slaves smile in mockery at the name of liberty.
Let us judge of what can be done by what has been done. I shall say nothing of the
Republics of ancient Greece; but the Roman Republic was, to my mind, a great State,
and the town of Rome a great town. The last census showed that there were in Rome
four hundred thousand citizens capable of bearing arms, and the last computation of
the population of the Empire showed over four million citizens, excluding subjects,
foreigners, women, children and slaves.
What difficulties might not be supposed to stand in the way of the frequent
assemblage of the vast population of this capital and its neighbourhood. Yet few
weeks passed without the Roman people being in assembly, and even being so several
times. It exercised not only the rights of Sovereignty, but also a part of those of
government. It dealt with certain matters, and judged certain cases, and this whole
people was found in the public meeting-place hardly less often as magistrates than as
citizens.
If we went back to the earliest history of nations, we should find that most ancient
governments, even those of monarchical form, such as the Macedonian and the
Frankish, had similar councils. In any case, the one incontestable fact I have given is
an answer to all difficulties; it is good logic to reason from the actual to the possible.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
98
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER XIII
The Same (Continued)
It is not enough for the assembled people to have once fixed the constitution of the
State by giving its sanction to a body of law; it is not enough for it to have set up a
perpetual government, or provided once for all for the election of magistrates. Besides
the extraordinary assemblies unforeseen circumstances may demand, there must be
fixed periodical assemblies which cannot be abrogated or prorogued, so that on the
proper day the people is legitimately called together by law, without need of any
formal summoning.
But, apart from these assemblies authorised by their date alone, every assembly of the
people not summoned by the magistrates appointed for that purpose, and in
accordance with the prescribed forms, should be regarded as unlawful, and all its acts
as null and void, because the command to assemble should itself proceed from the
law.
The greater or less frequency with which lawful assemblies should occur depends on
so many considerations that no exact rules about them can be given. It can only be
said generally that the stronger the government the more often should the Sovereign
show itself.
This, I shall be told, may do for a single town; but what is to be done when the State
includes several? Is the sovereign authority to be divided? Or is it to be concentrated
in a single town to which all the rest are made subject?
Neither the one nor the other, I reply. First, the sovereign authority is one and simple,
and cannot be divided without being destroyed. In the second place, one town cannot,
any more than one nation, legitimately be made subject to another, because the
essence of the body politic lies in the reconciliation of obedience and liberty, and the
words subject and Sovereign are identical correlatives the idea of which meets in the
single word “citizen.”
I answer further that the union of several towns in a single city is always bad, and
that, if we wish to make such a union, we should not expect to avoid its natural
disadvantages. It is useless to bring up abuses that belong to great States against one
who desires to see only small ones; but how can small States be given the strength to
resist great ones, as formerly the Greek towns resisted the Great King, and more
recently Holland and Switzerland have resisted the House of Austria?
Nevertheless, if the State cannot be reduced to the right limits, there remains still one
resource; this is, to allow no capital, to make the seat of government move from town
to town, and to assemble by turn in each the Provincial Estates of the country.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
99
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
People the territory evenly, extend everywhere the same rights, bear to every place in
it abundance and life: by these means will the State become at once as strong and as
well governed as possible. Remember that the walls of towns are built of the ruins of
the houses of the countryside. For every palace I see raised in the capital, my mind’s
eye sees a whole country made desolate.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
100
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER XIV
The Same (Continued)
The moment the people is legitimately assembled as a sovereign body, the jurisdiction
of the government wholly lapses, the executive power is suspended, and the person of
the meanest citizen is as sacred and inviolable as that of the first magistrate; for in the
presence of the person represented, representatives no longer exist. Most of the
tumults that arose in the comitia at Rome were due to ignorance or neglect of this
rule. The consuls were in them merely the presidents of the people; the tribunes were
mere speakers;1 the senate was nothing at all.
These intervals of suspension, during which the prince recognises or ought to
recognise an actual superior, have always been viewed by him with alarm; and these
assemblies of the people, which are the aegis of the body politic and the curb on the
government, have at all times been the horror of rulers: who therefore never spare
pains, objections, difficulties, and promises, to stop the citizens from having them.
When the citizens are greedy, cowardly, and pusillanimous, and love ease more than
liberty, they do not long hold out against the redoubled efforts of the government; and
thus, as the resisting force incessantly grows, the sovereign authority ends by
disappearing, and most cities fall and perish before their time.
But between the sovereign authority and arbitrary government there sometimes
intervenes a mean power of which something must be said.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
101
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER XV
Deputies Or Representatives
As soon as public service ceases to be the chief business of the citizens, and they
would rather serve with their money than with their persons, the State is not far from
its fall. When it is necessary to march out to war, they pay troops and stay at home:
when it is necessary to meet in council, they name deputies and stay at home. By
reason of idleness and money, they end by having soldiers to enslave their country
and representatives to sell it.
It is through the hustle of commerce and the arts, through the greedy self-interest of
profit, and through softness and love of amenities that personal services are replaced
by money payments. Men surrender a part of their profits in order to have time to
increase them at leisure. Make gifts of money, and you will not be long without
chains. The word finance is a slavish word, unknown in the city-state. In a country
that is truly free, the citizens do everything with their own arms and nothing by means
of money; so far from paying to be exempted from their duties, they would even pay
for the privilege of fulfilling them themselves. I am far from taking the common view:
I hold enforced labour to be less opposed to liberty than taxes.
The better the constitution of a State is, the more do public affairs encroach on private
in the minds of the citizens. Private affairs are even of much less importance, because
the aggregate of the common happiness furnishes a greater proportion of that of each
individual, so that there is less for him to seek in particular cares. In a well-ordered
city every man flies to the assemblies: under a bad government no one cares to stir a
step to get to them, because no one is interested in what happens there, because it is
foreseen that the general will will not prevail, and lastly because domestic cares are
all-absorbing. Good laws lead to the making of better ones; bad ones bring about
worse. As soon as any man says of the affairs of the State What does it matter to me?
the State may be given up for lost.
The lukewarmness of patriotism, the activity of private interest, the vastness of States,
conquest and the abuse of government suggested the method of having deputies or
representatives of the people in the national assemblies. These are what, in some
countries, men have presumed to call the Third Estate. Thus the individual interest of
two orders is put first and second; the public interest occupies only the third place.
Sovereignty, for the same reason as makes it inalienable, cannot be represented; it lies
essentially in the general will, and will does not admit of representation: it is either the
same, or other; there is no intermediate possibility. The deputies of the people,
therefore, are not and cannot be its representatives: they are merely its stewards, and
can carry through no definitive acts. Every law the people has not ratified in person is
null and void—is, in fact, not a law. The people of England regards itself as free; but
it is grossly mistaken; it is free only during the election of members of parliament. As
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
102
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
soon as they are elected, slavery overtakes it, and it is nothing. The use it makes of the
short moments of liberty it enjoys shows indeed that it deserves to lose them.
The idea of representation is modern; it comes to us from feudal government, from
that iniquitous and absurd system which degrades humanity and dishonours the name
of man. In ancient republics and even in monarchies, the people never had
representatives; the word itself was unknown. It is very singular that in Rome, where
the tribunes were so sacrosanct, it was never even imagined that they could usurp the
functions of the people, and that in the midst of so great a multitude they never
attempted to pass on their own authority a single plebiscitum. We can, however, form
an idea of the difficulties caused sometimes by the people being so numerous, from
what happened in the time of the Gracchi, when some of the citizens had to cast their
votes from the roofs of buildings.
Where right and liberty are everything, disadvantages count for nothing. Among this
wise people everything was given its just value, its lictors were allowed to do what its
tribunes would never have dared to attempt; for it had no fear that its lictors would try
to represent it.
To explain, however, in what way the tribunes did sometimes represent it, it is enough
to conceive how the government represents the Sovereign. Law being purely the
declaration of the general will, it is clear that, in the exercise of the legislative power,
the people cannot be represented; but in that of the executive power, which is only the
force that is applied to give the law effect, it both can and should be represented. We
thus see that if we looked closely into the matter we should find that very few nations
have any laws. However that may be, it is certain that the tribunes, possessing no
executive power, could never represent the Roman people by right of the powers
entrusted to them, but only by usurping those of the senate.
In Greece, all that the people had to do, it did for itself; it was constantly assembled in
the public square. The Greeks lived in a mild climate; they had no natural greed;
slaves did their work for them; their great concern was with liberty. Lacking the same
advantages, how can you preserve the same rights? Your severer climates add to your
needs;1 for half the year your public squares are uninhabitable; the flatness of your
languages unfits them for being heard in the open air; you sacrifice more for profit
than for liberty, and fear slavery less than poverty.
What then? Is liberty maintained only by the help of slavery? It may be so. Extremes
meet. Everything that is not in the course of nature has its disadvantages, civil society
most of all. There are some unhappy circumstances in which we can only keep our
liberty at others’ expense, and where the citizen can be perfectly free only when the
slave is most a slave. Such was the case with Sparta. As for you, modern peoples, you
have no slaves, but you are slaves yourselves; you pay for their liberty with your own.
It is in vain that you boast of this preference; I find in it more cowardice than
humanity.
I do not mean by all this that it is necessary to have slaves, or that the right of slavery
is legitimate: I am merely giving the reasons why modern peoples, believing
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
103
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
themselves to be free, have representatives, while ancient peoples had none. In any
case, the moment a people allows itself to be represented, it is no longer free: it no
longer exists.
All things considered, I do not see that it is possible henceforth for the Sovereign to
preserve among us the exercise of its rights, unless the city is very small. But if it is
very small, it will be conquered? No. I will show later on how the external strength of
a great people1 may be combined with the convenient polity and good order of a
small State.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
104
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER XVI
That The Institution Of Government Is Not A Contract
The legislative power once well established, the next thing is to establish similarly the
executive power; for this latter, which operates only by particular acts, not being of
the essence of the former, is naturally separate from it. Were it possible for the
Sovereign, as such, to possess the executive power, right and fact would be so
confounded that no one could tell what was law and what was not; and the body
politic, thus disfigured, would soon fall a prey to the violence it was instituted to
prevent.
As the citizens, by the social contract, are all equal, all can prescribe what all should
do, but no one has a right to demand that another shall do what he does not do
himself. It is strictly this right, which is indispensable for giving the body politic life
and movement, that the Sovereign, in instituting the government, confers upon the
prince.
It has been held that this act of establishment was a contract between the people and
the rulers it sets over itself,—a contract in which conditions were laid down between
the two parties binding the one to command and the other to obey. It will be admitted,
I am sure, that this is an odd kind of contract to enter into. But let us see if this view
can be upheld.
First, the supreme authority can no more be modified than it can be alienated; to limit
it is to destroy it. It is absurd and contradictory for the Sovereign to set a superior over
itself; to bind itself to obey a master would be to return to absolute liberty.
Moreover, it is clear that this contract between the people and such and such persons
would be a particular act; and from this it follows that it can be neither a law nor an
act of Sovereignty, and that consequently it would be illegitimate.
It is plain too that the contracting parties in relation to each other would be under the
law of nature alone and wholly without guarantees of their mutual undertakings, a
position wholly at variance with the civil state. He who has force at his command
being always in a position to control execution, it would come to the same thing if the
name “contract” were given to the act of one man who said to another; “I give you all
my goods, on condition that you give me back as much of them as you please.”
There is only one contract in the State, and that is the act of association, which in
itself excludes the existence of a second. It is impossible to conceive of any public
contract that would not be a violation of the first.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
105
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER XVII
The Institution Of Government
Under what general idea then should the act by which government is instituted be
conceived as falling? I will begin by stating that the act is complex, as being
composed of two others—the establishment of the law and its execution.
By the former, the Sovereign decrees that there shall be a governing body established
in this or that form; this act is clearly a law.
By the latter, the people nominates the rulers who are to be entrusted with the
government that has been established. This nomination, being a particular act, is
clearly not a second law, but merely a consequence of the first and a function of
government.
The difficulty is to understand how there can be a governmental act before
government exists, and how the people, which is only Sovereign or subject, can,
under certain circumstances, become a prince or magistrate.
It is at this point that there is revealed one of the astonishing properties of the body
politic, by means of which it reconciles apparently contradictory operations; for this is
accomplished by a sudden conversion of Sovereignty into democracy, so that, without
sensible change, and merely by virtue of a new relation of all to all, the citizens
become magistrates and pass from general to particular acts, from legislation to the
execution of the law.
This changed relation is no speculative subtlety without instances in practice: it
happens every day in the English Parliament, where, on certain occasions, the Lower
House resolves itself into Grand Committee, for the better discussion of affairs, and
thus, from being at one moment a sovereign court, becomes at the next a mere
commission; so that subsequently it reports to itself, as House of Commons, the result
of its proceedings in Grand Committee, and debates over again under one name what
it has already settled under another.
It is, indeed, the peculiar advantage of democratic government that it can be
established in actuality by a simple act of the general will. Subsequently, this
provisional government remains in power, if this form is adopted, or else establishes
in the name of the Sovereign the government that is prescribed by law; and thus the
whole proceeding is regular. It is impossible to set up government in any other
manner legitimately and in accordance with the principles so far laid down.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
106
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER XVIII
How To Check The Usurpations Of Government
What we have just said confirms Chapter XVI, and makes it clear that the institution
of government is not a contract, but a law; that the depositaries of the executive power
are not the people’s masters, but its officers; that it can set them up and pull them
down when it likes; that for them there is no question of contract, but of obedience;
and that in taking charge of the functions the State imposes on them they are doing no
more than fulfilling their duty as citizens, without having the remotest right to argue
about the conditions.
When therefore the people sets up an hereditary government, whether it be
monarchical and confined to one family, or aristocratic and confined to a class, what it
enters into is not an undertaking; the administration is given a provisional form, until
the people chooses to order it otherwise.
It is true that such changes are always dangerous, and that the established government
should never be touched except when it comes to be incompatible with the public
good; but the circumspection this involves is a maxim of policy and not a rule of
right, and the State is no more bound to leave civil authority in the hands of its rulers
than military authority in the hands of its generals.
It is also true that it is impossible to be too careful to observe, in such cases, all the
formalities necessary to distinguish a regular and legitimate act from a seditious
tumult, and the will of a whole people from the clamour of a faction. Here above all
no further concession should be made to the untoward possibility than cannot, in the
strictest logic, be refused it. From this obligation the prince derives a great advantage
in preserving his power despite the people, without it being possible to say he has
usurped it; for, seeming to avail himself only of his rights, he finds it very easy to
extend them, and to prevent, under the pretext of keeping the peace, assemblies that
are destined to the re-establishment of order; with the result that he takes advantage of
a silence he does not allow to be broken, or of irregularities he causes to be
committed, to assume that he has the support of those whom fear prevents from
speaking, and to punish those who dare to speak. Thus it was that the decemvirs, first
elected for one year and then kept on in office for a second, tried to perpetuate their
power by forbidding the comitia to assemble; and by this easy method every
government in the world, once clothed with the public power, sooner or later usurps
the sovereign authority.
The periodical assemblies of which I have already spoken are designed to prevent or
postpone this calamity, above all when they need no formal summoning; for in that
case, the prince cannot stop them without openly declaring himself a law-breaker and
an enemy of the State.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
107
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
The opening of these assemblies, whose sole object is the maintenance of the social
treaty, should always take the form of putting two propositions that may not be
suppressed, which should be voted on separately.
The first is: “Does it please the Sovereign to preserve the present form of
government?”
The second is: “Does it please the people to leave its administration in the hands of
those who are actually in charge of it?”
I am here assuming what I think I have shown; that there is in the State no
fundamental law that cannot be revoked, not excluding the social compact itself; for if
all the citizens assembled of one accord to break the compact, it is impossible to doubt
that it would be very legitimately broken. Grotius even thinks that each man can
renounce his membership of his own State, and recover his natural liberty and his
goods on leaving the country.1 It would be indeed absurd if all the citizens in
assembly could not do what each can do by himself.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
108
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
BOOK IV
CHAPTER I
That The General Will Is Indestructible
As long as several men in assembly regard themselves as a single body, they have
only a single will which is concerned with their common preservation and general
well-being. In this case, all the springs of the State are vigorous and simple and its
rules clear and luminous; there are no embroilments or conflicts of interests; the
common good is everywhere clearly apparent, and only good sense is needed to
perceive it. Peace, unity and equality are the enemies of political subtleties. Men who
are upright and simple are difficult to deceive because of their simplicity; lures and
ingenious pretexts fail to impose upon them, and they are not even subtle enough to
be dupes. When, among the happiest people in the world, bands of peasants are seen
regulating affairs of State under an oak, and always acting wisely, can we help
scorning the ingenious methods of other nations, which make themselves illustrious
and wretched with so much art and mystery?
A State so governed needs very few laws; and, as it becomes necessary to issue new
ones, the necessity is universally seen. The first man to propose them merely says
what all have already felt, and there is no question of factions or intrigues or
eloquence in order to secure the passage into law of what every one has already
decided to do, as soon as he is sure that the rest will act with him.
Theorists are led into error because, seeing only States that have been from the
beginning wrongly constituted, they are struck by the impossibility of applying such a
policy to them. They make great game of all the absurdities a clever rascal or an
insinuating speaker might get the people of Paris or London to believe. They do not
know that Cromwell would have been put to “the bells” by the people of Berne, and
the Duc de Beaufort on the treadmill by the Genevese.
But when the social bond begins to be relaxed and the State to grow weak, when
particular interests begin to make themselves felt and the smaller societies to exercise
an influence over the larger, the common interest changes and finds opponents:
opinion is no longer unanimous; the general will ceases to be the will of all;
contradictory views and debates arise; and the best advice is not taken without
question.
Finally, when the State, on the eve of ruin, maintains only a vain, illusory and formal
existence, when in every heart the social bond is broken, and the meanest interest
brazenly lays hold of the sacred name of “public good,” the general will becomes
mute: all men, guided by secret motives, no more give their views as citizens than if
the State had never been; and iniquitous decrees directed solely to private interest get
passed under the name of laws.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
109
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Does it follow from this that the general will is exterminated or corrupted? Not at all:
it is always constant, unalterable and pure; but it is subordinated to other wills which
encroach upon its sphere. Each man, in detaching his interest from the common
interest, sees clearly that he cannot entirely separate them; but his share in the public
mishaps seems to him negligible beside the exclusive good he aims at making his
own. Apart from this particular good, he wills the general good in his own interest, as
strongly as any one else. Even in selling his vote for money, he does not extinguish in
himself the general will, but only eludes it. The fault he commits is that of changing
the state of the question, and answering something different from what he is asked.
Instead of saying, by his vote, “It is to the advantage of the State,” he says, “It is of
advantage to this or that man or party that this or that view should prevail.” Thus the
law of public order in assemblies is not so much to maintain in them the general will
as to secure that the question be always put to it, and the answer always given by it.
I could here set down many reflections on the simple right of voting in every act of
Sovereignty—a right which no-one can take from the citizens—and also on the right
of stating views, making proposals, dividing and discussing, which the government is
always most careful to leave solely to its members; but this important subject would
need a treatise to itself, and it is impossible to say everything in a single work.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
110
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER II
Voting
It may be seen, from the last chapter, that the way in which general business is
managed may give a clear enough indication of the actual state of morals and the
health of the body politic. The more concert reigns in the assemblies, that is, the
nearer opinion approaches unanimity, the greater is the dominance of the general will.
On the other hand, long debates, dissensions and tumult proclaim the ascendancy of
particular interests and the decline of the State.
This seems less clear when two or more orders enter into the constitution, as
patricians and plebeians did at Rome; for quarrels between these two orders often
disturbed the comitia, even in the best days of the Republic. But the exception is
rather apparent than real; for then, through the defect that is inherent in the body
politic, there were, so to speak, two States in one, and what is not true of the two
together is true of either separately. Indeed, even in the most stormy times, the
plebiscita of the people, when the Senate did not interfere with them, always went
through quietly and by large majorities. The citizens having but one interest, the
people had but a single will.
At the other extremity of the circle, unanimity recurs; this is the case when the
citizens, having fallen into servitude, have lost both liberty and will. Fear and flattery
then change votes into acclamation; deliberation ceases, and only worship or
malediction is left. Such was the vile manner in which the senate expressed its views
under the Emperors. It did so sometimes with absurd precautions. Tacitus observes
that, under Otho, the senators, while they heaped curses on Vitellius, contrived at the
same time to make a deafening noise, in order that, should he ever become their
master, he might not know what each of them had said.
On these various considerations depend the rules by which the methods of counting
votes and comparing opinions should be regulated, according as the general will is
more or less easy to discover, and the State more or less in its decline.
There is but one law which, from its nature, needs unanimous consent. This is the
social compact; for civil association is the most voluntary of all acts. Every man being
born free and his own master, no-one, under any pretext whatsoever, can make any
man subject without his consent. To decide that the son of a slave is born a slave is to
decide that he is not born a man.
If then there are opponents when the social compact is made, their opposition does not
invalidate the contract, but merely prevents them from being included in it. They are
foreigners among citizens. When the State is instituted, residence constitutes consent;
to dwell within its territory is to submit to the Sovereign.1
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
111
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Apart from this primitive contract, the vote of the majority always binds all the rest.
This follows from the contract itself. But it is asked how a man can be both free and
forced to conform to wills that are not his own. How are the opponents at once free
and subject to laws they have not agreed to?
I retort that the question is wrongly put. The citizen gives his consent to all the laws,
including those which are passed in spite of his opposition, and even those which
punish him when he dares to break any of them. The constant will of all the members
of the State is the general will; by virtue of it they are citizens and free.2 When in the
popular assembly a law is proposed, what the people is asked is not exactly whether it
approves or rejects the proposal, but whether it is in conformity with the general will,
which is their will. Each man, in giving his vote, states his opinion on that point; and
the general will is found by counting votes. When therefore the opinion that is
contrary to my own prevails, this proves neither more nor less than that I was
mistaken, and that what I thought to be the general will was not so. If my particular
opinion had carried the day I should have achieved the opposite of what was my will;
and it is in that case that I should not have been free.
This presupposes, indeed, that all the qualities of the general will still reside in the
majority: when they cease to do so, whatever side a man may take, liberty is no longer
possible.
In my earlier demonstration of how particular wills are substituted for the general will
in public deliberation, I have adequately pointed out the practicable methods of
avoiding this abuse; and I shall have more to say of them later on. I have also given
the principles for determining the proportional number of votes for declaring that will.
A difference of one vote destroys equality; a single opponent destroys unanimity; but
between equality and unanimity, there are several grades of unequal division, at each
of which this proportion may be fixed in accordance with the condition and the needs
of the body politic.
There are two general rules that may serve to regulate this relation. First, the more
grave and important the questions discussed, the nearer should the opinion that is to
prevail approach unanimity. Secondly, the more the matter in hand calls for speed, the
smaller the prescribed difference in the numbers of votes may be allowed to become:
where an instant decision has to be reached, a majority of one vote should be enough.
The first of these two rules seems more in harmony with the laws, and the second
with practical affairs. In any case, it is the combination of them that gives the best
proportions for determining the majority necessary.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
112
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER III
Elections
In the elections of the prince and the magistrates, which are, as I have said, complex
acts, there are two possible methods of procedure, choice and lot. Both have been
employed in various republics, and a highly complicated mixture of the two still
survives in the election of the Doge at Venice.
“Election by lot,” says Montesquieu, “is democratic in nature.” I agree that it is so;
but in what sense? “The lot,” he goes on, “is a way of making choice that is unfair to
nobody; it leaves each citizen a reasonable hope of serving his country.” These are not
reasons.
If we bear in mind that the election of rulers is a function of government, and not of
Sovereignty, we shall see why the lot is the method more natural to democracy, in
which the administration is better in proportion as the number of its acts is small.
In every real democracy, magistracy is not an advantage, but a burdensome charge
which cannot justly be imposed on one individual rather than another. The law alone
can lay the charge on him on whom the lot falls. For, the conditions being then the
same for all, and the choice not depending on any human will, there is no particular
application to alter the universality of the law.
In an aristocracy, the prince chooses the prince, the government is preserved by itself,
and voting is rightly ordered.
The instance of the election of the Doge of Venice confirms, instead of destroying,
this distinction; the mixed form suits a mixed government. For it is an error to take the
government of Venice for a real aristocracy. If the people has no share in the
government, the nobility is itself the people. A host of poor Barnabotes never gets
near any magistracy, and its nobility consists merely in the empty title of Excellency,
and in the right to sit in the Great Council. As this Great Council is as numerous as
our General Council at Geneva, its illustrious members have no more privileges than
our plain citizens. It is indisputable that, apart from the extreme disparity between the
two republics, the bourgeoisie of Geneva is exactly equivalent to the patriciate of
Venice; our natives and inhabitants correspond to the townsmen and the people of
Venice; our peasants correspond to the subjects on the mainland; and, however that
republic be regarded, if its size be left out of account, its government is no more
aristocratic than our own. The whole difference is that, having no life-ruler, we do
not, like Venice, need to use the lot.
Election by lot would have few disadvantages in a real democracy, in which, as
equality would everywhere exist in morals and talents as well as in principles and
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
113
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
fortunes, it would become almost a matter of indifference who was chosen. But I have
already said that a real democracy is only an ideal.
When choice and lot are combined, positions that require special talents, such as
military posts, should be filled by the former; the latter does for cases, such as judicial
offices, in which good sense, justice, and integrity are enough, because in a State that
is well constituted, these qualities are common to all the citizens.
Neither lot nor vote has any place in monarchical government. The monarch being by
right sole prince and only magistrate, the choice of his lieutenants belongs to none but
him. When the Abbé de Saint-Pierre proposed that the Councils of the King of France
should be multiplied, and their members elected by ballot, he did not see that he was
proposing to change the form of government.
I should now speak of the methods of giving and counting opinions in the assembly of
the people; but perhaps an account of this aspect of the Roman constitution will more
forcibly illustrate all the rules I could lay down. It is worth the while of a judicious
reader to follow in some detail the working of public and private affairs in a Council
consisting of two hundred thousand men.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
114
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER IV
The Roman Comitia
We are without well-certified records of the first period of Rome’s existence; it even
appears very probable that most of the stories told about it are fables; indeed,
generally speaking, the most instructive part of the history of peoples, that which
deals with their foundation, is what we have least of. Experience teaches us every day
what causes lead to the revolutions of empires; but, as no new peoples are now
formed, we have almost nothing beyond conjecture to go upon in explaining how they
were created.
The customs we find established show at least that these customs had an origin. The
traditions that go back to those origins, that have the greatest authorities behind them,
and that are confirmed by the strongest proofs, should pass for the most certain. These
are the rules I have tried to follow in inquiring how the freest and most powerful
people on earth exercised its supreme power.
After the foundation of Rome, the new-born republic, that is, the army of its founder,
composed of Albans, Sabines and foreigners, was divided into three classes, which,
from this division, took the name of tribes. Each of these tribes was subdivided into
ten curiæ, and each curia into decuriæ, headed by leaders called curiones and
decuriones.
Besides this, out of each tribe was taken a body of one hundred Equites or Knights,
called a century, which shows that these divisions, being unnecessary in a town, were
at first merely military. But an instinct for greatness seems to have led the little
township of Rome to provide itself in advance with a political system suitable for the
capital of the world.
Out of this original division an awkward situation soon arose. The tribes of the Albans
(Ramnenses) and the Sabines (Tatienses) remained always in the same condition,
while that of the foreigners (Luceres) continually grew as more and more foreigners
came to live at Rome, so that it soon surpassed the others in strength. Servius
remedied this dangerous fault by changing the principle of cleavage, and substituting
for the racial division, which he abolished, a new one based on the quarter of the town
inhabited by each tribe. Instead of three tribes he created four, each occupying and
named after one of the hills of Rome. Thus, while redressing the inequality of the
moment, he also provided for the future; and in order that the division might be one of
persons as well as localities, he forbade the inhabitants of one quarter to migrate to
another, and so prevented the mingling of the races.
He also doubled the three old centuries of Knights and added twelve more, still
keeping the old names, and by this simple and prudent method, succeeded in making a
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
115
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
distinction between the body of Knights and the people, without a murmur from the
latter.
To the four urban tribes Servius added fifteen others called rural tribes, because they
consisted of those who lived in the country, divided into fifteen cantons.
Subsequently, fifteen more were created, and the Roman people finally found itself
divided into thirty-five tribes, as it remained down to the end of the Republic.
The distinction between urban and rural tribes had one effect which is worth mention,
both because it is without parallel elsewhere, and because to it Rome owed the
preservation of her morality and the enlargement of her empire. We should have
expected that the urban tribes would soon monopolise power and honours, and lose no
time in bringing the rural tribes into disrepute; but what happened was exactly the
reverse. The taste of the early Romans for country life is well known. This taste they
owed to their wise founder, who made rural and military labours go along with
liberty, and, so to speak, relegated to the town arts, crafts, intrigue, fortune and
slavery.
Since therefore all Rome’s most illustrious citizens lived in the fields and tilled the
earth, men grew used to seeking there alone the mainstays of the republic. This
condition, being that of the best patricians, was honoured by all men; the simple and
laborious life of the villager was preferred to the slothful and idle life of the
bourgeoisie of Rome; and he who, in the town, would have been but a wretched
proletarian, became, as a labourer in the fields, a respected citizen. Not without
reason, says Varro, did our great-souled ancestors establish in the village the nursery
of the sturdy and valiant men who defended them in time of war and provided for
their sustenance in time of peace. Pliny states positively that the country tribes were
honoured because of the men of whom they were composed; while cowards men
wished to dishonour were transferred, as a public disgrace, to the town tribes. The
Sabine Appius Claudius, when he had come to settle in Rome, was loaded with
honours and enrolled in a rural tribe, which subsequently took his family name.
Lastly, freedmen always entered the urban, and never the rural, tribes: nor is there a
single example, throughout the Republic, of a freedman, though he had become a
citizen, reaching any magistracy.
This was an excellent rule; but it was carried so far that in the end it led to a change
and certainly to an abuse in the political system.
First the censors, after having for a long time claimed the right of transferring citizens
arbitrarily from one tribe to another, allowed most persons to enrol themselves in
whatever tribe they pleased. This permission certainly did no good, and further robbed
the censorship of one of its greatest resources. Moreover, as the great and powerful all
got themselves enrolled in the country tribes, while the freedmen who had become
citizens remained with the populace in the town tribes, both soon ceased to have any
local or territorial meaning, and all were so confused that the members of one could
not be told from those of another except by the registers; so that the idea of the word
tribe became personal instead of real, or rather came to be little more than a chimera.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
116
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
It happened in addition that the town tribes, being more on the spot, were often the
stronger in the comitia and sold the State to those who stooped to buy the votes of the
rabble composing them.
As the founder had set up ten curiæ in each tribe, the whole Roman people, which
was then contained within the walls, consisted of thirty curiæ, each with its temples,
its gods, its officers, its priests and its festivals, which were called compitalia and
corresponded to the paganalia, held in later times by the rural tribes.
When Servius made his new division, as the thirty curiæ could not be shared equally
between his four tribes, and as he was unwilling to interfere with them, they became a
further division of the inhabitants of Rome, quite independent of the tribes: but in the
case of the rural tribes and their members there was no question of curiæ, as the tribes
had then become a purely civil institution, and, a new system of levying troops having
been introduced, the military divisions of Romulus were superfluous. Thus, although
every citizen was enrolled in a tribe, there were very many who were not members of
a curia.
Servius made yet a third division, quite distinct from the two we have mentioned,
which became, in its effects, the most important of all. He distributed the whole
Roman people into six classes, distinguished neither by place nor by person, but by
wealth; the first classes included the rich, the last the poor, and those between persons
of moderate means. These six classes were subdivided into one hundred and ninety-
three other bodies, called centuries, which were so divided that the first class alone
comprised more than half of them, while the last comprised only one. Thus the class
that had the smallest number of members had the largest number of centuries, and the
whole of the last class only counted as a single subdivision, although it alone included
more than half the inhabitants of Rome.
In order that the people might have the less insight into the results of this
arrangement, Servius tried to give it a military tone: in the second class he inserted
two centuries of armourers, and in the fourth two of makers of instruments of war: in
each class, except the last, he distinguished young and old, that is, those who were
under an obligation to bear arms and those whose age gave them legal exemption. It
was this distinction, rather than that of wealth, which required frequent repetition of
the census or counting. Lastly, he ordered that the assembly should be held in the
Campus Martius, and that all who were of age to serve should come there armed.
The reason for his not making in the last class also the division of young and old was
that the populace, of whom it was composed, was not given the right to bear arms for
its country: a man had to possess a hearth to acquire the right to defend it, and of all
the troops of beggars who to-day lend lustre to the armies of kings, there is perhaps
not one who would not have been driven with scorn out of a Roman cohort, at a time
when soldiers were the defenders of liberty.
In this last class, however, proletarians were distinguished from capite censi. The
former, not quite reduced to nothing, at least gave the State citizens, and sometimes,
when the need was pressing, even soldiers. Those who had nothing at all, and could
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
117
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
be numbered only by counting heads, were regarded as of absolutely no account, and
Marius was the first who stooped to enrol them.
Without deciding now whether this third arrangement was good or bad in itself, I
think I may assert that it could have been made practicable only by the simple morals,
the disinterestedness, the liking for agriculture and the scorn for commerce and for
love of gain which characterised the early Romans. Where is the modern people
among whom consuming greed, unrest, intrigue, continual removals, and perpetual
changes of fortune, could let such a system last for twenty years without turning the
State upside down? We must indeed observe that morality and the censorship, being
stronger than this institution, corrected its defects at Rome, and that the rich man
found himself degraded to the class of the poor for making too much display of his
riches.
From all this it is easy to understand why only five classes are almost always
mentioned, though there were really six. The sixth, as it furnished neither soldiers to
the army nor votes in the Campus Martius,1 and was almost without function in the
State, was seldom regarded as of any account.
These were the various ways in which the Roman people was divided. Let us now see
the effect on the assemblies. When lawfully summoned, these were called comitia:
they were usually held in the public square at Rome or in the Campus Martius, and
were distinguished as Comitia Curiata, Comitia Centuriata, and Comitia Tributa,
according to the form under which they were convoked. The Comitia Curiata were
founded by Romulus; the Centuriata by Servius; and the Tributa by the tribunes of
the people. No law received its sanction and no magistrate was elected, save in the
comitia; and as every citizen was enrolled in a curia, a century, or a tribe, it follows
that no citizen was excluded from the right of voting, and that the Roman people was
truly sovereign both de jure and de facto.
For the comitia to be lawfully assembled, and for their acts to have the force of law,
three conditions were necessary. First, the body or magistrate convoking them had to
possess the necessary authority; secondly, the assembly had to be held on a day
allowed by law; and thirdly, the auguries had to be favourable.
The reason for the first regulation needs no explanation; the second is a matter of
policy. Thus, the comitia might not be held on festivals or market-days, when the
country-folk, coming to Rome on business, had not time to spend the day in the public
square. By means of the third, the senate held in check the proud and restive people,
and meetly restrained the ardour of seditious tribunes, who, however, found more than
one way of escaping this hindrance.
Laws and the election of rulers were not the only questions submitted to the judgment
of the comitia: as the Roman people had taken on itself the most important functions
of government, it may be said that the lot of Europe was regulated in its assemblies.
The variety of their objects gave rise to the various forms these took, according to the
matters on which they had to pronounce.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
118
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
In order to judge of these various forms, it is enough to compare them. Romulus,
when he set up curiæ, had in view the checking of the senate by the people, and of the
people by the senate, while maintaining his ascendancy over both alike. He therefore
gave the people, by means of this assembly, all the authority of numbers to balance
that of power and riches, which he left to the patricians. But, after the spirit of
monarchy, he left all the same a greater advantage to the patricians in the influence of
their clients on the majority of votes. This excellent institution of patron and client
was a masterpiece of statesmanship and humanity without which the patriciate, being
flagrantly in contradiction to the republican spirit, could not have survived. Rome
alone has the honour of having given to the world this great example, which never led
to any abuse, and yet has never been followed.
As the assemblies by curiæ persisted under the kings till the time of Servius, and the
reign of the later Tarquin was not regarded as legitimate, royal laws were called
generally leges curiatæ.
Under the Republic, the curiæ, still confined to the four urban tribes, and including
only the populace of Rome, suited neither the senate, which led the patricians, nor the
tribunes, who, though plebeians, were at the head of the well-to-do citizens. They
therefore fell into disrepute, and their degradation was such, that thirty lictors used to
assemble and do what the Comitia Curiata should have done.
The division by centuries was so favourable to the aristocracy that it is hard to see at
first how the senate ever failed to carry the day in the comitia bearing their name, by
which the consuls, the censors and the other curule magistrates were elected. Indeed,
of the hundred and ninety-three centuries into which the six classes of the whole
Roman people were divided, the first class contained ninety-eight; and, as voting went
solely by centuries, this class alone had a majority over all the rest. When all these
centuries were in agreement, the rest of the votes were not even taken; the decision of
the smallest number passed for that of the multitude, and it may be said that, in the
Comitia Centuriata, decisions were regulated far more by depth of purses than by the
number of votes.
But this extreme authority was modified in two ways. First, the tribunes as a rule, and
always a great number of plebeians, belonged to the class of the rich, and so
counterbalanced the influence of the patricians in the first class.
The second way was this. Instead of causing the centuries to vote throughout in order,
which would have meant beginning always with the first, the Romans always chose
one by lot which proceeded alone to the election; after this all the centuries were
summoned another day according to their rank, and the same election was repeated,
and as a rule confirmed. Thus the authority of example was taken away from rank,
and given to the lot on a democratic principle.
From this custom resulted a further advantage. The citizens from the country had
time, between the two elections, to inform themselves of the merits of the candidate
who had been provisionally nominated, and did not have to vote without knowledge
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
119
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
of the case. But, under the pretext of hastening matters, the abolition of this custom
was achieved, and both elections were held on the same day.
The Comitia Tributa were properly the council of the Roman people. They were
convoked by the tribunes alone; at them the tribunes were elected and passed their
plebiscita. The senate not only had no standing in them, but even no right to be
present; and the senators, being forced to obey laws on which they could not vote,
were in this respect less free than the meanest citizens. This injustice was altogether
ill-conceived, and was alone enough to invalidate the decrees of a body to which all
its members were not admitted. Had all the patricians attended the comitia by virtue
of the right they had as citizens, they would not, as mere private individuals, have had
any considerable influence on a vote reckoned by counting heads, where the meanest
proletarian was as good as the princeps senatus.
It may be seen, therefore, that besides the order which was achieved by these various
ways of distributing so great a people and taking its votes, the various methods were
not reducible to forms indifferent in themselves, but the results of each were relative
to the objects which caused it to be preferred.
Without going here into further details, we may gather from what has been said above
that the Comitia Tributa were the most favourable to popular government, and the
Comitia Centuriata to aristocracy. The Comitia Curiata, in which the populace of
Rome formed the majority, being fitted only to further tyranny and evil designs,
naturally fell into disrepute, and even seditious persons abstained from using a
method which too clearly revealed their projects. It is indisputable that the whole
majesty of the Roman people lay solely in the Comitia Centuriata, which alone
included all; for the Comitia Curiata excluded the rural tribes, and the Comitia
Tributa the senate and the patricians.
As for the method of taking the vote, it was among the ancient Romans as simple as
their morals, although not so simple as at Sparta. Each man declared his vote aloud,
and a clerk duly wrote it down; the majority in each tribe determined the vote of the
tribe, the majority of the tribes that of the people, and so with curiæ and centuries.
This custom was good as long as honesty was triumphant among the citizens, and
each man was ashamed to vote publicly in favour of an unjust proposal or an
unworthy subject; but, when the people grew corrupt and votes were bought, it was
fitting that voting should be secret in order that purchasers might be restrained by
mistrust, and rogues be given the means of not being traitors.
I know that Cicero attacks this change, and attributes partly to it the ruin of the
Republic. But though I feel the weight Cicero’s authority must carry on such a point, I
cannot agree with him; I hold, on the contrary, that, for want of enough such changes,
the destruction of the State must be hastened. Just as the regimen of health does not
suit the sick, we should not wish to govern a people that has been corrupted by the
laws that a good people requires. There is no better proof of this rule than the long life
of the Republic of Venice, of which the shadow still exists, solely because its laws are
suitable only for men who are wicked.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
120
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
The citizens were provided, therefore, with tablets by means of which each man could
vote without any one knowing how he voted: new methods were also introduced for
collecting the tablets, for counting voices, for comparing numbers, etc.; but all these
precautions did not prevent the good faith of the officers charged with these
functions1 from being often suspect. Finally, to prevent intrigues and trafficking in
votes, edicts were issued; but their very number proves how useless they were.
Towards the close of the Republic, it was often necessary to have recourse to
extraordinary expedients in order to supplement the inadequacy of the laws.
Sometimes miracles were supposed; but this method, while it might impose on the
people, could not impose on those who governed. Sometimes an assembly was hastily
called together, before the candidates had time to form their factions: sometimes a
whole sitting was occupied with talk, when it was seen that the people had been won
over and was on the point of taking up a wrong position. But in the end ambition
eluded all attempts to check it; and the most incredible fact of all is that, in the midst
of all these abuses, the vast people, thanks to its ancient regulations, never ceased to
elect magistrates, to pass laws, to judge cases, and to carry through business both
public and private, almost as easily as the senate itself could have done.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
121
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER V
The Tribunate
When an exact proportion cannot be established between the constituent parts of the
State, or when causes that cannot be removed continually alter the relation of one part
to another, recourse is had to the institution of a peculiar magistracy that enters into
no corporate unity with the rest. This restores to each term its right relation to the
others, and provides a link or middle term between either prince and people, or prince
and Sovereign, or, if necessary, both at once.
This body, which I shall call the tribunate, is the preserver of the laws and of the
legislative power. It serves sometimes to protect the Sovereign against the
government, as the tribunes of the people did at Rome; sometimes to uphold the
government against the people, as the Council of Ten now does at Venice; and
sometimes to maintain the balance between the two, as the Ephors did at Sparta.
The tribunate is not a constituent part of the city, and should have no share in either
legislative or executive power; but this very fact makes its own power the greater: for,
while it can do nothing, it can prevent anything from being done. It is more sacred and
more revered, as the defender of the laws, than the prince who executes them, or than
the Sovereign which ordains them. This was seen very clearly at Rome, when the
proud patricians, for all their scorn of the people, were forced to bow before one of its
officers, who had neither auspices nor jurisdiction.
The tribunate, wisely tempered, is the strongest support a good constitution can have;
but if its strength is ever so little excessive, it upsets the whole State. Weakness, on
the other hand, is not natural to it: provided it is something, it is never less than it
should be.
It degenerates into tyranny when it usurps the executive power, which it should
confine itself to restraining, and when it tries to dispense with the laws, which it
should confine itself to protecting. The immense power of the Ephors, harmless as
long as Sparta preserved its morality, hastened corruption when once it had begun.
The blood of Agis, slaughtered by these tyrants, was avenged by his successor; the
crime and the punishment of the Ephors alike hastened the destruction of the republic,
and after Cleomenes Sparta ceased to be of any account. Rome perished in the same
way: the excessive power of the tribunes, which they had usurped by degrees, finally
served, with the help of laws made to secure liberty, as a safeguard for the emperors
who destroyed it. As for the Venetian Council of Ten, it is a tribunal of blood, an
object of horror to patricians and people alike; and, so far from giving a lofty
protection to the laws, it does nothing, now they have become degraded, but strike in
the darkness blows of which no one dare take note.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
122
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
The tribunate, like the government, grows weak as the number of its members
increases. When the tribunes of the Roman people, who first numbered only two, and
then five, wished to double that number, the senate let them do so, in the confidence
that it could use one to check another, as indeed it afterwards freely did.
The best method of preventing usurpations by so formidable a body, though no
government has yet made use of it, would be not to make it permanent, but to regulate
the periods during which it should remain in abeyance. These intervals, which should
not be long enough to give abuses time to grow strong, may be so fixed by law that
they can easily be shortened at need by extraordinary commissions.
This method seems to me to have no disadvantages, because, as I have said, the
tribunate, which forms no part of the constitution, can be removed without the
constitution being affected. It seems to be also efficacious, because a newly restored
magistrate starts not with the power his predecessor exercised, but with that which the
law allows him.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
123
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER VI
The Dictatorship
The inflexibility of the laws, which prevents them from adapting themselves to
circumstances, may, in certain cases, render them disastrous, and make them bring
about, at a time of crisis, the ruin of the State. The order and slowness of the forms
they enjoin require a space of time which circumstances sometimes withhold. A
thousand cases against which the legislator has made no provision may present
themselves, and it is a highly necessary part of foresight to be conscious that
everything cannot be foreseen.
It is wrong therefore to wish to make political institutions so strong as to render it
impossible to suspend their operation. Even Sparta allowed its laws to lapse.
However, none but the greatest dangers can counter-balance that of changing the
public order, and the sacred power of the laws should never be arrested save when the
existence of the country is at stake. In these rare and obvious cases, provision is made
for the public security by a particular act entrusting it to him who is most worthy. This
commitment may be carried out in either of two ways, according to the nature of the
danger.
If increasing the activity of the government is a sufficient remedy, power is
concentrated in the hands of one or two of its members: in this case the change is not
in the authority of the laws, but only in the form of administering them. If, on the
other hand, the peril is of such a kind that the paraphernalia of the laws are an obstacle
to their preservation, the method is to nominate a supreme ruler, who shall silence all
the laws and suspend for a moment the sovereign authority. In such a case, there is no
doubt about the general will, and it is clear that the people’s first intention is that the
State shall not perish. Thus the suspension of the legislative authority is in no sense its
abolition; the magistrate who silences it cannot make it speak; he dominates it, but
cannot represent it. He can do anything, except make laws.
The first method was used by the Roman senate when, in a consecrated formula, it
charged the consuls to provide for the safety of the Republic. The second was
employed when one of the two consuls nominated a dictator:1 a custom Rome
borrowed from Alba.
During the first period of the Republic, recourse was very often had to the
dictatorship, because the State had not yet a firm enough basis to be able to maintain
itself by the strength of its constitution alone. As the state of morality then made
superfluous many of the precautions which would have been necessary at other times,
there was no fear that a dictator would abuse his authority, or try to keep it beyond his
term of office. On the contrary, so much power appeared to be burdensome to him
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
124
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
who was clothed with it, and he made all speed to lay it down, as if taking the place of
the laws had been too troublesome and too perilous a position to retain.
It is therefore the danger not of its abuse, but of its cheapening, that makes me attack
the indiscreet use of this supreme magistracy in the earliest times. For as long as it
was freely employed at elections, dedications and purely formal functions, there was
danger of its becoming less formidable in time of need, and of men growing
accustomed to regarding as empty a title that was used only on occasions of empty
ceremonial.
Towards the end of the Republic, the Romans, having grown more circumspect, were
as unreasonably sparing in the use of the dictatorship as they had formerly been
lavish. It is easy to see that their fears were without foundation, that the weakness of
the capital secured it against the magistrates who were in its midst; that a dictator
might, in certain cases, defend the public liberty, but could never endanger it; and that
the chains of Rome would be forged, not in Rome itself, but in her armies. The weak
resistance offered by Marius to Sulla, and by Pompey to Cæsar, clearly showed what
was to be expected from authority at home against force from abroad.
This misconception led the Romans to make great mistakes; such, for example, as the
failure to nominate a dictator in the Catilinarian conspiracy. For, as only the city
itself, with at most some province in Italy, was concerned, the unlimited authority the
laws gave to the dictator would have enabled him to make short work of the
conspiracy, which was, in fact, stifled only by a combination of lucky chances human
prudence had no right to expect.
Instead, the senate contented itself with entrusting its whole power to the consuls, so
that Cicero, in order to take effective action, was compelled on a capital point to
exceed his powers; and if, in the first transports of joy, his conduct was approved, he
was justly called, later on, to account for the blood of citizens spilt in violation of the
laws. Such a reproach could never have been levelled at a dictator. But the consul’s
eloquence carried the day; and he himself, Roman though he was, loved his own glory
better than his country, and sought, not so much the most lawful and secure means of
saving the State, as to get for himself the whole honour of having done so.1 He was
therefore justly honoured as the liberator of Rome, and also justly punished as a law-
breaker. However brilliant his recall may have been, it was undoubtedly an act of
pardon.
However this important trust be conferred, it is important that its duration should be
fixed at a very brief period, incapable of being ever prolonged. In the crises which
lead to its adoption, the State is either soon lost, or soon saved; and, the present need
passed, the dictatorship becomes either tyrannical or idle. At Rome, where dictators
held office for six months only, most of them abdicated before their time was up. If
their term had been longer, they might well have tried to prolong it still further, as the
decemvirs did when chosen for a year. The dictator had only time to provide against
the need that had caused him to be chosen; he had none to think of further projects.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
125
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER VII
The Censorship
As the law is the declaration of the general will, the censorship is the declaration of
the public judgment: public opinion is the form of law which the censor administers,
and, like the prince, only applies to particular cases.
The censorial tribunal, so far from being the arbiter of the people’s opinion, only
declares it, and, as soon as the two part company, its decisions are null and void.
It is useless to distinguish the morality of a nation from the objects of its esteem; both
depend on the same principle and are necessarily indistinguishable. There is no people
on earth the choice of whose pleasures is not decided by opinion rather than nature.
Right men’s opinions, and their morality will purge itself. Men always love what is
good or what they find good; it is in judging what is good that they go wrong. This
judgment, therefore, is what must be regulated. He who judges of morality judges of
honour; and he who judges of honour finds his law in opinion.
The opinions of a people are derived from its constitution; although the law does not
regulate morality, it is legislation that gives it birth. When legislation grows weak,
morality degenerates; but in such cases the judgment of the censors will not do what
the force of the laws has failed to effect.
From this it follows that the censorship may be useful for the preservation of morality,
but can never be so for its restoration. Set up censors while the laws are vigorous; as
soon as they have lost their vigour, all hope is gone; no legitimate power can retain
force when the laws have lost it.
The censorship upholds morality by preventing opinion from growing corrupt, by
preserving its rectitude by means of wise applications, and sometimes even by fixing
it when it is still uncertain. The employment of seconds in duels, which had been
carried to wild extremes in the kingdom of France, was done away with merely by
these words in a royal edict: “As for those who are cowards enough to call upon
seconds.” This judgment, in anticipating that of the public, suddenly decided it. But
when edicts from the same source tried to pronounce duelling itself an act of
cowardice, as indeed it is, then, since common opinion does not regard it as such, the
public took no notice of a decision on a point on which its mind was already made up.
I have stated elsewhere1 that as public opinion is not subject to any constraint, there
need be no trace of it in the tribunal set up to represent it. It is impossible to admire
too much the art with which this resource, which we moderns have wholly lost, was
employed by the Romans, and still more by the Lacedæmonians.
A man of bad morals having made a good proposal in the Spartan Council, the Ephors
neglected it, and caused the same proposal to be made by a virtuous citizen. What an
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
126
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
honour for the one, and what a disgrace for the other, without praise or blame of
either! Certain drunkards from Samos2 polluted the tribunal of the Ephors: the next
day, a public edict gave Samians permission to be filthy. An actual punishment would
not have been so severe as such an impunity. When Sparta has pronounced on what is
or is not right, Greece makes no appeal from her judgments.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
127
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER VIII
Civil Religion
At first men had no kings save the gods, and no government save theocracy. They
reasoned like Caligula, and, at that period, reasoned aright. It takes a long time for
feeling so to change that men can make up their minds to take their equals as masters,
in the hope that they will profit by doing so.
From the mere fact that God was set over every political society, it followed that there
were as many gods as peoples. Two peoples that were strangers the one to the other,
and almost always enemies, could not long recognise the same master: two armies
giving battle could not obey the same leader. National divisions thus led to
polytheism, and this in turn gave rise to theological and civil intolerance, which, as
we shall see hereafter, are by nature the same.
The fancy the Greeks had for rediscovering their gods among the barbarians arose
from the way they had of regarding themselves as the natural Sovereigns of such
peoples. But there is nothing so absurd as the erudition which in our days identifies
and confuses gods of different nations. As if Moloch, Saturn and Chronos could be
the same god! As if the Phœnician Baal, the Greek Zeus, and the Latin Jupiter could
be the same! As if there could still be anything common to imaginary beings with
different names!
If it is asked how in pagan times, where each State had its cult and its gods, there were
no wars of religion, I answer that it was precisely because each State, having its own
cult as well as its own government, made no distinction between its gods and its laws.
Political war was also theological; the provinces of the gods were, so to speak, fixed
by the boundaries of nations. The god of one people had no right over another. The
gods of the pagans were not jealous gods; they shared among themselves the empire
of the world: even Moses and the Hebrews sometimes lent themselves to this view by
speaking of the God of Israel. It is true, they regarded as powerless the gods of the
Canaanites, a proscribed people condemned to destruction, whose place they were to
take; but remember how they spoke of the divisions of the neighbouring peoples they
were forbidden to attack! “Is not the possession of what belongs to your god Chamos
lawfully your due?” said Jephthah to the Ammonites. “We have the same title to the
lands our conquering God has made his own.”1 Here, I think, there is a recognition
that the rights of Chamos and those of the God of Israel are of the same nature.
But when the Jews, being subject to the kings of Babylon, and, subsequently, to those
of Syria, still obstinately refused to recognise any god save their own, their refusal
was regarded as rebellion against their conqueror, and drew down on them the
persecutions we read of in their history, which are without parallel till the coming of
Christianity.2
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
128
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Every religion, therefore, being attached solely to the laws of the State which
prescribed it, there was no way of converting a people except by enslaving it, and
there could be no missionaries save conquerors. The obligation to change cults being
the law to which the vanquished yielded, it was necessary to be victorious before
suggesting such a change. So far from men fighting for the gods, the gods, as in
Homer, fought for men; each asked his god for victory, and repayed him with new
altars. The Romans, before taking a city, summoned its gods to quit it; and, in leaving
the Tarentines their outraged gods, they regarded them as subject to their own and
compelled to do them homage. They left the vanquished their gods as they left them
their laws. A wreath to the Jupiter of the Capitol was often the only tribute they
imposed.
Finally, when, along with their empire, the Romans had spread their cult and their
gods, and had themselves often adopted those of the vanquished, by granting to both
alike the rights of the city, the peoples of that vast empire insensibly found themselves
with multitudes of gods and cults, everywhere almost the same; and thus paganism
throughout the known world finally came to be one and the same religion.
It was in these circumstances that Jesus came to set up on earth a spiritual kingdom,
which, by separating the theological from the political system, made the State no
longer one, and brought about the internal divisions which have never ceased to
trouble Christian peoples. As the new idea of a kingdom of the other world could
never have occurred to pagans, they always looked on the Christians as really rebels,
who, while feigning to submit, were only waiting for the chance to make themselves
independent and their masters, and to usurp by guile the authority they pretended in
their weakness to respect. This was the cause of the persecutions.
What the pagans had feared took place. Then everything changed its aspect: the
humble Christians changed their language, and soon this so-called kingdom of the
other world turned, under a visible leader, into the most violent of earthly despotisms.
However, as there have always been a prince and civil laws, this double power and
conflict of jurisdiction have made all good polity impossible in Christian States; and
men have never succeeded in finding out whether they were bound to obey the master
or the priest.
Several peoples, however, even in Europe and its neighbourhood, have desired
without success to preserve or restore the old system: but the spirit of Christianity has
everywhere prevailed. The sacred cult has always remained or again become
independent of the Sovereign, and there has been no necessary link between it and the
body of the State. Mahomet held very sane views, and linked his political system well
together; and, as long as the form of his government continued under the caliphs who
succeeded him, that government was indeed one, and so far good. But the Arabs,
having grown prosperous, lettered, civilised, slack and cowardly, were conquered by
barbarians: the division between the two powers began again; and, although it is less
apparent among the Mahometans than among the Christians, it none the less exists,
especially in the sect of Ali, and there are States, such as Persia, where it is
continually making itself felt.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
129
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Among us, the Kings of England have made themselves heads of the Church, and the
Czars have done the same: but this title has made them less its masters than its
ministers; they have gained not so much the right to change it, as the power to
maintain it: they are not its legislators, but only its princes. Wherever the clergy is a
corporate body,1 it is master and legislator in its own country. There are thus two
powers, two Sovereigns, in England and in Russia, as well as elsewhere.
Of all Christian writers, the philosopher Hobbes alone has seen the evil and how to
remedy it, and has dared to propose the reunion of the two heads of the eagle, and the
restoration throughout of political unity, without which no State or government will
ever be rightly constituted. But he should have seen that the masterful spirit of
Christianity is incompatible with his system, and that the priestly interest would
always be stronger than that of the State. It is not so much what is false and terrible in
his political theory, as what is just and true, that has drawn down hatred on it.2
I believe that if the study of history were developed from this point of view, it would
be easy to refute the contrary opinions of Bayle and Warburton, one of whom holds
that religion can be of no use to the body politic, while the other, on the contrary,
maintains that Christianity is its strongest support. We should demonstrate to the
former that no State has ever been founded without a religious basis, and to the latter,
that the law of Christianity at bottom does more harm by weakening than good by
strengthening the constitution of the State. To make myself understood, I have only to
make a little more exact the too vague ideas of religion as relating to this subject.
Religion, considered in relation to society, which is either general or particular, may
also be divided into two kinds: the religion of man, and that of the citizen. The first,
which has neither temples, nor altars, nor rites, and is confined to the purely internal
cult of the supreme God and the eternal obligations of morality, is the religion of the
Gospel pure and simple, the true theism, what may be called natural divine right or
law. The other, which is codified in a single country, gives it its gods, its own tutelary
patrons; it has its dogmas, its rites, and its external cult prescribed by law; outside the
single nation that follows it, all the world is in its sight infidel, foreign and barbarous;
the duties and rights of man extend for it only as far as its own altars. Of this kind
were all the religions of early peoples, which we may define as civil or positive divine
right or law.
There is a third sort of religion of a more singular kind, which gives men two codes of
legislation, two rulers, and two countries, renders them subject to contradictory duties,
and makes it impossible for them to be faithful both to religion and to citizenship.
Such are the religions of the Lamas and of the Japanese, and such is Roman
Christianity, which may be called the religion of the priest. It leads to a sort of mixed
and anti-social code which has no name.
In their political aspect, all these three kinds of religion have their defects. The third is
so clearly bad, that it is waste of time to stop to prove it such. All that destroys social
unity is worthless; all institutions that set man in contradiction to himself are
worthless.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
130
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
The second is good in that it unites the divine cult with love of the laws, and, making
country the object of the citizens’ adoration, teaches them that service done to the
State is service done to its tutelary god. It is a form of theocracy, in which there can
be no pontiff save the prince, and no priests save the magistrates. To die for one’s
country then becomes martyrdom; violation of its laws, impiety; and to subject one
who is guilty to public execration is to condemn him to the anger of the gods: Sacer
estod.
On the other hand, it is bad in that, being founded on lies and error, it deceives men,
makes them credulous and superstitious, and drowns the true cult of the Divinity in
empty ceremonial. It is bad, again, when it becomes tyrannous and exclusive, and
makes a people bloodthirsty and intolerant, so that it breathes fire and slaughter, and
regards as a sacred act the killing of every one who does not believe in its gods. The
result is to place such a people in a natural state of war with all others, so that its
security is deeply endangered.
There remains therefore the religion of man or Christianity—not the Christianity of
to-day, but that of the Gospel, which is entirely different. By means of this holy,
sublime, and real religion all men, being children of one God, recognise one another
as brothers, and the society that unites them is not dissolved even at death.
But this religion, having no particular relation to the body politic, leaves the laws in
possession of the force they have in themselves without making any addition to it; and
thus one of the great bonds that unite society considered in severalty fails to operate.
Nay, more, so far from binding the hearts of the citizens to the State, it has the effect
of taking them away from all earthly things. I know of nothing more contrary to the
social spirit.
We are told that a people of true Christians would form the most perfect society
imaginable. I see in this supposition only one great difficulty: that a society of true
Christians would not be a society of men.
I say further that such a society, with all its perfection, would be neither the strongest
nor the most lasting: the very fact that it was perfect would rob it of its bond of union;
the flaw that would destroy it would lie in its very perfection.
Every one would do his duty; the people would be lawabiding, the rulers just and
temperate; the magistrates upright and incorruptible; the soldiers would scorn death;
there would be neither vanity nor luxury. So far, so good; but let us hear more.
Christianity as a religion is entirely spiritual, occupied solely with heavenly things;
the country of the Christian is not of this world. He does his duty, indeed, but does it
with profound indifference to the good or ill success of his cares. Provided he has
nothing to reproach himself with, it matters little to him whether things go well or ill
here on earth. If the State is prosperous, he hardly dares to share in the public
happiness, for fear he may grow proud of his country’s glory; if the State is
languishing, he blesses the hand of God that is hard upon His people.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
131
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
For the State to be peaceable and for harmony to be maintained, all the citizens
without exception would have to be good Christians; if by ill hap there should be a
single self-seeker or hypocrite, a Catiline or a Cromwell, for instance, he would
certainly get the better of his pious compatriots. Christian charity does not readily
allow a man to think hardly of his neighbours. As soon as, by some trick, he has
discovered the art of imposing on them and getting hold of a share in the public
authority, you have a man established in dignity; it is the will of God that he be
respected: very soon you have a power; it is God’s will that it be obeyed: and if the
power is abused by him who wields it, it is the scourge wherewith God punishes His
children. There would be scruples about driving out the usurper: public tranquillity
would have to be disturbed, violence would have to be employed, and blood spilt; all
this accords ill with Christian meekness; and after all, in this vale of sorrows, what
does it matter whether we are free men or serfs? The essential thing is to get to
heaven, and resignation is only an additional means of doing so.
If war breaks out with another State, the citizens march readily out to battle; not one
of them thinks of flight; they do their duty, but they have no passion for victory; they
know better how to die than how to conquer. What does it matter whether they win or
lose? Does not Providence know better than they what is meet for them? Only think to
what account a proud, impetuous and passionate enemy could turn their stoicism! Set
over against them those generous peoples who were devoured by ardent love of glory
and of their country, imagine your Christian republic face to face with Sparta or
Rome: the pious Christians will be beaten, crushed and destroyed, before they know
where they are, or will owe their safety only to the contempt their enemy will
conceive for them. It was to my mind a fine oath that was taken by the soldiers of
Fabius, who swore, not to conquer or die, but to come back victorious—and kept their
oath. Christians would never have taken such an oath; they would have looked on it as
tempting God.
But I am mistaken in speaking of a Christian republic; the terms are mutually
exclusive. Christianity preaches only servitude and dependence. Its spirit is so
favourable to tyranny that it always profits by such a régime. True Christians are
made to be slaves, and they know it and do not much mind: this short life counts for
too little in their eyes.
I shall be told that Christian troops are excellent. I deny it. Show me an instance. For
my part, I know of no Christian troops. I shall be told of the Crusades. Without
disputing the valour of the Crusaders, I answer that, so far from being Christians, they
were the priests’ soldiery, citizens of the Church. They fought for their spiritual
country, which the Church had, somehow or other, made temporal. Well understood,
this goes back to paganism: as the Gospel sets up no national religion, a holy war is
impossible among Christians.
Under the pagan emperors, the Christian soldiers were brave; every Christian writer
affirms it, and I believe it: it was a case of honourable emulation of the pagan troops.
As soon as the emperors were Christian, this emulation no longer existed, and, when
the Cross had driven out the eagle, Roman valour wholly disappeared.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
132
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
But, setting aside political considerations, let us come back to what is right, and settle
our principles on this important point. The right which the social compact gives the
Sovereign over the subjects does not, we have seen, exceed the limits of public
expediency.1 The subjects then owe the Sovereign an account of their opinions only
to such an extent as they matter to the community. Now, it matters very much to the
community that each citizen should have a religion. That will make him love his duty;
but the dogmas of that religion concern the State and its members only so far as they
have reference to morality and to the duties which he who professes them is bound to
do to others. Each man may have, over and above, what opinions he pleases, without
it being the Sovereign’s business to take cognisance of them; for, as the Sovereign has
no authority in the other world, whatever the lot of its subjects may be in the life to
come, that is not its business, provided they are good citizens in this life.
There is therefore a purely civil profession of faith of which the Sovereign should fix
the articles, not exactly as religious dogmas, but as social sentiments without which a
man cannot be a good citizen or a faithful subject.1 While it can compel no one to
believe them, it can banish from the State whoever does not believe them—it can
banish him, not for impiety, but as an anti-social being, incapable of truly loving the
laws and justice, and of sacrificing, at need, his life to his duty. If any one, after
publicly recognising these dogmas, behaves as if he does not believe them, let him be
punished by death: he has committed the worst of all crimes, that of lying before the
law.
The dogmas of civil religion ought to be few, simple, and exactly worded, without
explanation or commentary. The existence of a mighty, intelligent and beneficent
Divinity, possessed of foresight and providence, the life to come, the happiness of the
just, the punishment of the wicked, the sanctity of the social contract and the laws:
these are its positive dogmas. Its negative dogmas I confine to one, intolerance, which
is a part of the cults we have rejected.
Those who distinguish civil from theological intolerance are, to my mind, mistaken.
The two forms are inseparable. It is impossible to live at peace with those we regard
as damned; to love them would be to hate God who punishes them: we positively
must either reclaim or torment them. Wherever theological intolerance is admitted, it
must inevitably have some civil effect;1 and as soon as it has such an effect, the
Sovereign is no longer Sovereign even in the temporal sphere: thenceforth priests are
the real masters, and kings only their ministers.
Now that there is and can be no longer an exclusive national religion, tolerance should
be given to all religions that tolerate others, so long as their dogmas contain nothing
contrary to the duties of citizenship. But whoever dares to say: Outside the Church is
no salvation, ought to be driven from the State, unless the State is the Church, and the
prince the pontiff. Such a dogma is good only in a theocratic government; in any
other, it is fatal. The reason for which Henry IV is said to have embraced the Roman
religion ought to make every honest man leave it, and still more any prince who
knows how to reason.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
133
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
CHAPTER IX
Conclusion
Now that I have laid down the true principles of political right, and tried to give the
State a basis of its own to rest on, I ought next to strengthen it by its external relations,
which would include the law of nations, commerce, the right of war and conquest,
public right, leagues, negotiations, treaties, etc. But all this forms a new subject that is
far too vast for my narrow scope. I ought throughout to have kept to a more limited
sphere.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
134
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
A DISCOURSE Which Won The Prize At The Academy Of
Dijon In 1750, On This Question Proposed By The Academy:
Has The Restoration Of The Arts And Sciences Had A Purifying
Effect Upon Morals?
Barbarus hic ego sum, qui non intelligor illis.—Ovid.1
PREFACE
The following pages contain a discussion of one of the most sublime and interesting
of all moral questions. It is not concerned, however, with those metaphysical
subtleties, which of late have found their way into every department of literature, and
from which even our academic curricula are not always free. We have now to do with
one of those truths on which the happiness of mankind depends.
I foresee that I shall not readily be forgiven for having taken up the position I have
adopted. Setting myself up against all that is nowadays most admired, I can expect no
less than a universal outcry against me: nor is the approbation of a few sensible men
enough to make me count on that of the public. But I have taken my stand, and I shall
be at no pains to please either intellectuals or men of the world. There are in all ages
men born to be in bondage to the opinions of the society in which they live. There are
not a few, who to-day play the free-thinker and the philosopher, who would, if they
had lived in the time of the League, have been no more than fanatics. No author, who
has a mind to outlive his own age, should write for such readers.
A word more and I have done. As I did not expect the honour conferred on me, I had,
since sending in my Discourse, so altered and enlarged it as almost to make it a new
work; but in the circumstances I have felt bound to publish it just as it was when it
received the prize. I have only added a few notes, and left two alterations which are
easily recognisable, of which the Academy possibly might not have approved. The
respect, gratitude and even justice I owe to that body seemed to me to demand this
acknowledgment.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
135
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
A DISCOURSE ON THE MORAL EFFECTS OF THE ARTS
AND SCIENCES
Decipimur Specie Recti.—Horace.
The question before me is, “Whether the Restoration of the arts and sciences has had
the effect of purifying or corrupting morals.” Which side am I to take? That,
gentlemen, which becomes an honest man, who is sensible of his own ignorance, and
thinks himself none the worse for it.
I feel the difficulty of treating this subject fittingly, before the tribunal which is to
judge of what I advance. How can I presume to belittle the sciences before one of the
most learned assemblies in Europe, to commend ignorance in a famous Academy, and
reconcile my contempt for study with the respect due to the truly learned?
I was aware of these inconsistencies, but not discouraged by them. It is not science, I
said to myself, that I am attacking; it is virtue that I am defending, and that before
virtuous men—and goodness is even dearer to the good than learning to the learned.
What then have I to fear? The sagacity of the assembly before which I am pleading?
That, I acknowledge, is to be feared; but rather on account of faults of construction
than of the views I hold. Just sovereigns have never hesitated to decide against
themselves in doubtful cases; and indeed the most advantageous situation in which a
just claim can be, is that of being laid before a just and enlightened arbitrator, who is
judge in his own case.
To this motive, which encouraged me, I may add another which finally decided me.
And this is, that as I have upheld the cause of truth to the best of my natural abilities,
whatever my apparent success, there is one reward which cannot fail me. That reward
I shall find in the bottom of my heart.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
136
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
THE FIRST PART
It is a noble and beautiful spectacle to see man raising himself, so to speak, from
nothing by his own exertions; dissipating, by the light of reason, all the thick clouds in
which he was by nature enveloped; mounting above himself; soaring in thought even
to the celestial regions; like the sun, encompassing with giant strides the vast extent of
the universe; and, what is still grander and more wonderful, going back into himself,
there to study man and get to know his own nature, his duties and his end. All these
miracles we have seen renewed within the last few generations.
Europe had relapsed into the barbarism of the earliest ages; the inhabitants of this part
of the world, which is at present so highly enlightened, were plunged, some centuries
ago, in a state still worse than ignorance. A scientific jargon, more despicable than
mere ignorance, had usurped the name of knowledge, and opposed an almost
invincible obstacle to its restoration.
Things had come to such a pass, that it required a complete revolution to bring men
back to common sense. This came at last from the quarter from which it was least to
be expected. It was the stupid Mussulman, the eternal scourge of letters, who was the
immediate cause of their revival among us. The fall of the throne of Constantine
brought to Italy the relics of ancient Greece; and with these precious spoils France in
turn was enriched. The sciences soon followed literature, and the art of thinking
joined that of writing: an order which may seem strange, but is perhaps only too
natural. The world now began to perceive the principal advantage of an intercourse
with the Muses, that of rendering mankind more sociable by inspiring them with the
desire to please one another with performances worthy of their mutual approbation.
The mind, as well as the body, has its needs: those of the body are the basis of society,
those of the mind its ornaments.
So long as government and law provide for the security and well-being of men in their
common life, the arts, literature and the sciences, less despotic though perhaps more
powerful, fling garlands of flowers over the chains which weigh them down. They
stifle in men’s breasts that sense of original liberty, for which they seem to have been
born; cause them to love their own slavery, and so make of them what is called a
civilised people.
Necessity raised up thrones; the arts and sciences have made them strong. Powers of
the earth, cherish all talents and protect those who cultivate them.1 Civilised peoples,
cultivate such pursuits: to them, happy slaves, you owe that delicacy and
exquisiteness of taste, which is so much your boast, that sweetness of disposition and
urbanity of manners which make intercourse so easy and agreeable among you—in a
word, the appearance of all the virtues, without being in possession of one of them.
It was for this sort of accomplishment, which is by so much the more captivating as it
seems less affected, that Athens and Rome were so much distinguished in the boasted
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
137
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
times of their splendour and magnificence: and it is doubtless in the same respect that
our own age and nation will excel all periods and peoples. An air of philosophy
without pedantry; an address at once natural and engaging, distant equally from
Teutonic clumsiness and Italian pantomime; these are the effects of a taste acquired
by liberal studies and improved by conversation with the world. What happiness
would it be for those who live among us, if our external appearance were always a
true mirror of our hearts; if decorum were but virtue; if the maxims we professed were
the rules of our conduct; and if real philosophy were inseparable from the title of a
philosopher! But so many good qualities too seldom go together; virtue rarely appears
in so much pomp and state.
Richness of apparel may proclaim the man of fortune, and elegance the man of taste;
but true health and manliness are known by different signs. It is under the homespun
of the labourer, and not beneath the gilt and tinsel of the courtier, that we should look
for strength and vigour of body.
External ornaments are no less foreign to virtue, which is the strength and activity of
the mind. The honest man is an athlete, who loves to wrestle stark naked; he scorns all
those vile trappings, which prevent the exertion of his strength, and were, for the most
part, invented only to conceal some deformity.
Before art had moulded our behaviour, and taught our passions to speak an artificial
language, our morals were rude but natural; and the different ways in which we
behaved proclaimed at the first glance the difference of our dispositions. Human
nature was not at bottom better then than now; but men found their security in the
ease with which they could see through one another, and this advantage, of which we
no longer feel the value, prevented their having many vices.
In our day, now that more subtle study and a more refined taste have reduced the art
of pleasing to a system, there prevails in modern manners a servile and deceptive
conformity; so that one would think every mind had been cast in the same mould.
Politeness requires this thing; decorum that; ceremony has its forms, and fashion its
laws, and these we must always follow, never the promptings of our own nature.
We no longer dare seem what we really are, but lie under a perpetual restraint; in the
meantime the herd of men, which we call society, all act under the same
circumstances exactly alike, unless very particular and powerful motives prevent
them. Thus we never know with whom we have to deal; and even to know our friends
we must wait for some critical and pressing occasion; that is, till it is too late; for it is
on those very occasions that such knowledge is of use to us.
What a train of vices must attend this uncertainty! Sincere friendship, real esteem, and
perfect confidence are banished from among men. Jealousy, suspicion, fear, coldness,
reserve, hate and fraud lie constantly concealed under that uniform and deceitful veil
of politeness; that boasted candour and urbanity, for which we are indebted to the
light and leading of this age. We shall no longer take in vain by our oaths the name of
our Creator; but we shall insult Him with our blasphemies, and our scrupulous ears
will take no offence. We have grown too modest to brag of our own deserts; but we
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
138
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
do not scruple to decry those of others. We do not grossly outrage even our enemies,
but artfully calumniate them. Our hatred of other nations diminishes, but patriotism
dies with it. Ignorance is held in contempt; but a dangerous scepticism has succeeded
it. Some vices indeed are condemned and others grown dishonourable; but we have
still many that are honoured with the names of virtues, and it is become necessary that
we should either have, or at least pretend to have them. Let who will extol the
moderation of our modern sages, I see nothing in it but a refinement of intemperance
as unworthy of my commendation as their artificial simplicity.1
Such is the purity to which our morals have attained; this is the virtue we have made
our own. Let the arts and sciences claim the share they have had in this salutary work.
I shall add but one reflection more; suppose an inhabitant of some distant country
should endeavour to form an idea of European morals from the state of the sciences,
the perfection of the arts, the propriety of our public entertainments, the politeness of
our behaviour, the affability of our conversation, our constant professions of
benevolence, and from those tumultuous assemblies of people of all ranks, who seem,
from morning till night, to have no other care than to oblige one another. Such a
stranger, I maintain, would arrive at a totally false view of our morality.
Where there is no effect, it is idle to look for a cause: but here the effect is certain and
the depravity actual; our minds have been corrupted in proportion as the arts and
sciences have improved. Will it be said, that this is a misfortune peculiar to the
present age? No, gentlemen, the evils resulting from our vain curiosity are as old as
the world. The daily ebb and flow of the tides are not more regularly influenced by
the moon, than the morals of a people by the progress of the arts and sciences. As
their light has risen above our horizon, virtue has taken flight, and the same
phenomenon has been constantly observed in all times and places.
Take Egypt, the first school of mankind, that ancient country, famous for its fertility
under a brazen sky; the spot from which Sesostris once set out to conquer the world.
Egypt became the mother of philosophy and the fine arts; soon she was conquered by
Cambyses, and then successively by the Greeks, the Romans, the Arabs, and finally
the Turks.
Take Greece, once peopled by heroes, who twice vanquished Asia. Letters, as yet in
their infancy, had not corrupted the disposition of its inhabitants; but the progress of
the sciences soon produced a dissoluteness of manners, and the imposition of the
Macedonian yoke: from which time Greece, always learned, always voluptuous and
always a slave, has experienced amid all its revolutions no more than a change of
masters. Not all the eloquence of Demosthenes could breathe life into a body which
luxury and the arts had once enervated.
It was not till the days of Ennius and Terence that Rome, founded by a shepherd, and
made illustrious by peasants, began to degenerate. But after the appearance of an
Ovid, a Catullus, a Martial, and the rest of those numerous obscene authors, whose
very names are enough to put modesty to the blush, Rome, once the shrine of virtue,
became the theatre of vice, a scorn among the nations, and an object of derision even
to barbarians. Thus the capital of the world at length submitted to the yoke of slavery
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
139
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
it had imposed on others, and the very day of its fall was the eve of that on which it
conferred on one of its citizens the title of Arbiter of Good Taste.
What shall I say of that metropolis of the Eastern Empire, which, by its situation,
seemed destined to be the capital of the world; that refuge of the arts and sciences,
when they were banished from the rest of Europe, more perhaps by wisdom than
barbarism? The most profligate debaucheries, the most abandoned villainies, the most
atrocious crimes, plots, murders and assassinations form the warp and woof of the
history of Constantinople. Such is the pure source from which have flowed to us the
floods of knowledge on which the present age so prides itself.
But wherefore should we seek, in past ages, for proofs of a truth, of which the present
affords us ample evidence? There is in Asia a vast empire, where learning is held in
honour, and leads to the highest dignities in the state. If the sciences improved our
morals, if they inspired us with courage and taught us to lay down our lives for the
good of our country, the Chinese should be wise, free and invincible. But, if there be
no vice they do not practise, no crime with which they are not familiar; if the sagacity
of their ministers, the supposed wisdom of their laws, and the multitude of inhabitants
who people that vast empire, have alike failed to preserve them from the yoke of the
rude and ignorant Tartars, of what use were their men of science and literature? What
advantage has that country reaped from the honours bestowed on its learned men?
Can it be that of being peopled by a race of scoundrels and slaves?
Contrast with these instances the morals of those few nations which, being preserved
from the contagion of useless knowledge, have by their virtues become happy in
themselves and afforded an example to the rest of the world. Such were the first
inhabitants of Persia, a nation so singular that virtue was taught among them in the
same manner as the sciences are with us. They very easily subdued Asia, and possess
the exclusive glory of having had the history of their political institutions regarded as
a philosophical romance. Such were the Scythians, of whom such wonderful eulogies
have come down to us. Such were the Germans, whose simplicity, innocence and
virtue, afforded a most delightful contrast to the pen of an historian, weary of
describing the baseness and villainies of an enlightened, opulent and voluptuous
nation. Such had been even Rome in the days of its poverty and ignorance. And such
has shown itself to be, even in our own times, that rustic nation, whose justly
renowned courage not even adversity could conquer, and whose fidelity no example
could corrupt.1
It is not through stupidity that the people have preferred other activities to those of the
mind. They were not ignorant that in other countries there were men who spent their
time in disputing idly about the sovereign good, and about vice and virtue. They knew
that these useless thinkers were lavish in their own praises, and stigmatised other
nations contemptuously as barbarians. But they noted the morals of these people, and
so learnt what to think of their learning.1
Can it be forgotten that, in the very heart of Greece, there arose a city as famous for
the happy ignorance of its inhabitants, as for the wisdom of its laws; a republic of
demi-gods rather than of men, so greatly superior their virtues seemed to those of
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
140
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
mere humanity? Sparta, eternal proof of the vanity of science, while the vices, under
the conduct of the fine arts, were being introduced into Athens, even while its tyrant
was carefully collecting together the works of the prince of poets, was driving from
her walls artists and the arts, the learned and their learning!
The difference was seen in the outcome. Athens became the seat of politeness and
taste, the country of orators and philosophers. The elegance of its buildings equalled
that of its language; on every side might be seen marble and canvas, animated by the
hands of the most skilful artists. From Athens we derive those astonishing
performances, which will serve as models to every corrupt age. The picture of
Lacedæmon is not so highly coloured. There, the neighbouring nations used to say,
“men were born virtuous, their native air seeming to inspire them with virtue.” But its
inhabitants have left us nothing but the memory of their heroic actions: monuments
that should not count for less in our eyes than the most curious relics of Athenian
marble.
It is true that, among the Athenians, there were some few wise men who withstood the
general torrent, and preserved their integrity even in the company of the muses. But
hear the judgment which the principal, and most unhappy of them, passed on the
artists and learned men of his day.
“I have considered the poets,” says he, “and I look upon them as people whose talents
impose both on themselves and on others; they give themselves out for wise men, and
are taken for such; but in reality they are anything sooner than that.”
“From the poets,” continues Socrates, “I turned to the artists. Nobody was more
ignorant of the arts than myself; nobody was more fully persuaded that the artists
were possessed of amazing knowledge. I soon discovered, however, that they were in
as bad a way as the poets, and that both had fallen into the same misconception.
Because the most skilful of them excel others in their particular jobs, they think
themselves wiser than all the rest of mankind. This arrogance spoilt all their skill in
my eyes, so that, putting myself in the place of the oracle, and asking myself whether
I would rather be what I am or what they are, know what they know, or know that I
know nothing, I very readily answered, for myself and the god, that I had rather
remain as I am.
“None of us, neither the sophists, nor the poets, nor the orators, nor the artists, nor I,
know what is the nature of the true, the good, or the beautiful. But there is this
difference between us; that, though none of these people know anything, they all think
they know something; whereas for my part, if I know nothing, I am at least in no
doubt of my ignorance. So the superiority of wisdom, imputed to me by the oracle, is
reduced merely to my being fully convinced that I am ignorant of what I do not
know.”
Thus we find Socrates, the wisest of men in the judgment of the god, and the most
learned of all the Athenians in the opinion of all Greece, speaking in praise of
ignorance. Were he alive now, there is little reason to think that our modern scholars
and artists would induce him to change his mind. No, gentlemen, that honest man
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
141
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
would still persist in despising our vain sciences. He would lend no aid to swell the
flood of books that flows from every quarter: he would leave to us, as he did to his
disciples, only the example and memory of his virtues; that is the noblest method of
instructing mankind.
Socrates had begun at Athens, and the elder Cato proceeded at Rome, to inveigh
against those seductive and subtle Greeks, who corrupted the virtue and destroyed the
courage of their fellow-citizens: culture, however, prevailed. Rome was filled with
philosophers and orators, military discipline was neglected, agriculture was held in
contempt, men formed sects, and forgot their country. To the sacred names of liberty,
disinterestedness and obedience to law, succeeded those of Epicurus, Zeno and
Arcesilaus. It was even a saying among their own philosophers that since learned men
appeared among them, honest men had been in eclipse. Before that time the Romans
were satisfied with the practice of virtue; they were undone when they began to study
it.
What would the great soul of Fabricius have felt, if it had been his misfortune to be
called back to life, when he saw the pomp and magnificence of that Rome, which his
arm had saved from ruin, and his honourable name made more illustrious than all its
conquests. “Ye gods!” he would have said, “what has become of those thatched roofs
and rustic hearths, which were formerly the habitations of temperance and virtue?
What fatal splendour has succeeded the ancient Roman simplicity? What is this
foreign language, this effeminacy of manners? What is the meaning of these statues,
paintings and buildings? Fools, what have you done? You, the lords of the earth, have
made yourselves the slaves of the frivolous nations you have subdued. You are
governed by rhetoricians, and it has been only to enrich architects, painters, sculptors
and stage-players that you have watered Greece and Asia with your blood. Even the
spoils of Carthage are the prize of a flute-player. Romans! Romans! make haste to
demolish those amphitheatres, break to pieces those statues, burn those paintings;
drive from among you those slaves who keep you in subjection, and whose fatal arts
are corrupting your morals. Let other hands make themselves illustrious by such vain
talents; the only talent worthy of Rome is that of conquering the world and making
virtue its ruler. When Cyneas took the Roman senate for an assembly of kings, he was
not struck by either useless pomp or studied elegance. He heard there none of that
futile eloquence, which is now the study and the charm of frivolous orators. What
then was the majesty that Cyneas beheld? Fellow citizens, he saw the noblest sight
that ever existed under heaven, a sight which not all your riches or your arts can
show; an assembly of two hundred virtuous men, worthy to command in Rome, and to
govern the world.”
But let pass the distance of time and place, and let us see what has happened in our
own time and country; or rather let us banish odious descriptions that might offend
our delicacy, and spare ourselves the pains of repeating the same things under
different names. It was not for nothing that I invoked the Manes of Fabricius; for what
have I put into his mouth, that might not have come with as much propriety from
Louis the Twelfth or Henry the Fourth? It is true that in France Socrates would not
have drunk the hemlock, but he would have drunk of a potion infinitely more bitter, of
insult, mockery and contempt a hundred times worse than death.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
142
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Thus it is that luxury, profligacy and slavery, have been, in all ages, the scourge of the
efforts of our pride to emerge from that happy state of ignorance, in which the
wisdom of providence had placed us. That thick veil with which it has covered all its
operations seems to be a sufficient proof that it never designed us for such fruitless
researches. But is there, indeed, one lesson it has taught us, by which we have rightly
profited, or which we have neglected with impunity? Let men learn for once that
nature would have preserved them from science, as a mother snatches a dangerous
weapon from the hands of her child. Let them know that all the secrets she hides are
so many evils from which she protects them, and that the very difficulty they find in
acquiring knowledge is not the least of her bounty towards them. Men are perverse;
but they would have been far worse, if they had had the misfortune to be born learned.
How humiliating are these reflections to humanity, and how mortified by them our
pride should be! What! it will be asked, is uprightness the child of ignorance? Is virtue
inconsistent with learning? What consequences might not be drawn from such
suppositions? But to reconcile these apparent contradictions, we need only examine
closely the emptiness and vanity of those pompous titles, which are so liberally
bestowed on human knowledge, and which so blind our judgment. Let us consider,
therefore, the arts and sciences in themselves. Let us see what must result from their
advancement, and let us not hesitate to admit the truth of all those points on which our
arguments coincide with the inductions we can make from history.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
143
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
THE SECOND PART
An ancient tradition passed out of Egypt into Greece, that some god, who was an
enemy to the repose of mankind, was the inventor of the sciences.1 What must the
Egyptians, among whom the sciences first arose, have thought of them? And they
beheld, near at hand, the sources from which they sprang. In fact, whether we turn to
the annals of the world, or eke out with philosophical investigations the uncertain
chronicles of history, we shall not find for human knowledge an origin answering to
the idea we are pleased to entertain of it at present. Astronomy was born of
superstition, eloquence of ambition, hatred, falsehood and flattery; geometry of
avarice; physics of an idle curiosity; and even moral philosophy of human pride. Thus
the arts and sciences owe their birth to our vices; we should be less doubtful of their
advantages, if they had sprung from our virtues.
Their evil origin is, indeed, but too plainly reproduced in their objects. What would
become of the arts, were they not cherished by luxury? If men were not unjust, of
what use were jurisprudence? What would become of history, if there were no tyrants,
wars, or conspiracies? In a word, who would pass his life in barren speculations, if
everybody, attentive only to the obligations of humanity and the necessities of nature,
spent his whole life in serving his country, obliging his friends, and relieving the
unhappy? Are we then made to live and die on the brink of that well at the bottom of
which Truth lies hid? This reflection alone is, in my opinion, enough to discourage at
first setting out every man who seriously endeavours to instruct himself by the study
of philosophy.
What a variety of dangers surrounds us! What a number of wrong paths present
themselves in the investigation of the sciences! Through how many errors, more
perilous than truth itself is useful, must we not pass to arrive at it? The disadvantages
we lie under are evident; for falsehood is capable of an infinite variety of
combinations; but the truth has only one manner of being. Besides, where is the man
who sincerely desires to find it? Or even admitting his good will, by what
characteristic marks is he sure of knowing it? Amid the infinite diversity of opinions
where is the criterion1 by which we may certainly judge of it? Again, what is still
more difficult, should we even be fortunate enough to discover it, who among us will
know how to make right use of it?
If our sciences are futile in the objects they propose, they are no less dangerous in the
effects they produce. Being the effect of idleness, they generate idleness in their turn;
and an irreparable loss of time is the first prejudice which they must necessarily cause
to society. To live without doing some good is a great evil as well in the political as in
the moral world; and hence every useless citizen should be regarded as a pernicious
person. Tell me then, illustrious philosophers, of whom we learn the ratios in which
attraction acts in vacuo; and in the revolution of the planets, the relations of spaces
traversed in equal times; by whom we are taught what curves have conjugate points,
points of inflexion, and cusps; how the soul and body correspond, like two clocks,
without actual communication; what planets may be inhabited; and what insects
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
144
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
reproduce in an extraordinary manner. Answer me, I say, you from whom we receive
all this sublime information, whether we should have been less numerous, worse
governed, less formidable, less flourishing, or more perverse, supposing you had
taught us none of all these fine things.
Reconsider therefore the importance of your productions; and, since the labours of the
most enlightened of our learned men and the best of our citizens are of so little utility,
tell us what we ought to think of that numerous herd of obscure writers and useless
littérateurs, who devour without any return the substance of the State.
Useless, do I say? Would God they were! Society would be more peaceful, and
morals less corrupt. But these vain and futile declaimers go forth on all sides, armed
with their fatal paradoxes, to sap the foundations of our faith, and nullify virtue. They
smile contemptuously at such old names as patriotism and religion, and consecrate
their talents and philosophy to the destruction and defamation of all that men hold
sacred. Not that they bear any real hatred to virtue or dogma; they are the enemies of
public opinion alone; to bring them to the foot of the altar, it would be enough to
banish them to a land of atheists. What extravagancies will not the rage of singularity
induce men to commit!
The waste of time is certainly a great evil; but still greater evils attend upon literature
and the arts. One is luxury, produced like them by indolence and vanity. Luxury is
seldom unattended by the arts and sciences; and they are always attended by luxury. I
know that our philosophy, fertile in paradoxes, pretends, in contradiction to the
experience of all ages, that luxury contributes to the splendour of States. But, without
insisting on the necessity of sumptuary laws, can it be denied that rectitude of morals
is essential to the duration of empires, and that luxury is diametrically opposed to
such rectitude? Let it be admitted that luxury is a certain indication of wealth; that it
even serves, if you will, to increase such wealth: what conclusion is to be drawn from
this paradox, so worthy of the times? And what will become of virtue if riches are to
be acquired at any cost? The politicians of the ancient world were always talking of
morals and virtue; ours speak of nothing but commerce and money. One of them will
tell you that in such a country a man is worth just as much as he will sell for at
Algiers: another, pursuing the same mode of calculation, finds that in some countries
a man is worth nothing, and in others still less than nothing; they value men as they do
droves of oxen. According to them, a man is worth no more to the State, than the
amount he consumes; and thus a Sybarite would be worth at least thirty
Lacedæmonians. Let these writers tell me, however, which of the two republics,
Sybaris or Sparta, was subdued by a handful of peasants, and which became the terror
of Asia.
The monarchy of Cyrus was conquered by thirty thousand men, led by a prince poorer
than the meanest of Persian Satraps: in like manner the Scythians, the poorest of all
nations, were able to resist the most powerful monarchs of the universe. When two
famous republics contended for the empire of the world, the one rich and the other
poor, the former was subdued by the latter. The Roman empire in its turn, after having
engulfed all the riches of the universe, fell a prey to peoples who knew not even what
riches were. The Franks conquered the Gauls, and the Saxons England, without any
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
145
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
other treasures than their bravery and their poverty. A band of poor mountaineers,
whose whole cupidity was confined to the possession of a few sheep-skins, having
first given a check to the arrogance of Austria, went on to crush the opulent and
formidable house of Burgundy, which at that time made the potentates of Europe
tremble. In short, all the power and wisdom of the heir of Charles the Fifth, backed by
all the treasures of the Indies, broke before a few herring-fishers. Let our politicians
condescend to lay aside their calculations for a moment, to reflect on these examples;
let them learn for once that money, though it buys everything else, cannot buy morals
and citizens. What then is the precise point in dispute about luxury? It is to know
which is most advantageous to empires, that their existence should be brilliant and
momentary, or virtuous and lasting? I say brilliant, but with what lustre! A taste for
ostentation never prevails in the same minds as a taste for honesty. No, it is
impossible that understandings, degraded by a multitude of futile cares, should ever
rise to what is truly great and noble; even if they had the strength, they would want
the courage.
Every artist loves applause. The praise of his contemporaries is the most valuable part
of his recompense. What then will he do to obtain it, if he have the misfortune to be
born among a people, and at a time, when learning is in vogue, and the superficiality
of youth is in a position to lead the fashion; when men have sacrificed their taste to
those who tyrannise over their liberty, and one sex dare not approve anything but
what is proportionate to the pusillanimity of the other;1 when the greatest
masterpieces of dramatic poetry are condemned, and the noblest of musical
productions neglected? This is what he will do. He will lower his genius to the level
of the age, and will rather submit to compose mediocre works, that will be admired
during his life-time, than labour at sublime achievements which will not be admired
till long after he is dead. Let the famous Voltaire tell us how many nervous and
masculine beauties he has sacrificed to our false delicacy, and how much that is great
and noble, that spirit of gallantry, which delights in what is frivolous and petty, has
cost him.
It is thus that the dissolution of morals, the necessary consequence of luxury, brings
with it in its turn the corruption of taste. Further, if by chance there be found among
men of average ability, an individual with enough strength of mind to refuse to
comply with the spirit of the age, and to debase himself by puerile productions, his lot
will be hard. He will die in indigence and oblivion. This is not so much a prediction,
as a fact already confirmed by experience! Yes, Carle and Pierre Vanloo, the time is
already come when your pencils, destined to increase the majesty of our temples by
sublime and holy images, must fall from your hands, or else be prostituted to adorn
the panels of a coach with lascivious paintings. And you, inimitable Pigal, rival of
Phidias and Praxiteles, whose chisel the ancients would have employed to carve them
gods, whose images almost excuse their idolatry in our eyes; even your hand must
condescend to fashion the belly of an ape, or else remain idle.
We cannot reflect on the morality of mankind without contemplating with pleasure
the picture of the simplicity which prevailed in the earliest times. This image may be
justly compared to a beautiful coast, adorned only by the hands of nature; towards
which our eyes are constantly turned, and which we see receding with regret. While
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
146
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
men were innocent and virtuous and loved to have the gods for witnesses of their
actions, they dwelt together in the same huts; but when they became vicious, they
grew tired of such inconvenient onlookers, and banished them to magnificent temples.
Finally, they expelled their deities even from these, in order to dwell there
themselves; or at least the temples of the gods were no longer more magnificent than
the palaces of the citizens. This was the height of degeneracy; nor could vice ever be
carried to greater lengths than when it was seen, supported, as it were, at the doors of
the great, on columns of marble, and graven on Corinthian capitals.
As the conveniences of life increase, as the arts are brought to perfection, and luxury
spreads, true courage flags, the virtues disappear; and all this is the effect of the
sciences and of those arts which are exercised in the privacy of men’s dwellings.
When the Goths ravaged Greece, the libraries only escaped the flames owing to an
opinion that was set on foot among them, that it was best to leave the enemy with a
possession so calculated to divert their attention from military exercises, and keep
them engaged in indolent and sedentary occupations.
Charles the Eighth found himself master of Tuscany and the kingdom of Naples,
almost without drawing sword; and all his court attributed this unexpected success to
the fact that the princes and nobles of Italy applied themselves with greater
earnestness to the cultivation of their understandings than to active and martial
pursuits. In fact, says the sensible person who records these characteristics, experience
plainly tells us, that in military matters and all that resemble them application to the
sciences tends rather to make men effeminate and cowardly than resolute and
vigorous.
The Romans confessed that military virtue was extinguished among them, in
proportion as they became connoisseurs in the arts of the painter, the engraver and the
goldsmith, and began to cultivate the fine arts. Indeed, as if this famous country was
to be for ever an example to other nations, the rise of the Medici and the revival of
letters has once more destroyed, this time perhaps for ever, the martial reputation
which Italy seemed a few centuries ago to have recovered.
The ancient republics of Greece, with that wisdom which was so conspicuous in most
of their institutions, forbade their citizens to pursue all those inactive and sedentary
occupations, which by enervating and corrupting the body diminish also the vigour of
the mind. With what courage, in fact, can it be thought that hunger and thirst, fatigues,
dangers and death, can be faced by men whom the smallest want overwhelms and the
slightest difficulty repels? With what resolution can soldiers support the excessive
toils of war, when they are entirely unaccustomed to them? With what spirits can they
make forced marches under officers who have not even the strength to travel on
horseback? It is no answer to cite the reputed valour of all the modern warriors who
are so scientifically trained. I hear much of their bravery in a day’s battle; but I am
told nothing of how they support excessive fatigue, how they stand the severity of the
seasons and the inclemency of the weather. A little sunshine or snow, or the want of a
few superfluities, is enough to cripple and destroy one of our finest armies in a few
days. Intrepid warriors! permit me for once to tell you the truth, which you seldom
hear. Of your bravery I am fully satisfied. I have no doubt that you would have
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
147
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
triumphed with Hannibal at Cannæ, and at Trasimene: that you would have passed the
Rubicon with Cæsar, and enabled him to enslave his country; but you never would
have been able to cross the Alps with the former, or with the latter to subdue your
own ancestors, the Gauls.
A war does not always depend on the events of battle: there is in generalship an art
superior to that of gaining victories. A man may behave with great intrepidity under
fire, and yet be a very bad officer. Even in the common soldier, a little more strength
and vigour would perhaps be more useful than so much courage, which after all is no
protection from death. And what does it matter to the State whether its troops perish
by cold and fever, or by the sword of the enemy?
If the cultivation of the sciences is prejudicial to military qualities, it is still more so to
moral qualities. Even from our infancy an absurd system of education serves to adorn
our wit and corrupt our judgment. We see, on every side, huge institutions, where our
youth are educated at great expense, and instructed in everything but their duty. Your
children will be ignorant of their own language, when they can talk others which are
not spoken anywhere. They will be able to compose verses which they can hardly
understand; and, without being capable of distinguishing truth from error, they will
possess the art of making them unrecognisable by specious arguments. But
magnanimity, equity, temperance, humanity and courage will be words of which they
know not the meaning. The dear name of country will never strike on their ears; and if
they ever hear speak of God,1 it will be less to fear, than to be frightened of, Him. I
would as soon, said a wise man, that my pupil had spent his time in the tennis court as
in this manner; for there his body at least would have got exercise.
I well know that children ought to be kept employed, and that idleness is for them the
danger most to be feared. But what should they be taught? This is undoubtedly an
important question. Let them be taught what they are to practise when they come to be
men;1 not what they ought to forget.
Our gardens are adorned with statues and our galleries with pictures. What would you
imagine these masterpieces of art, thus exhibited to public admiration, represent? The
great men, who have defended their country, or the still greater men who have
enriched it by their virtues? Far from it. They are the images of every perversion of
heart and mind, carefully selected from ancient mythology, and presented to the early
curiosity of our children, doubtless that they may have before their eyes the
representations of vicious actions, even before they are able to read.
Whence arise all those abuses, unless it be from that fatal inequality introduced
among men by the difference of talents and the cheapening of virtue? This is the most
evident effect of all our studies, and the most dangerous of all their consequences. The
question is no longer whether a man is honest, but whether he is clever. We do not ask
whether a book is useful, but whether it is well-written. Rewards are lavished on with
and ingenuity, while virtue is left unhonoured. There are a thousand prizes for fine
discourses, and none for good actions. I should be glad, however, to know whether the
honour attaching to the best discourse that ever wins the prize in this Academy is
comparable with the merit of having founded the prize.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
148
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
A wise man does not go in chase of fortune; but he is by no means insensible to glory,
and when he sees it so ill distributed, his virtue, which might have been animated by a
little emulation, and turned to the advantage of society, droops and dies away in
obscurity and indigence. It is for this reason that the agreeable arts must in time
everywhere be preferred to the useful; and this truth has been but too much confirmed
since the revival of the arts and sciences. We have physicists, geometricians,
chemists, astronomers, poets, musicians, and painters in plenty; but we have no longer
a citizen among us; or if there be found a few scattered over our abandoned
countryside, they are left to perish there unnoticed and neglected. Such is the
condition to which we are reduced, and such are our feelings towards those who give
us our daily bread, and our children milk.
I confess, however, that the evil is not so great as it might have become. The eternal
providence, in placing salutary simples beside noxious plants, and making poisonous
animals contain their own antidote, has taught the sovereigns of the earth, who are its
ministers, to imitate its wisdom. It is by following this example that the truly great
monarch, to whose glory every age will add new lustre, drew from the very bosom of
the arts and sciences, the very fountains of a thousand lapses from rectitude, those
famous societies, which, while they are depositaries of the dangerous trust of human
knowledge, are yet the sacred guardians of morals, by the attention they pay to their
maintenance among themselves in all their purity, and by the demands which they
make on every member whom they admit.
These wise institutions, confirmed by his august successor and imitated by all the
kings of Europe, will serve at least to restrain men of letters, who, all aspiring to the
honour of being admitted into these Academies, will keep watch over themselves, and
endeavour to make themselves worthy of such honour by useful performances and
irreproachable morals. Those Academies also, which, in proposing prizes for literary
merit, make choice of such subjects as are calculated to arouse the love of virtue in
the hearts of citizens, prove that it prevails in themselves, and must give men the rare
and real pleasure of finding learned societies devoting themselves to the
enlightenment of mankind, not only by agreeable exercises of the intellect, but also by
useful instructions.
An objection which may be made is, in fact, only an additional proof of my argument.
So much precaution proves but too evidently the need for it. We never seek remedies
for evils that do not exist. Why, indeed, must these bear all the marks of ordinary
remedies, on account of their inefficacy? The numerous establishments in favour of
the learned are only adapted to make men mistake the objects of the sciences, and turn
men’s attention to the cultivation of them. One would be inclined to think, from the
precautions everywhere taken, that we are overstocked with husbandmen, and are
afraid of a shortage of philosophers. I will not venture here to enter into a comparison
between agriculture and philosophy, as they would not bear it. I shall only ask What is
philosophy? What is contained in the writings of the most celebrated philosophers?
What are the lessons of these friends of wisdom. To hear them, should we not take
them for so many mountebanks, exhibiting themselves in public, and crying out,
Here, Here, come to me, I am the only true doctor? One of them teaches that there is
no such thing as matter, but that everything exists only in representation. Another
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
149
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
declares that there is no other substance than matter, and no other God than the world
itself. A third tells you that there are no such things as virtue and vice, and that moral
good and evil are chimeras; while a fourth informs you that men are only beasts of
prey, and may conscientiously devour one another. Why, my great philosophers, do
you not reserve these wise and profitable lessons for your friends and children? You
would soon reap the benefit of them, nor should we be under any apprehension of our
own becoming your disciples.
Such are the wonderful men, whom their contemporaries held in the highest esteem
during their lives, and to whom immortality has been attributed since their decease.
Such are the wise maxims we have received from them, and which are transmitted,
from age to age, to our descendants. Paganism, though given over to all the
extravagances of human reason, has left nothing to compare with the shameful
monuments which have been prepared by the art of printing, during the reign of the
gospel. The impious writings of Leucippus and Diagoras perished with their authors.
The world, in their days, was ignorant of the art of immortalising the errors and
extravagancies of the human mind. But thanks to the art of printing1 and the use we
make of it, the pernicious reflections of Hobbes and Spinoza will last for ever. Go,
famous writings, of which the ignorance and rusticity of our forefathers would have
been incapable. Go to our descendants, along with those still more pernicious works
which reek of the corrupted manners of the present age! Let them together convey to
posterity a faithful history of the progress and advantages of our arts and sciences. If
they are read, they will leave not a doubt about the question we are now discussing,
and unless mankind should then be still more foolish than we, they will lift up their
hands to Heaven and exclaim in bitterness of heart: “Almighty God! thou who holdest
in Thy hand the minds of men, deliver us from the fatal arts and sciences of our
forefathers; give us back ignorance, innocence and poverty, which alone can make us
happy and are precious in Thy sight.”
But if the progress of the arts and sciences has added nothing to our real happiness; if
it has corrupted our morals, and if that corruption has vitiated our taste, what are we to
think of the herd of text-book authors, who have removed those impediments which
nature purposely laid in the way to the Temple of the Muses, in order to guard its
approach and try the powers of those who might be tempted to seek knowledge? What
are we to think of those compilers who have indiscreetly broken open the door of the
sciences, and introduced into their sanctuary a populace unworthy to approach it,
when it was greatly to be wished that all who should be found incapable of making a
considerable progress in the career of learning should have been repulsed at the
entrance, and thereby cast upon those arts which are useful to society. A man who
will be all his life a bad versifier, or a third-rate geometrician, might have made
nevertheless an excellent clothier. Those whom nature intended for her disciples have
not needed masters. Bacon, Descartes and Newton, those teachers of mankind, had
themselves no teachers. What guide indeed could have taken them so far as their
sublime genius directed them? Ordinary masters would only have cramped their
intelligence, by confining it within the narrow limits of their own capacity. It was
from the obstacles they met with at first, that they learned to exert themselves, and
bestirred themselves to traverse the vast field which they covered. If it be proper to
allow some men to apply themselves to the study of the arts and sciences, it is only
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
150
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
those who feel themselves able to walk alone in their footsteps and to outstrip them. It
belongs only to these few to raise monuments to the glory of the human
understanding. But if we are desirous that nothing should be above their genius,
nothing should be beyond their hopes. This is the only encouragement they require.
The soul insensibly adapts itself to the objects on which it is employed, and thus it is
that great occasions produce great men. The greatest orator in the world was Consul
of Rome, and perhaps the greatest of philosophers Lord Chancellor of England. Can it
be conceived that, if the former had only been a professor at some University, and the
latter a pensioner of some Academy, their works would not have suffered from their
situation. Let not princes disdain to admit into their councils those who are most
capable of giving them good advice. Let them renounce the old prejudice, which was
invented by the pride of the great, that the art of governing mankind is more difficult
than that of instructing them; as if it was easier to induce men to do good voluntarily,
than to compel them to it by force. Let the learned of the first rank find an honourable
refuge in their courts; let them there enjoy the only recompense worthy of them, that
of promoting by their influence the happiness of the peoples they have enlightened by
their wisdom. It is by this means only that we are likely to see what virtue, science
and authority can do, when animated by the noblest emulation, and working
unanimously for the happiness of mankind.
But so long as power alone is on one side, and knowledge and understanding alone on
the other, the learned will seldom make great objects their study, princes will still
more rarely do great actions, and the peoples will continue to be, as they are, mean,
corrupt and miserable.
As for us, ordinary men, on whom Heaven has not been pleased to bestow such great
talents; as we are not destined to reap such glory, let us remain in our obscurity. Let
us not covet a reputation we should never attain, and which, in the present state of
things, would never make up to us for the trouble it would have cost us, even if we
were fully qualified to obtain it. Why should we build our happiness on the opinions
of others, when we can find it in our own hearts? Let us leave to others the task of
instructing mankind in their duty, and confine ourselves to the discharge of our own.
We have no occasion for greater knowledge than this.
Virtue! sublime science of simple minds, are such industry and preparation needed if
we are to know you? Are not your principles graven on every heart? Need we do
more, to learn your laws, than examine ourselves, and listen to the voice of
conscience, when the passions are silent?
This is the true philosophy, with which we must learn to be content, without envying
the fame of those celebrated men, whose names are immortal in the republic of letters.
Let us, instead of envying them, endeavour to make, between them and us, that
honourable distinction which was formerly seen to exist between two great peoples,
that the one knew how to speak, and the other how to act, aright.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
151
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
A DISCOURSE On A Subject Proposed By The Academy Of
Dijon:
What Is The Origin Of Inequality Among Men, And Is It
Authorised By Natural Law?
Non in depravatis, sed in his quæ bene secundum naturam se habent, considerandum
est quid sit naturale.
Aristotle, Politics, Bk. i, ch. 2.
[We should consider what is natural not in things which are depraved but in those
which are rightly ordered according to nature.]
Dedication To The REPUBLIC OF GENEVA
Most Honourable, Magnificent and Sovereign Lords, convinced that only a virtuous
citizen can confer on his country honours which it can accept, I have been for thirty
years past working to make myself worthy to offer you some public homage; and, this
fortunate opportunity supplementing in some degree the insufficiency of my efforts, I
have thought myself entitled to follow in embracing it the dictates of the zeal which
inspires me, rather than the right which should have been my authorisation. Having
had the happiness to be born among you, how could I reflect on the equality which
nature has ordained between men, and the inequality which they have introduced,
without reflecting on the profound wisdom by which both are in this State happily
combined and made to coincide, in the manner that is most in conformity with natural
law, and most favourable to society, to the maintenance of public order and to the
happiness of individuals? In my researches after the best rules common sense can lay
down for the constitution of a government, I have been so struck at finding them all in
actuality in your own, that even had I not been born within your walls I should have
thought it indispensable for me to offer this picture of human society to that people,
which of all others seems to be possessed of its greatest advantages, and to have best
guarded against its abuses.
If I had had to make choice of the place of my birth, I should have preferred a society
which had an extent proportionate to the limits of the human faculties; that is, to the
possibility of being well governed: in which every person being equal to his
occupation, no one should be obliged to commit to others the functions with which he
was entrusted: a State, in which all the individuals being well known to one another,
neither the secret machinations of vice, nor the modesty of virtue should be able to
escape the notice and judgment of the public; and in which the pleasant custom of
seeing and knowing one another should make the love of country rather a love of the
citizens than of its soil.
I should have wished to be born in a country in which the interest of the Sovereign
and that of the people must be single and identical; to the end that all the movements
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
152
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
of the machine might tend always to the general happiness. And as this could not be
the case, unless the Sovereign and the people were one and the same person, it
follows that I should have wished to be born under a democratic government, wisely
tempered.
I should have wished to live and die free: that is, so far subject to the laws that neither
I, nor anybody else, should be able to cast off their honourable yoke: the easy and
salutary yoke which the haughtiest necks bear with the greater docility, as they are
made to bear no other.
I should have wished then that no one within the State should be able to say he was
above the law; and that no one without should be able to dictate so that the State
should be obliged to recognise his authority. For, be the constitution of a government
what it may, if there be within its jurisdiction a single man who is not subject to the
law, all the rest are necessarily at his discretion. And if there be a national ruler
within, and a foreign ruler without, however they may divide their authority, it is
impossible that both should be duly obeyed, or that the State should be well governed.
I should not have chosen to live in a republic of recent institution, however excellent
its laws; for fear the government, being perhaps otherwise framed than the
circumstances of the moment might require, might disagree with the new citizens, or
they with it, and the State run the risk of overthrow and destruction almost as soon as
it came into being. For it is with liberty as it is with those solid and succulent foods, or
with those generous wines which are well adapted to nourish and fortify robust
constitutions that are used to them, but ruin and intoxicate weak and delicate
constitutions to which they are not suited. Peoples once accustomed to masters are not
in a condition to do without them. If they attempt to shake off the yoke, they still
more estrange themselves from freedom, as, by mistaking for it an unbridled license
to which it is diametrically opposed, they nearly always manage, by their revolutions,
to hand themselves over to seducers, who only make their chains heavier than before.
The Roman people itself, a model for all free peoples, was wholly incapable of
governing itself when it escaped from the oppression of the Tarquins. Debased by
slavery, and the ignominious tasks which had been imposed upon it, it was at first no
better than a stupid mob, which it was necessary to control and govern with the
greatest wisdom; in order that, being accustomed by degrees to breathe the health-
giving air of liberty, minds which had been enervated or rather brutalised under
tyranny, might gradually acquire that severity of morals and spirit of fortitude which
made it at length the people of all most worthy of respect. I should, then, have sought
out for my country some peaceful and happy Republic, of an antiquity that lost itself,
as it were, in the night of time: which had experienced only such shocks as served to
manifest and strengthen the courage and patriotism of its subjects; and whose citizens,
long accustomed to a wise independence, were not only free, but worthy to be so.
I should have wished to choose myself a country, diverted, by a fortunate impotence,
from the brutal love of conquest, and secured, by a still more fortunate situation, from
the fear of becoming itself the conquest of other States: a free city situated between
several nations, none of which should have any interest in attacking it, while each had
an interest in preventing it from being attacked by the others; in short, a Republic
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
153
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
which should have nothing to tempt the ambition of its neighbours, but might
reasonably depend on their assistance in case of need. It follows that a republican
State so happily situated could have nothing to fear but from itself; and that, if its
members trained themselves to the use of arms, it would be rather to keep alive that
military ardour and courageous spirit which are so proper among free-men, and tend
to keep up their taste for liberty, than from the necessity of providing for their
defence.
I should have sought a country, in which the right of legislation was vested in all the
citizens; for who can judge better than they of the conditions under which they had
best dwell together in the same society? Not that I should have approved of Plebiscita,
like those among the Romans; in which the rulers in the State, and those most
interested in its preservation, were excluded from the deliberations on which in many
cases its security depended; and in which, by the most absurd inconsistency, the
magistrates were deprived of rights which the meanest citizens enjoyed.
On the contrary, I should have desired that, in order to prevent self-interested and ill-
conceived projects, and all such dangerous innovations as finally ruined the
Athenians, each man should not be at liberty to propose new laws at pleasure; but that
this right should belong exclusively to the magistrates; and that even they should use
it with so much caution, the people, on its side, be so reserved in giving its consent to
such laws, and the promulgation of them be attended with so much solemnity, that
before the constitution could be upset by them, there might be time enough for all to
be convinced, that it is above all the great antiquity of the laws which makes them
sacred and venerable, that men soon learn to despise laws which they see daily
altered, and that States, by accustoming themselves to neglect their ancient customs
under the pretext of improvement, often introduce greater evils than those they
endeavour to remove.
I should have particularly avoided, as necessarily ill-governed, a Republic in which
the people, imagining themselves in a position to do without magistrates, or at least to
leave them with only a precarious authority, should imprudently have kept for
themselves the administration of civil affairs and the execution of their own laws.
Such must have been the rude constitution of primitive governments, directly
emerging from a state of nature; and this was another of the vices that contributed to
the downfall of the Republic of Athens.
But I should have chosen a community in which the individuals, content with
sanctioning their laws, and deciding the most important public affairs in general
assembly and on the motion of the rulers, had established honoured tribunals,
carefully distinguished the several departments, and elected year by year some of the
most capable and upright of their fellow-citizens to administer justice and govern the
State; a community, in short, in which the virtue of the magistrates thus bearing
witness to the wisdom of the people, each class reciprocally did the other honour. If in
such a case any fatal misunderstandings arose to disturb the public peace, even these
intervals of blindness and error would bear the marks of moderation, mutual esteem,
and a common respect for the laws; which are sure signs and pledges of a
reconciliation as lasting as sincere. Such are the advantages, most honourable,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
154
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
magnificent and sovereign lords, which I should have sought in the country in which I
should have chosen to be born. And if providence had added to all these a delightful
situation, a temperate climate, a fertile soil, and the most beautiful countryside under
Heaven, I should have desired only, to complete my felicity, the peaceful enjoyment
of all these blessings, in the bosom of this happy country; to live at peace in the sweet
society of my fellow-citizens, and practising towards them, from their own example,
the duties of friendship, humanity, and every other virtue, to leave behind me the
honourable memory of a good man, and an upright and virtuous patriot.
But, if less fortunate or too late grown wise, I had seen myself reduced to end an
infirm and languishing life in other climates, vainly regretting that peaceful repose
which I had forfeited in the imprudence of youth, I should at least have entertained the
same feelings in my heart, though denied the opportunity of making use of them in
my native country. Filled with a tender and disinterested love for my distant fellow-
citizens, I should have addressed them from my heart, much in the following terms.
“My dear fellow-citizens, or rather my brothers, since the ties of blood, as well as the
laws, unite almost all of us, it gives me pleasure that I cannot think of you, without
thinking, at the same time, of all the blessings you enjoy, and of which none of you,
perhaps, more deeply feels the value than I who have lost them. The more I reflect on
your civil and political condition, the less can I conceive that the nature of human
affairs could admit of a better. In all other governments, when there is a question of
ensuring the greatest good of the State, nothing gets beyond projects and ideas, or at
best bare possibilities. But as for you, your happiness is complete, and you have
nothing to do but enjoy it; you require nothing more to be made perfectly happy, than
to know how to be satisfied with being so. Your sovereignty, acquired or recovered by
the sword, and maintained for two centuries past by your valour and wisdom, is at
length fully and universally acknowledged. Your boundaries are fixed, your rights
confirmed and your repose secured by honourable treaties. Your constitution is
excellent, being not only dictated by the profoundest wisdom, but guaranteed by great
and friendly powers. Your State enjoys perfect tranquillity; you have neither wars nor
conquerors to fear; you have no other master than the wise laws you have yourselves
made; and these are administered by upright magistrates of your own choosing. You
are neither so wealthy as to be enervated by effeminacy, and thence to lose, in the
pursuit of frivolous pleasures, the taste for real happiness and solid virtue; nor poor
enough to require more assistance from abroad than your own industry is sufficient to
procure you. In the meantime the precious privilege of liberty, which in great nations
is maintained only by submission to the most exorbitant impositions, costs you hardly
anything for its preservation.
May a Republic, so wisely and happily constituted, last for ever, for an example to
other nations, and for the felicity of its own citizens! This is the only prayer you have
left to make, the only precaution that remains to be taken. It depends, for the future,
on yourselves alone (not to make you happy, for your ancestors have saved you that
trouble), but to render that happiness lasting, by your wisdom in its enjoyment. It is on
your constant union, your obedience to the laws, and your respect for their ministers,
that your preservation depends. If there remains among you the smallest trace of
bitterness or distrust, hasten to destroy it, as an accursed leaven which sooner or later
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
155
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
must bring misfortune and ruin on the State. I conjure you all to look into your hearts,
and to hearken to the secret voice of conscience. Is there any among you who can
find, throughout the universe, a more upright, more enlightened and more honourable
body than your magistracy? Do not all its members set you an example of moderation,
of simplicity of manners, of respect for the laws, and of the most sincere harmony?
Place, therefore, without reserve, in such wise superiors, that salutary confidence
which reason ever owes to virtue. Consider that they are your own choice, that they
justify that choice, and that the honours due to those whom you have dignified are
necessarily yours by reflexion. Not one of you is so ignorant as not to know that,
when the laws lose their force and those who defend them their authority, security and
liberty are universally impossible. Why, therefore, should you hesitate to do that
cheerfully and with just confidence which you would all along have been bound to do
by your true interest, your duty and reason itself?
Let not a culpable and pernicious indifference to the maintenance of the constitution
ever induce you to neglect, in case of need, the prudent advice of the most enlightened
and zealous of your fellow-citizens; but let equity, moderation and firmness of
resolution continue to regulate all your proceedings, and to exhibit you to the whole
universe as the example of a valiant and modest people, jealous equally of their
honour and of their liberty. Beware particularly, as the last piece of advice I shall give
you, of sinister constructions and venomous rumours, the secret motives of which are
often more dangerous than the actions at which they are levelled. A whole house will
be awake and take the first alarm given by a good and trusty watch-dog, who barks
only at the approach of thieves; but we hate the importunity of those noisy curs, which
are perpetually disturbing the public repose, and whose continual ill-timed warnings
prevent our attending to them, when they may perhaps be necessary.”
And you, most honourable and magnificent lords, the worthy and revered magistrates
of a free people, permit me to offer you in particular my duty and homage. If there is
in the world a station capable of conferring honour on those who fill it, it is
undoubtedly that which virtue and talents combine to bestow, that of which you have
made yourselves worthy, and to which you have been promoted by your fellow-
citizens. Their worth adds a new lustre to your own; while, as you have been chosen,
by men capable of governing others, to govern themselves, I cannot but hold you as
much superior to all other magistrates, as a free people, and particularly that over
which you have the honour to preside, is by its wisdom and its reason superior to the
populace of other States.
Be it permitted me to cite an example of which there ought to have existed better
records, and one which will be ever near to my heart. I cannot recall to mind, without
the sweetest emotions, the memory of that virtuous citizen, to whom I owe my being,
and by whom I was often instructed, in my infancy, in the respect which is due to you.
I see him still, living by the work of his hands, and feeding his soul on the sublimest
truths. I see the works of Tacitus, Plutarch and Grotius, lying before him in the midst
of the tools of his trade. At his side stands his dear son, receiving, alas with too little
profit, the tender instructions of the best of fathers. But, if the follies of youth made
me for a while forget his wise lessons, I have at length the happiness to be conscious
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
156
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
that, whatever propensity one may have to vice, it is not easy for an education, with
which love has mingled, to be entirely thrown away.
Such, my most honourable and magnificent lords, are the citizens, and even the
common inhabitants of the State which you govern; such are those intelligent and
sensible men, of whom, under the name of workmen and the people, it is usual, in
other nations, to have a low and false opinion. My father, I own with pleasure, was in
no way distinguished among his fellow-citizens. He was only such as they all are; and
yet, such as he was, there is no country, in which his acquaintance would not have
been coveted, and cultivated even with advantage by men of the highest character. It
would not become me, nor is it, thank Heaven, at all necessary for me to remind you
of the regard which such men have a right to expect of their magistrates, to whom
they are equal both by education and by the rights of nature and birth, and inferior
only, by their own will, by that preference which they owe to your merit, and, for
giving you, can claim some sort of acknowledgment on your side. It is with a lively
satisfaction I understand that the greatest candour and condescension attend, in all
your behaviour towards them, on that gravity which becomes the ministers of the law;
and that you so well repay them, by your esteem and attention, the respect and
obedience which they owe to you. This conduct is not only just but prudent; as it
happily tends to obliterate the memory of many unhappy events, which ought to be
buried in eternal oblivion. It is also so much the more judicious, as it tends to make
this generous and equitable people find a pleasure in their duty; to make them
naturally love to do you honour, and to cause those who are the most zealous in the
maintenance of their own rights to be at the same time the most disposed to respect
yours.
It ought not to be thought surprising that the rulers of a civil society should have the
welfare and glory of their communities at heart: but it is uncommonly fortunate for
the peace of men, when those persons who look upon themselves as the magistrates,
or rather the masters of a more holy and sublime country, show some love for the
earthly country which maintains them. I am happy in having it in my power to make
so singular an exception in our favour, and to be able to rank, among its best citizens,
those zealous depositaries of the sacred articles of faith established by the laws, those
venerable shepherds of souls whose powerful and captivating eloquence are so much
the better calculated to bear to men’s hearts the maxims of the gospel, as they are
themselves the first to put them into practice. All the world knows of the great success
with which the art of the pulpit is cultivated at Geneva; but men are so used to hearing
divines preach one thing and practise another, that few have a chance of knowing how
far the spirit of Christianity, holiness of manners, severity towards themselves and
indulgence towards their neighbours, prevail throughout the whole body of our
ministers. It is, perhaps, given to the city of Geneva alone, to produce the edifying
example of so perfect a union between its clergy and men of letters. It is in great
measure on their wisdom, their known moderation, and their zeal for the prosperity of
the State that I build my hopes of its perpetual tranquillity. At the same time, I notice,
with a pleasure mingled with surprise and veneration, how much they detest the
frightful maxims of those accursed and barbarous men, of whom history furnishes us
with more than one example; who, in order to support the pretended rights of God,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
157
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
that is to say their own interests, have been so much the less greedy of human blood,
as they were more hopeful their own in particular would be always respected.
I must not forget that precious half of the Republic, which makes the happiness of the
other; and whose sweetness and prudence preserve its tranquillity and virtue. Amiable
and virtuous daughters of Geneva, it will be always the lot of your sex to govern ours.
Happy are we, so long as your chaste influence, solely exercised within the limits of
conjugal union, is exerted only for the glory of the State and the happiness of the
public. It was thus the female sex commanded at Sparta; and thus you deserve to
command at Geneva. What man can be such a barbarian as to resist the voice of
honour and reason, coming from the lips of an affectionate wife? Who would not
despise the vanities of luxury, on beholding the simple and modest attire which, from
the lustre it derives from you, seems the most favourable to beauty? It is your task to
perpetuate, by your insinuating influence and your innocent and amiable rule, a
respect for the laws of the State, and harmony among the citizens. It is yours to
reunite divided families by happy marriages; and, above all things, to correct, by the
persuasive sweetness of your lessons and the modest graces of your conversation,
those extravagancies which our young people pick up in other countries, whence,
instead of many useful things by which they might profit, they bring home hardly
anything, besides a puerile air and a ridiculous manner, acquired among loose women,
but an admiration for I know not what so-called grandeur, and paltry recompenses for
being slaves, which can never come near the real greatness of liberty. Continue,
therefore, always to be what you are, the chaste guardians of our morals, and the
sweet security for our peace, exerting on every occasion the privileges of the heart
and of nature, in the interests of duty and virtue.
I flatter myself that I shall never be proved to have been mistaken, in building on such
a foundation my hopes of the general happiness of the citizens and the glory of the
Republic. It must be confessed, however, that with all these advantages, it will not
shine with that lustre, by which the eyes of most men are dazzled; a puerile and fatal
taste for which is the most mortal enemy of happiness and liberty.
Let our dissolute youth seek elsewhere light pleasures and long repentances. Let our
pretenders to taste admire elsewhere the grandeur of palaces, the beauty of equipages,
sumptuous furniture, the pomp of public entertainments, and all the refinements of
luxury and effeminacy. Geneva boasts nothing but men; such a sight has nevertheless
a value of its own, and those who have a taste for it are well worth the admirers of all
the rest.
Deign, most honourable, magnificent and sovereign lords, to receive, and with equal
goodness, this respectful testimony of the interest I take in your common prosperity.
And, if I have been so unhappy as to be guilty of any indiscreet transport in this
glowing effusion of my heart, I beseech you to pardon me, and to attribute it to the
tender affection of a true patriot, and to the ardent and legitimate zeal of a man, who
can imagine for himself no greater felicity than to see you happy.
Most honourable, magnificent and sovereign lords, I am, with the most profound
respect,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
158
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Your most humble and obedient servant and fellow-citizen.
J. J. Rousseau.
Chambéry,
June 12, 1754.
PREFACE
Of all human sciences the most useful and most imperfect appears to me to be that of
mankind: and I will venture to say, the single inscription on the Temple of Delphi
contained a precept more difficult and more important than is to be found in all the
huge volumes that moralists have ever written. I consider the subject of the following
discourse as one of the most interesting questions philosophy can propose, and
unhappily for us, one of the most thorny that philosophers can have to solve. For how
shall we know the source of inequality between men, if we do not begin by knowing
mankind? And how shall man hope to see himself as nature made him, across all the
changes which the succession of place and time must have produced in his original
constitution? How can he distinguish what is fundamental in his nature from the
changes and additions which his circumstances and the advances he has made have
introduced to modify his primitive condition? Like the statue of Glaucus, which was
so disfigured by time, seas and tempests, that it looked more like a wild beast than a
god, the human soul, altered in society by a thousand causes perpetually recurring, by
the acquisition of a multitude of truths and errors, by the changes happening to the
constitution of the body, and by the continual jarring of the passions, has, so to speak,
changed in appearance, so as to be hardly recognisable. Instead of a being, acting
constantly from fixed and invariable principles, instead of that celestial and majestic
simplicity, impressed on it by its divine Author, we find in it only the frightful
contrast of passion mistaking itself for reason, and of understanding grown delirious.
It is still more cruel that, as every advance made by the human species removes it still
farther from its primitive state, the more discoveries we make, the more we deprive
ourselves of the means of making the most important of all. Thus it is, in one sense,
by our very study of man, that the knowledge of him is put out of our power.
It is easy to perceive that it is in these successive changes in the constitution of man
that we must look for the origin of those differences which now distinguish men, who,
it is allowed, are as equal among themselves as were the animals of every kind, before
physical causes had introduced those varieties which are now observable among some
of them.
It is, in fact, not to be conceived that these primary changes, however they may have
arisen, could have altered, all at once and in the same manner, every individual of the
species. It is natural to think that, while the condition of some of them grew better or
worse, and they were acquiring various good or bad qualities not inherent in their
nature, there were others who continued a longer time in their original condition. Such
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
159
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
was doubtless the first source of the inequality of mankind, which it is much easier to
point out thus in general terms, than to assign with precision to its actual causes.
Let not my readers therefore imagine that I flatter myself with having seen what it
appears to me so difficult to discover. I have here entered upon certain arguments, and
risked some conjectures, less in the hope of solving the difficulty, than with a view to
throwing some light upon it, and reducing the question to its proper form. Others may
easily proceed farther on the same road, and yet no one find it very easy to get to the
end. For it is by no means a light undertaking to distinguish properly between what is
original and what is artificial in the actual nature of man, or to form a true idea of a
state which no longer exists, perhaps never did exist, and probably never will exist;
and of which, it is, nevertheless, necessary to have true ideas, in order to form a
proper judgment of our present state. It requires, indeed, more philosophy than can be
imagined to enable any one to determine exactly what precautions he ought to take, in
order to make solid observations on this subject; and it appears to me that a good
solution of the following problem would be not unworthy of the Aristotles and Plinys
of the present age. What experiments would have to be made, to discover the natural
man? And how are those experiments to be made in a state of society?
So far am I from undertaking to solve this problem, that I think I have sufficiently
considered the subject, to venture to declare beforehand that our greatest philosophers
would not be too good to direct such experiments, and our most powerful sovereigns
to make them. Such a combination we have very little reason to expect, especially
attended with the perseverance, or rather succession of intelligence and good-will
necessary on both sides to success.
These investigations, which are so difficult to make, and have been hitherto so little
thought of, are, nevertheless, the only means that remain of obviating a multitude of
difficulties which deprive us of the knowledge of the real foundations of human
society. It is this ignorance of the nature of man, which casts so much uncertainty and
obscurity on the true definition of natural right: for, the idea of right, says
Burlamaqui, and more particularly that of natural right, are ideas manifestly relative to
the nature of man. It is then from this very nature itself, he goes on, from the
constitution and state of man, that we must deduce the first principles of this science.
We cannot see without surprise and disgust how little agreement there is between the
different authors who have treated this great subject. Among the more important
writers there are scarcely two of the same mind about it. Not to speak of the ancient
philosophers, who seem to have done their best purposely to contradict one another on
the most fundamental principles, the Roman jurists subjected man and the other
animals indiscriminately to the same natural law, because they considered, under that
name, rather the law which nature imposes on herself than that which she prescribes
to others; or rather because of the particular acceptation of the term law among those
jurists; who seem on this occasion to have understood nothing more by it than the
general relations established by nature between all animated beings, for their common
preservation. The moderns, understanding, by the term law, merely a rule prescribed
to a moral being, that is to say intelligent, free and considered in his relations to other
beings, consequently confine the jurisdiction of natural law to man, as the only animal
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
160
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
endowed with reason. But, defining this law, each after his own fashion, they have
established it on such metaphysical principles, that there are very few persons among
us capable of comprehending them, much less of discovering them for themselves. So
that the definitions of these learned men, all differing in everything else, agree only in
this, that it is impossible to comprehend the law of nature, and consequently to obey
it, without being a very subtle casuist and a profound metaphysician. All which is as
much as to say that mankind must have employed, in the establishment of society, a
capacity which is acquired only with great difficulty, and by very few persons, even in
a state of society.
Knowing so little of nature, and agreeing so ill about the meaning of the word law, it
would be difficult for us to fix on a good definition of natural law. Thus all the
definitions we meet with in books, setting aside their defect in point of uniformity,
have yet another fault, in that they are derived from many kinds of knowledge, which
men do not possess naturally, and from advantages of which they can have no idea
until they have already departed from that state. Modern writers begin by inquiring
what rules it would be expedient for men to agree on for their common interest, and
then give the name of natural law to a collection of these rules, without any other
proof than the good that would result from their being universally practised. This is
undoubtedly a simple way of making definitions, and of explaining the nature of
things by almost arbitrary conveniences.
But as long as we are ignorant of the natural man, it is in vain for us to attempt to
determine either the law originally prescribed to him, or that which is best adapted to
his constitution. All we can know with any certainty respecting this law is that, if it is
to be a law, not only the wills of those it obliges must be sensible of their submission
to it; but also, to be natural, it must come directly from the voice of nature.
Throwing aside, therefore, all those scientific books, which teach us only to see men
such as they have made themselves, and contemplating the first and most simple
operations of the human soul, I think I can perceive in it two principles prior to
reason, one of them deeply interesting us in our own welfare and preservation, and the
other exciting a natural repugnance at seeing any other sensible being, and
particularly any of our own species, suffer pain or death. It is from the agreement and
combination which the understanding is in a position to establish between these two
principles, without its being necessary to introduce that of sociability, that all the rules
of natural right appear to me to be derived—rules which our reason is afterwards
obliged to establish on other foundations, when by its successive developments it has
been led to suppress nature itself.
In proceeding thus, we shall not be obliged to make man a philosopher before he is a
man. His duties toward others are not dictated to him only by the later lessons of
wisdom; and, so long as he does not resist the internal impulse of compassion, he will
never hurt any other man, nor even any sentient being, except on those lawful
occasions on which his own preservation is concerned and he is obliged to give
himself the preference. By this method also we put an end to the time-honoured
disputes concerning the participation of animals in natural law: for it is clear that,
being destitute of intelligence and liberty, they cannot recognise that law; as they
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
161
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
partake, however, in some measure of our nature, in consequence of the sensibility
with which they are endowed, they ought to partake of natural right; so that mankind
is subjected to a kind of obligation even toward the brutes. It appears, in fact, that if I
am bound to do no injury to my fellow-creatures, this is less because they are rational
than because they are sentient beings: and this quality, being common both to men
and beasts, ought to entitle the latter at least to the privilege of not being wantonly ill-
treated by the former.
The very study of the original man, of his real wants, and the fundamental principles
of his duty, is besides the only proper method we can adopt to obviate all the
difficulties which the origin of moral inequality presents, on the true foundations of
the body politic, on the reciprocal rights of its members, and on many other similar
topics equally important and obscure.
If we look at human society with a calm and disinterested eye, it seems, at first, to
show us only the violence of the powerful and the oppression of the weak. The mind
is shocked at the cruelty of the one, or is induced to lament the blindness of the other;
and as nothing is less permanent in life than those external relations, which are more
frequently produced by accident than wisdom, and which are called weakness or
power, riches or poverty, all human institutions seem at first glance to be founded
merely on banks of shifting sand. It is only by taking a closer look, and removing the
dust and sand that surround the edifice, that we perceive the immovable basis on
which it is raised, and learn to respect its foundations. Now, without a serious study of
man, his natural faculties and their successive development, we shall never be able to
make these necessary distinctions, or to separate, in the actual constitution of things,
that which is the effect of the divine will, from the innovations attempted by human
art. The political and moral investigations, therefore, to which the important question
before us leads, are in every respect useful; while the hypothetical history of
governments affords a lesson equally instructive to mankind.
In considering what we should have become, had we been left to ourselves, we should
learn to bless Him, whose gracious hand, correcting our institutions, and giving them
an immovable basis, has prevented those disorders which would otherwise have arisen
from them, and caused our happiness to come from those very sources which seemed
likely to involve us in misery.
Quem te deus esse
Jussit, et humanâ quâ parte locatus es in re,
Disce.
Persius, Satire iii, 71.
A DISSERTATION
On The Origin And Foundation Of The Inequality Of Mankind
It is of man that I have to speak; and the question I am investigating shows me that it
is to men that I must address myself: for questions of this sort are not asked by those
who are afraid to honour truth. I shall then confidently uphold the cause of humanity
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
162
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
before the wise men who invite me to do so, and shall not be dissatisfied if I acquit
myself in a manner worthy of my subject and of my judges.
I conceive that there are two kinds of inequality among the human species; one, which
I call natural or physical, because it is established by nature, and consists in a
difference of age, health, bodily strength, and the qualities of the mind or of the soul:
and another, which may be called moral or political inequality, because it depends on
a kind of convention, and is established, or at least authorised by the consent of men.
This latter consists of the different privileges, which some men enjoy to the prejudice
of others; such as that of being more rich, more honoured, more powerful or even in a
position to exact obedience.
It is useless to ask what is the source of natural inequality, because that question is
answered by the simple definition of the word. Again, it is still more useless to inquire
whether there is any essential connection between the two inequalities; for this would
be only asking, in other words, whether those who command are necessarily better
than those who obey, and if strength of body or of mind, wisdom or virtue are always
found in particular individuals, in proportion to their power or wealth: a question fit
perhaps to be discussed by slaves in the hearing of their masters, but highly
unbecoming to reasonable and free men in search of the truth.
The subject of the present discourse, therefore, is more precisely this. To mark, in the
progress of things, the moment at which right took the place of violence and nature
became subject to law, and to explain by what sequence of miracles the strong came
to submit to serve the weak, and the people to purchase imaginary repose at the
expense of real felicity.
The philosophers, who have inquired into the foundations of society, have all felt the
necessity of going back to a state of nature; but not one of them has got there. Some
of them have not hesitated to ascribe to man, in such a state, the idea of just and
unjust, without troubling themselves to show that he must be possessed of such an
idea, or that it could be of any use to him. Others have spoken of the natural right of
every man to keep what belongs to him, without explaining what they meant by
belongs. Others again, beginning by giving the strong authority over the weak,
proceeded directly to the birth of government, without regard to the time that must
have elapsed before the meaning of the words authority and government could have
existed among men. Every one of them, in short, constantly dwelling on wants,
avidity, oppression, desires and pride, has transferred to the state of nature ideas
which were acquired in society; so that, in speaking of the savage, they described the
social man. It has not even entered into the heads of most of our writers to doubt
whether the state of nature ever existed; but it is clear from the Holy Scriptures that
the first man, having received his understanding and commandments immediately
from God, was not himself in such a state; and that, if we give such credit to the
writings of Moses as every Christian philosopher ought to give, we must deny that,
even before the deluge, men were ever in the pure state of nature; unless, indeed, they
fell back into it from some very extraordinary circumstance; a paradox which it would
be very embarrassing to defend, and quite impossible to prove.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
163
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Let us begin then by laying facts aside, as they do not affect the question. The
investigations we may enter into, in treating this subject, must not be considered as
historical truths, but only as mere conditional and hypothetical reasonings, rather
calculated to explain the nature of things, than to ascertain their actual origin; just like
the hypotheses which our physicists daily form respecting the formation of the world.
Religion commands us to believe that, God Himself having taken men out of a state of
nature immediately after the creation, they are unequal only because it is His will they
should be so: but it does not forbid us to form conjectures based solely on the nature
of man, and the beings around him, concerning what might have become of the
human race, if it had been left to itself. This then is the question asked me, and that
which I propose to discuss in the following discourse. As my subject interests
mankind in general, I shall endeavour to make use of a style adapted to all nations, or
rather, forgetting time and place, to attend only to men to whom I am speaking. I shall
suppose myself in the Lyceum of Athens, repeating the lessons of my masters, with
Plato and Xenocrates for judges, and the whole human race for audience.
O man, of whatever country you are, and whatever your opinions may be, behold your
history, such as I have thought to read it, not in books written by your fellow-
creatures, who are liars, but in nature, which never lies. All that comes from her will
be true; nor will you meet with anything false, unless I have involuntarily put in
something of my own. The times of which I am going to speak are very remote: how
much are you changed from what you once were! It is, so to speak, the life of your
species which I am going to write, after the qualities which you have received, which
your education and habits may have depraved, but cannot have entirely destroyed.
There is, I feel, an age at which the individual man would wish to stop: you are about
to inquire about the age at which you would have liked your whole species to stand
still. Discontented with your present state, for reasons which threaten your
unfortunate descendants with still greater discontent, you will perhaps wish it were in
your power to go back; and this feeling should be a panegyric on your first ancestors,
a criticism of your contemporaries, and a terror to the unfortunates who will come
after you.
THE FIRST PART
Important as it may be, in order to judge rightly of the natural state of man, to
consider him from his origin, and to examine him, as it were, in the embryo of his
species; I shall not follow his organisation through its successive developments, nor
shall I stay to inquire what his animal system must have been at the beginning, in
order to become at length what it actually is. I shall not ask whether his long nails
were at first, as Aristotle supposes, only crooked talons; whether his whole body, like
that of a bear, was not covered with hair; or whether the fact that he walked upon all
fours, with his looks directed toward the earth, confined to a horizon of a few paces,
did not at once point out the nature and limits of his ideas. On this subject I could
form none but vague and almost imaginary conjectures. Comparative anatomy has as
yet made too little progress, and the observations of naturalists are too uncertain, to
afford an adequate basis for any solid reasoning. So that, without having recourse to
the supernatural information given us on this head, or paying any regard to the
changes which must have taken place in the internal, as well as the external,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
164
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
conformation of man, as he applied his limbs to new uses, and fed himself on new
kinds of food, I shall suppose his conformation to have been at all times what it
appears to us at this day; that he always walked on two legs, made use of his hands as
we do, directed his looks over all nature, and measured with his eyes the vast expanse
of Heaven.
If we strip this being, thus constituted, of all the supernatural gifts he may have
received, and all the artificial faculties he can have acquired only by a long process; if
we consider him, in a word, just as he must have come from the hands of nature, we
behold in him an animal weaker than some, and less agile than others; but, taking him
all round, the most advantageously organised of any. I see him satisfying his hunger at
the first oak, and slaking his thirst at the first brook; finding his bed at the foot of the
tree which afforded him a repast; and, with that, all his wants supplied.
While the earth was left to its natural fertility and covered with immense forests,
whose trees were never mutilated by the axe, it would present on every side both
sustenance and shelter for every species of animal. Men, dispersed up and down
among the rest, would observe and imitate their industry, and thus attain even to the
instinct of the beasts, with the advantage that, whereas every species of brutes was
confined to one particular instinct, man, who perhaps has not any one peculiar to
himself, would appropriate them all, and live upon most of those different foods,
which other animals shared among themselves; and thus would find his subsistence
much more easily than any of the rest.
Accustomed from their infancy to the inclemencies of the weather and the rigour of
the seasons, inured to fatigue, and forced, naked and unarmed, to defend themselves
and their prey from other ferocious animals, or to escape them by flight, men would
acquire a robust and almost unalterable constitution. The children, bringing with them
into the world the excellent constitution of their parents, and fortifying it by the very
exercises which first produced it, would thus acquire all the vigour of which the
human frame is capable. Nature in this case treats them exactly as Sparta treated the
children of her citizens: those who come well formed into the world she renders
strong and robust, and all the rest she destroys; differing in this respect from our
modern communities, in which the State, by making children a burden to their
parents, kills them indiscriminately before they are born.
The body of a savage man being the only instrument he understands, he uses it for
various purposes, of which ours, for want of practice, are incapable: for our industry
deprives us of that force and agility, which necessity obliges him to acquire. If he had
had an axe, would he have been able with his naked arm to break so large a branch
from a tree? If he had had a sling, would he have been able to throw a stone with so
great velocity? If he had had a ladder, would he have been so nimble in climbing a
tree? If he had had a horse, would he have been himself so swift of foot? Give
civilised man time to gather all his machines about him, and he will no doubt easily
beat the savage; but if you would see a still more unequal contest, set them together
naked and unarmed, and you will soon see the advantage of having all our forces
constantly at our disposal, of being always prepared for every event, and of carrying
one’s self, as it were, perpetually whole and entire about one.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
165
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Hobbes contends that man is naturally intrepid, and is intent only upon attacking and
fighting. Another illustrious philosopher holds the opposite, and Cumberland and
Puffendorf also affirm that nothing is more timid and fearful than man in the state of
nature; that he is always in a tremble, and ready to fly at the least noise or the slightest
movement. This may be true of things he does not know; and I do not doubt his being
terrified by every novelty that presents itself, when he neither knows the physical
good or evil he may expect from it, nor can make a comparison between his own
strength and the dangers he is about to encounter. Such circumstances, however,
rarely occur in a state of nature, in which all things proceed in a uniform manner, and
the face of the earth is not subject to those sudden and continual changes which arise
from the passions and caprices of bodies of men living together. But savage man,
living dispersed among other animals, and finding himself betimes in a situation to
measure his strength with theirs, soon comes to compare himself with them; and,
perceiving that he surpasses them more in adroitness than they surpass him in
strength, learns to be no longer afraid of them. Set a bear, or a wolf, against a robust,
agile, and resolute savage, as they all are, armed with stones and a good cudgel, and
you will see that the danger will be at least on both sides, and that, after a few trials of
this kind, wild beasts, which are not fond of attacking each other, will not be at all
ready to attack man, whom they will have found to be as wild and ferocious as
themselves. With regard to such animals as have really more strength than man has
adroitness, he is in the same situation as all weaker animals, which notwithstanding
are still able to subsist; except indeed that he has the advantage that, being equally
swift of foot, and finding an almost certain place of refuge in every tree, he is at
liberty to take or leave it at every encounter, and thus to fight or fly, as he chooses.
Add to this that it does not appear that any animal naturally makes war on man,
except in case of self-defence or excessive hunger, or betrays any of those violent
antipathies, which seem to indicate that one species is intended by nature for the food
of another.
This is doubtless why negroes and savages are so little afraid of the wild beasts they
may meet in the woods. The Caraibs of Venezuela among others live in this respect in
absolute security and without the smallest inconvenience. Though they are almost
naked, Francis Corréal tells us, they expose themselves freely in the woods, armed
only with bows and arrows; but no one has ever heard of one of them being devoured
by wild beasts.
But man has other enemies more formidable, against which he is not provided with
such means of defence: these are the natural infirmities of infancy, old age, and illness
of every kind, melancholy proofs of our weakness, of which the two first are common
to all animals, and the last belongs chiefly to man in a state of society. With regard to
infancy, it is observable that the mother, carrying her child always with her, can nurse
it with much greater ease than the females of many other animals, which are forced to
be perpetually going and coming, with great fatigue, one way to find subsistence, and
another to suckle or feed their young. It is true that if the woman happens to perish,
the infant is in great danger of perishing with her; but this risk is common to many
other species of animals, whose young take a long time before they are able to provide
for themselves. And if our infancy is longer than theirs, our lives are longer in
proportion; so that all things are in this respect fairly equal; though there are other
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
166
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
rules to be considered regarding the duration of the first period of life, and the number
of young, which do not affect the present subject. In old age, when men are less active
and perspire little, the need for food diminishes with the ability to provide it. As the
savage state also protects them from gout and rheumatism, and old age is, of all ills,
that which human aid can least alleviate, they cease to be, without others perceiving
that they are no more, and almost without perceiving it themselves.
With respect to sickness, I shall not repeat the vain and false declamations which most
healthy people pronounce against medicine; but I shall ask if any solid observations
have been made from which it may be justly concluded that, in the countries where
the art of medicine is most neglected, the mean duration of man’s life is less than in
those where it is most cultivated. How indeed can this be the case, if we bring on
ourselves more diseases than medicine can furnish remedies? The great inequality in
manner of living, the extreme idleness of some, and the excessive labour of others, the
easiness of exciting and gratifying our sensual appetites, the too exquisite foods of the
wealthy which overheat and fill them with indigestion, and, on the other hand, the
unwholesome food of the poor, often, bad as it is, insufficient for their needs, which
induces them, when opportunity offers, to eat voraciously and overcharge their
stomachs; all these, together with sitting up late, and excesses of every kind,
immoderate transports of every passion, fatigue, mental exhaustion, the innumerable
pains and anxieties inseparable from every condition of life, by which the mind of
man is incessantly tormented; these are too fatal proofs that the greater part of our ills
are of our own making, and that we might have avoided them nearly all by adhering
to that simple, uniform and solitary manner of life which nature prescribed. If she
destined man to be healthy, I venture to declare that a state of reflection is a state
contrary to nature, and that a thinking man is a depraved animal. When we think of
the good constitution of the savages, at least of those whom we have not ruined with
our spirituous liquors, and reflect that they are troubled with hardly any disorders,
save wounds and old age, we are tempted to believe that, in following the history of
civil society, we shall be telling also that of human sickness. Such, at least, was the
opinion of Plato, who inferred from certain remedies prescribed, or approved, by
Podalirius and Machaon at the siege of Troy, that several sicknesses which these
remedies gave rise to in his time, were not then known to mankind: and Celsus tells us
that diet, which is now so necessary, was first invented by Hippocrates.
Being subject therefore to so few causes of sickness, man, in the state of nature, can
have no need of remedies, and still less of physicians: nor is the human race in this
respect worse off than other animals, and it is easy to learn from hunters whether they
meet with many infirm animals in the course of the chase. It is certain they frequently
meet with such as carry the marks of having been considerably wounded, with many
that have had bones or even limbs broken, yet have been healed without any other
surgical assistance than that of time, or any other regimen than that of their ordinary
life. At the same time their cures seem not to have been less perfect, for their not
having been tortured by incisions, poisoned with drugs, or wasted by fasting. In short,
however useful medicine, properly administered, may be among us, it is certain that,
if the savage, when he is sick and left to himself, has nothing to hope but from nature,
he has, on the other hand, nothing to fear but from his disease; which renders his
situation often preferable to our own.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
167
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
We should beware, therefore, of confounding the savage man with the men we have
daily before our eyes. Nature treats all the animals left to her care with a predilection
that seems to show how jealous she is of that right. The horse, the cat, the bull, and
even the ass are generally of greater stature, and always more robust, and have more
vigour, strength and courage, when they run wild in the forests than when bred in the
stall. By becoming domesticated, they lose half these advantages; and it seems as if all
our care to feed and treat them well serves only to deprave them. It is thus with man
also: as he becomes sociable and a slave, he grows weak, timid and servile; his
effeminate way of life totally enervates his strength and courage. To this it may be
added that there is still a greater difference between savage and civilised man, than
between wild and tame beasts: for men and brutes having been treated alike by nature,
the several conveniences in which men indulge themselves still more than they do
their beasts, are so many additional causes of their deeper degeneracy.
It is not therefore so great a misfortune to these primitive men, nor so great an
obstacle to their preservation, that they go naked, have no dwellings and lack all the
superfluities which we think so necessary. If their skins are not covered with hair,
they have no need of such covering in warm climates; and, in cold countries, they
soon learn to appropriate the skins of the beasts they have overcome. If they have but
two legs to run with, they have two arms to defend themselves with, and provide for
their wants. Their children are slowly and with difficulty taught to walk; but their
mothers are able to carry them with ease; an advantage which other animals lack, as
the mother, if pursued, is forced either to abandon her young, or to regulate her pace
by theirs. Unless, in short, we suppose a singular and fortuitous concurrence of
circumstances of which I shall speak later, and which would be unlikely to exist, it is
plain in every state of the case, that the man who first made himself clothes or a
dwelling was furnishing himself with things not at all necessary; for he had till then
done without them, and there is no reason why he should not have been able to put up
in manhood with the same kind of life as had been his in infancy.
Solitary, indolent, and perpetually accompanied by danger, the savage cannot but be
fond of sleep; his sleep too must be light, like that of the animals, which think but
little and may be said to slumber all the time they do not think. Self-preservation
being his chief and almost sole concern, he must exercise most those faculties which
are most concerned with attack or defence, either for overcoming his prey, or for
preventing him from becoming the prey of other animals. On the other hand, those
organs which are perfected only by softness and sensuality will remain in a gross and
imperfect state, incompatible with any sort of delicacy; so that, his senses being
divided on this head, his touch and taste will be extremely coarse, his sight, hearing
and smell exceedingly fine and subtle. Such in general is the animal condition, and
such, according to the narratives of travellers, is that of most savage nations. It is
therefore no matter for surprise that the Hottentots of the Cape of Good Hope
distinguish ships at sea, with the naked eye, at as great a distance as the Dutch can do
with their telescopes; or that the savages of America should trace the Spaniards, by
their smell, as well as the best dogs could have done; or that these barbarous peoples
feel no pain in going naked, or that they use large quantities of piemento with their
food, and drink the strongest European liquors like water.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
168
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Hitherto I have considered merely the physical man; let us now take a view of him on
his metaphysical and moral side.
I see nothing in any animal but an ingenious machine, to which nature hath given
senses to wind itself up, and to guard itself, to a certain degree, against anything that
might tend to disorder or destroy it. I perceive exactly the same things in the human
machine, with this difference, that in the operations of the brute, nature is the sole
agent, whereas man has some share in his own operations, in his character as a free
agent. The one chooses and refuses by instinct, the other from an act of free-will:
hence the brute cannot deviate from the rule prescribed to it, even when it would be
advantageous for it to do so; and, on the contrary, man frequently deviates from such
rules to his own prejudice. Thus a pigeon would be starved to death by the side of a
dish of the choicest meats, and a cat on a heap of fruit or grain; though it is certain
that either might find nourishment in the foods which it thus rejects with disdain, did
it think of trying them. Hence it is that dissolute men run into excesses which bring on
fevers and death; because the mind depraves the senses, and the will continues to
speak when nature is silent.
Every animal has ideas, since it has senses; it even combines those ideas in a certain
degree; and it is only in degree that man differs, in this respect, from the brute. Some
philosophers have even maintained that there is a greater difference between one man
and another than between some men and some beasts. It is not, therefore, so much the
understanding that constitutes the specific difference between the man and the brute,
as the human quality of free-agency. Nature lays her commands on every animal, and
the brute obeys her voice. Man receives the same impulsion, but at the same time
knows himself at liberty to acquiesce or resist: and it is particularly in his
consciousness of this liberty that the spirituality of his soul is displayed. For physics
may explain, in some measure, the mechanism of the senses and the formation of
ideas; but in the power of willing or rather of choosing, and in the feeling of this
power, nothing is to be found but acts which are purely spiritual and wholly
inexplicable by the laws of mechanism.
However, even if the difficulties attending all these questions should still leave room
for difference in this respect between men and brutes, there is another very specific
quality which distinguishes them, and which will admit of no dispute. This is the
faculty of self-improvement, which, by the help of circumstances, gradually develops
all the rest of our faculties, and is inherent in the species as in the individual: whereas
a brute is, at the end of a few months, all he will ever be during his whole life, and his
species, at the end of a thousand years, exactly what it was the first year of that
thousand. Why is man alone liable to grow into a dotard? Is it not because he returns,
in this, to his primitive state; and that, while the brute, which has acquired nothing and
has therefore nothing to lose, still retains the force of instinct, man, who loses, by age
or accident, all that his perfectibility had enabled him to gain, falls by this means
lower than the brutes themselves? It would be melancholy, were we forced to admit
that this distinctive and almost unlimited faculty is the source of all human
misfortunes; that it is this which, in time, draws man out of his original state, in which
he would have spent his days insensibly in peace and innocence; that it is this faculty,
which, successively producing in different ages his discoveries and his errors, his
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
169
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
vices and his virtues, makes him at length a tyrant both over himself and over nature.1
It would be shocking to be obliged to regard as a benefactor the man who first
suggested to the Oroonoko Indians the use of the boards they apply to the temples of
their children, which secure to them some part at least of their imbecility and original
happiness.
Savage man, left by nature solely to the direction of instinct, or rather indemnified for
what he may lack by faculties capable at first of supplying its place, and afterwards of
raising him much above it, must accordingly begin with purely animal functions: thus
seeing and feeling must be his first condition, which would be common to him and all
other animals. To will, and not to will, to desire and to fear, must be the first, and
almost the only operations of his soul, till new circumstances occasion new
developments of his faculties.
Whatever moralists may hold, the human understanding is greatly indebted to the
passions, which, it is universally allowed, are also much indebted to the
understanding. It is by the activity of the passions that our reason is improved; for we
desire knowledge only because we wish to enjoy; and it is impossible to conceive any
reason why a person who has neither fears nor desires should give himself the trouble
of reasoning. The passions, again, originate in our wants, and their progress depends
on that of our knowledge; for we cannot desire or fear anything, except from the idea
we have of it, or from the simple impulse of nature. Now savage man, being destitute
of every species of intelligence, can have no passions save those of the latter kind: his
desires never go beyond his physical wants. The only goods he recognises in the
universe are food, a female, and sleep: the only evils he fears are pain and hunger. I
say pain, and not death: for no animal can know what it is to die; the knowledge of
death and its terrors being one of the first acquisitions made by man in departing from
an animal state.
It would be easy, were it necessary, to support this opinion by facts, and to show that,
in all the nations of the world, the progress of the understanding has been exactly
proportionate to the wants which the peoples had received from nature, or been
subjected to by circumstances, and in consequence to the passions that induced them
to provide for those necessities. I might instance the arts, rising up in Egypt and
expanding with the inundation of the Nile. I might follow their progress into Greece,
where they took root afresh, grew up and towered to the skies, among the rocks and
sands of Attica, without being able to germinate on the fertile banks of the Eurotas: I
might observe that in general, the people of the North are more industrious than those
of the South, because they cannot get on so well without being so: as if nature wanted
to equalise matters by giving their understandings the fertility she had refused to their
soil.
But who does not see, without recurring to the uncertain testimony of history, that
everything seems to remove from savage man both the temptation and the means of
changing his condition? His imagination paints no pictures; his heart makes no
demands on him. His few wants are so readily supplied, and he is so far from having
the knowledge which is needful to make him want more, that he can have neither
foresight nor curiosity. The face of nature becomes indifferent to him as it grows
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
170
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
familiar. He sees in it always the same order, the same successions: he has not
understanding enough to wonder at the greatest miracles; nor is it in his mind that we
can expect to find that philosophy man needs, if he is to know how to notice for once
what he sees every day. His soul, which nothing disturbs, is wholly wrapped up in the
feeling of its present existence, without any idea of the future, however near at hand;
while his projects, as limited as his views, hardly extend to the close of day. Such,
even at present, is the extent of the native Caribean’s foresight: he will improvidently
sell you his cotton-bed in the morning, and come crying in the evening to buy it again,
not having foreseen he would want it again the next night.
The more we reflect on this subject, the greater appears the distance between pure
sensation and the most simple knowledge: it is impossible indeed to conceive how a
man, by his own powers alone, without the aid of communication and the spur of
necessity, could have bridged so great a gap. How many ages may have elapsed
before mankind were in a position to behold any other fire than that of the heavens.
What a multiplicity of chances must have happened to teach them the commonest
uses of that element! How often must they have let it out before they acquired the art
of reproducing it? and how often may not such a secret have died with him who had
discovered it? What shall we say of agriculture, an art which requires so much labour
and foresight, which is so dependent on others that it is plain it could only be
practised in a society which had at least begun, and which does not serve so much to
draw the means of subsistence from the earth—for these it would produce of
itself—but to compel it to produce what is most to our taste? But let us suppose that
men had so multiplied that the natural produce of the earth was no longer sufficient
for their support; a supposition, by the way, which would prove such a life to be very
advantageous for the human race; let us suppose that, without forges or workshops,
the instruments of husbandry had dropped from the sky into the hands of savages; that
they had overcome their natural aversion to continual labour; that they had learnt so
much foresight for their needs; that they had divined how to cultivate the earth, to sow
grain and plant trees; that they had discovered the arts of grinding corn, and of setting
the grape to ferment—all being things that must have been taught them by the gods,
since it is not to be conceived how they could discover them for themselves—yet after
all this, what man among them would be so absurd as to take the trouble of cultivating
a field, which might be stripped of its crop by the first comer, man or beast, that might
take a liking to it; and how should each of them resolve to pass his life in wearisome
labour, when, the more necessary to him the reward of his labour might be, the surer
he would be of not getting it? In a word, how could such a situation induce men to
cultivate the earth, till it was regularly parcelled out among them; that is to say, till the
state of nature had been abolished?
Were we to suppose savage man as trained in the art of thinking as philosophers make
him; were we, like them, to suppose him a very philosopher capable of investigating
the sublimest truths, and of forming, by highly abstract chains of reasoning, maxims
of reason and justice, deduced from the love of order in general, or the known will of
his Creator; in a word, were we to suppose him as intelligent and enlightened, as he
must have been, and is in fact found to have been, dull and stupid, what advantage
would accrue to the species, from all such metaphysics, which could not be
communicated by one to another, but must end with him who made them? What
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
171
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
progress could be made by mankind, while dispersed in the woods among other
animals? and how far could men improve or mutually enlighten one another, when,
having no fixed habitation, and no need of one another’s assistance, the same persons
hardly met twice in their lives, and perhaps then, without knowing one another or
speaking together?
Let it be considered how many ideas we owe to the use of speech; how far grammar
exercises the understanding and facilitates its operations. Let us reflect on the
inconceivable pains and the infinite space of time that the first invention of languages
must have cost. To these reflections add what preceded, and then judge how many
thousand ages must have elapsed in the successive development in the human mind of
those operations of which it is capable.
I shall here take the liberty for a moment, of considering the difficulties of the origin
of languages, on which subject I might content myself with a simple repetition of the
Abbé Condillac’s investigations, as they fully confirm my system, and perhaps even
first suggested it. But it is plain, from the manner in which this philosopher solves the
difficulties he himself raises, concerning the origin of arbitrary signs, that he assumes
what I question, viz. that a kind of society must already have existed among the first
inventors of language. While I refer, therefore, to his observations on this head, I
think it right to give my own, in order to exhibit the same difficulties in a light
adapted to my subject. The first which presents itself is to conceive how language can
have become necessary; for as there was no communication among men and no need
for any, we can neither conceive the necessity of this invention, nor the possibility of
it, if it was not somehow indispensable. I might affirm, with many others, that
languages arose in the domestic intercourse between parents and their children. But
this expedient would not obviate the difficulty, and would besides involve the blunder
made by those who, in reasoning on the state of nature, always import into it ideas
gathered in a state of society. Thus they constantly consider families as living together
under one roof, and the individuals of each as observing among themselves a union as
intimate and permanent as that which exists among us, where so many common
interests unite them: whereas, in this primitive state, men had neither houses, nor huts,
nor any kind of property whatever; every one lived where he could, seldom for more
than a single night; the sexes united without design, as accident, opportunity or
inclination brought them together, nor had they any great need of words to
communicate their designs to each other; and they parted with the same indifference.
The mother gave suck to her children at first for her own sake; and afterwards, when
habit had made them dear, for theirs: but as soon as they were strong enough to go in
search of their own food, they forsook her of their own accord; and, as they had
hardly any other method of not losing one another than that of remaining continually
within sight, they soon became quite incapable of recognising one another when they
happened to meet again. It is farther to be observed that the child, having all his wants
to explain, and of course more to say to his mother than the mother could have to say
to him, must have borne the brunt of the task of invention, and the language he used
would be of his own device, so that the number of languages would be equal to that of
the individuals speaking them, and the variety would be increased by the vagabond
and roving life they led, which would not give time for any idiom to become constant.
For to say that the mother dictated to her child the words he was to use in asking her
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
172
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
for one thing or another, is an explanation of how languages already formed are
taught, but by no means explains how languages were originally formed.
We will suppose, however, that this first difficulty is obviated. Let us for a moment
then take ourselves as being on this side of the vast space which must lie between a
pure state of nature and that in which languages had become necessary, and, admitting
their necessity, let us inquire how they could first be established. Here we have a new
and worse difficulty to grapple with; for if men need speech to learn to think, they
must have stood in much greater need of the art of thinking, to be able to invent that
of speaking. And though we might conceive how the articulate sounds of the voice
came to be taken as the conventional interpreters of our ideas, it would still remain for
us to inquire what could have been the interpreters of this convention for those ideas,
which, answering to no sensible objects, could not be indicated either by gesture or
voice; so that we can hardly form any tolerable conjectures about the origin of this art
of communicating our thoughts and establishing a correspondence between minds: an
art so sublime, that far distant as it is from its origin, philosophers still behold it at
such an immeasurable distance from perfection, that there is none rash enough to
affirm it will ever reach it, even though the revolutions time necessarily produces
were suspended in its favour, though prejudice should be banished from our
academies or condemned to silence, and those learned societies should devote
themselves uninterruptedly for whole ages to this thorny question.
The first language of mankind, the most universal and vivid, in a word the only
language man needed, before he had occasion to exert his eloquence to persuade
assembled multitudes, was the simple cry of nature. But as this was excited only by a
sort of instinct on urgent occasions, to implore assistance in case of danger, or relief
in case of suffering, it could be of little use in the ordinary course of life, in which
more moderate feelings prevail. When the ideas of men began to expand and multiply,
and closer communication took place among them, they strove to invent more
numerous signs and a more copious language. They multiplied the inflections of the
voice, and added gestures, which are in their own nature more expressive, and depend
less for their meaning on a prior determination. Visible and movable objects were
therefore expressed by gestures, and audible ones by imitative sounds: but, as hardly
anything can be indicated by gestures, except objects actually present or easily
described, and visible actions; as they are not universally useful—for darkness or the
interposition of a material object destroys their efficacy—and as besides they rather
request than secure our attention; men at length bethought themselves of substituting
for them the articulate sounds of the voice, which, without bearing the same relation
to any particular ideas, are better calculated to express them all, as conventional signs.
Such an institution could only be made by common consent, and must have been
effected in a manner not very easy for men whose gross organs had not been
accustomed to any such exercise. It is also in itself still more difficult to conceive,
since such a common agreement must have had motives, and speech seems to have
been highly necessary to establish the use of it.
It is reasonable to suppose that the words first made use of by mankind had a much
more extensive signification than those used in languages already formed, and that
ignorant as they were of the division of discourse into its constituent parts, they at first
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
173
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
gave every single word the sense of a whole proposition. When they began to
distinguish subject and attribute, and noun and verb, which was itself no common
effort of genius, substantives were at first only so many proper names; the present
infinitive was the only tense of verbs; and the very idea of adjectives must have been
developed with great difficulty; for every adjective is an abstract idea, and
abstractions are painful and unnatural operations.
Every object at first received a particular name without regard to genus or species,
which these primitive originators were not in a position to distinguish; every
individual presented itself to their minds in isolation, as they are in the picture of
nature. If one oak was called A, another was called B; for the primitive idea of two
things is that they are not the same, and it often takes a long time for what they have
in common to be seen: so that, the narrower the limits of their knowledge of things,
the more copious their dictionary must have been. The difficulty of using such a
vocabulary could not be easily removed; for, to arrange beings under common and
generic denominations, it became necessary to know their distinguishing properties:
the need arose for observation and definition, that is to say, for natural history and
metaphysics of a far more developed kind than men can at that time have possessed.
Add to this, that general ideas cannot be introduced into the mind without the
assistance of words, nor can the understanding seize them except by means of
propositions. This is one of the reasons why animals cannot form such ideas, or ever
acquire that capacity for self-improvement which depends on them. When a monkey
goes from one nut to another, are we to conceive that he entertains any general idea of
that kind of fruit, and compares its archetype with the two individual nuts? Assuredly
he does not; but the sight of one of these nuts recalls to his memory the sensations
which he received from the other, and his eyes, being modified after a certain manner,
give information to the palate of the modification it is about to receive. Every general
idea is purely intellectual; if the imagination meddles with it ever so little, the idea
immediately becomes particular. If you endeavour to trace in your mind the image of
a tree in general, you never attain to your end. In spite of all you can do, you will have
to see it as great or little, bare or leafy, light or dark, and were you capable of seeing
nothing in it but what is common to all trees, it would no longer be like a tree at all.
Purely abstract beings are perceivable in the same manner, or are only conceivable by
the help of language. The definition of a triangle alone gives you a true idea of it: the
moment you imagine a triangle in your mind, it is some particular triangle and not
another, and you cannot avoid giving it sensible lines and a coloured area. We must
then make use of propositions and of language in order to form general ideas. For no
sooner does the imagination cease to operate than the understanding proceeds only by
the help of words. If then the first inventors of speech could give names only to ideas
they already had, it follows that the first substantives could be nothing more than
proper names.
But when our new grammarians, by means of which I have no conception, began to
extend their ideas and generalise their terms, the ignorance of the inventors must have
confined this method within very narrow limits; and, as they had at first gone too far
in multiplying the names of individuals, from ignorance of their genus and species,
they made afterwards too few of these, from not having considered beings in all their
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
174
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
specific differences. It would indeed have needed more knowledge and experience
than they could have, and more pains and inquiry than they would have bestowed, to
carry these distinctions to their proper length. If, even to-day, we are continually
discovering new species, which have hitherto escaped observation, let us reflect how
many of them must have escaped men who judged things merely from their first
appearance! It is superfluous to add that the primitive classes and the most general
notions must necessarily have escaped their notice also. How, for instance, could they
have understood or thought of the words matter, spirit, substance, mode, figure,
motion, when even our philosophers, who have so long been making use of them,
have themselves the greatest difficulty in understanding them; and when, the ideas
attached to them being purely metaphysical, there are no models of them to be found
in nature?
But I stop at this point, and ask my judges to suspend their reading a while, to
consider, after the invention of physical substantives, which is the easiest part of
language to invent, that there is still a great way to go, before the thoughts of men will
have found perfect expression and constant form, such as would answer the purposes
of public speaking, and produce their effect on society. I beg of them to consider how
much time must have been spent, and how much knowledge needed, to find out
numbers, abstract terms, aorists and all the tenses of verbs, particles, syntax, the
method of connecting propositions, the forms of reasoning, and all the logic of
speech. For myself, I am so aghast at the increasing difficulties which present
themselves, and so well convinced of the almost demonstrable impossibility that
languages should owe their original institution to merely human means, that I leave,
to any one who will undertake it, the discussion of the difficult problem, which was
most necessary, the existence of society to the invention of language, or the invention
of language to the establishment of society. But be the origin of language and society
what they may, it may be at least inferred, from the little care which nature has taken
to unite mankind by mutual wants, and to facilitate the use of speech, that she has
contributed little to make them sociable, and has put little of her own into all they
have done to create such bonds of union. It is in fact impossible to conceive why, in a
state of nature, one man should stand more in need of the assistance of another, than a
monkey or a wolf of the assistance of another of its kind: or, granting that he did,
what motives could induce that other to assist him; or, even then, by what means they
could agree about the conditions. I know it is incessantly repeated that man would in
such a state have been the most miserable of creatures; and indeed, if it be true, as I
think I have proved, that he must have lived many ages, before he could have either
desire or an opportunity of emerging from it, this would only be an accusation against
nature, and not against the being which she had thus unhappily constituted. But as I
understand the word miserable, it either has no meaning at all, or else signifies only a
painful privation of something, or a state of suffering either in body or soul. I should
be glad to have explained to me, what kind of misery a free being, whose heart is at
ease and whose body is in health, can possibly suffer. I would ask also, whether a
social or a natural life is most likely to become insupportable to those who enjoy it.
We see around us hardly a creature in civil society, who does not lament his
existence: we even see many deprive themselves of as much of it as they can, and
laws human and divine together can hardly put a stop to the disorder. I ask, if it was
ever known that a savage took it into his head, when at liberty, to complain of life or
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
175
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
to make away with himself. Let us therefore judge, with less vanity, on which side the
real misery is found. On the other hand, nothing could be more unhappy than savage
man, dazzled by science, tormented by his passions, and reasoning about a state
different from his own. It appears that Providence most wisely determined that the
faculties, which he potentially possessed, should develop themselves only as occasion
offered to exercise them, in order that they might not be superfluous or perplexing to
him, by appearing before their time, nor slow and useless when the need for them
arose. In instinct alone, he had all he required for living in the state of nature; and
with a developed understanding he has only just enough to support life in society.
It appears, at first view, that men in a state of nature, having no moral relations or
determinate obligations one with another, could not be either good or bad, virtuous or
vicious; unless we take these terms in a physical sense, and call, in an individual,
those qualities vices which may be injurious to his preservation, and those virtues
which contribute to it; in which case, he would have to be accounted most virtuous,
who put least check on the pure impulses of nature. But without deviating from the
ordinary sense of the words, it will be proper to suspend the judgment we might be
led to form on such a state, and be on our guard against our prejudices, till we have
weighed the matter in the scales of impartiality, and seen whether virtues or vices
preponderate among civilised men; and whether their virtues do them more good than
their vices do harm; till we have discovered, whether the progress of the sciences
sufficiently indemnifies them for the mischiefs they do one another, in proportion as
they are better informed of the good they ought to do; or whether they would not be,
on the whole, in a much happier condition if they had nothing to fear or to hope from
any one, than as they are, subjected to universal dependence, and obliged to take
everything from those who engage to give them nothing in return.
Above all, let us not conclude, with Hobbes, that because man has no idea of
goodness, he must be naturally wicked; that he is vicious because he does not know
virtue; that he always refuses to do his fellow-creatures services which he does not
think they have a right to demand; or that by virtue of the right he truly claims to
everything he needs, he foolishly imagines himself the sole proprietor of the whole
universe. Hobbes had seen clearly the defects of all the modern definitions of natural
right: but the consequences which he deduces from his own show that he understands
it in an equally false sense. In reasoning on the principles he lays down, he ought to
have said that the state of nature, being that in which the care for our own
preservation is the least prejudicial to that of others, was consequently the best
calculated to promote peace, and the most suitable for mankind. He does say the exact
opposite, in consequence of having improperly admitted, as a part of savage man’s
care for self-preservation, the gratification of a multitude of passions which are the
work of society, and have made laws necessary. A bad man, he says, is a robust child.
But it remains to be proved whether man in a state of nature is this robust child: and,
should we grant that he is, what would he infer? Why truly, that if this man, when
robust and strong, were dependent on others as he is when feeble, there is no
extravagance he would not be guilty of; that he would beat his mother when she was
too slow in giving him her breast; that he would strangle one of his younger brothers,
if he should be troublesome to him, or bite the arm of another, if he put him to any
inconvenience. But that man in the state of nature is both strong and dependent
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
176
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
involves two contrary suppositions. Man is weak when he is dependent, and is his
own master before he comes to be strong. Hobbes did not reflect that the same cause,
which prevents a savage from making use of his reason, as our jurists hold, prevents
him also from abusing his faculties, as Hobbes himself allows: so that it may be justly
said that savages are not bad merely because they do not know what it is to be good:
for it is neither the development of the understanding nor the restraint of law that
hinders them from doing ill; but the peacefulness of their passions, and their
ignorance of vice: tanto plus in illis proficit vitiorum ignoratio, quam in his cognitio
virtutis.1 There is another principle which has escaped Hobbes; which, having been
bestowed on mankind, to moderate, on certain occasions, the impetuosity of egoism,
or, before its birth, the desire of self-preservation, tempers the ardour with which he
pursues his own welfare, by an innate repugnance at seeing a fellow-creature suffer.2
I think I need not fear contradiction in holding man to be possessed of the only natural
virtue, which could not be denied him by the most violent detractor of human virtue. I
am speaking of compassion, which is a disposition suitable to creatures so weak and
subject to so many evils as we certainly are: by so much the more universal and useful
to mankind, as it comes before any kind of reflection; and at the same time so natural,
that the very brutes themselves sometimes give evident proofs of it. Not to mention
the tenderness of mothers for their offspring and the perils they encounter to save
them from danger, it is well known that horses show a reluctance to trample on living
bodies. One animal never passes by the dead body of another of its species: there are
even some which give their fellows a sort of burial; while the mournful lowings of the
cattle when they enter the slaughter-house show the impressions made on them by the
horrible spectacle which meets them. We find, with pleasure, the author of the Fable
of the Bees obliged to own that man is a compassionate and sensible being, and laying
aside his cold subtlety of style, in the example he gives, to present us with the pathetic
description of a man who, from a place of confinement, is compelled to behold a wild
beast tear a child from the arms of its mother, grinding its tender limbs with its
murderous teeth, and tearing its palpitating entrails with its claws. What horrid
agitation must not the eye-witness of such a scene experience, although he would not
be personally concerned! What anxiety would he not suffer at not being able to give
any assistance to the fainting mother and the dying infant!
Such is the pure emotion of nature, prior to all kinds of reflection! Such is the force of
natural compassion, which the greatest depravity of morals has as yet hardly been able
to destroy! for we daily find at our theatres men affected, nay shedding tears at the
sufferings of a wretch who, were he in the tyrant’s place, would probably even add to
the torments of his enemies; like the blood-thirsty Sulla, who was so sensitive to ills
he had not caused, or that Alexander of Pheros who did not dare to go and see any
tragedy acted, for fear of being seen weeping with Andromache and Priam, though he
could listen without emotion to the cries of all the citizens who were daily strangled at
his command.
Mollissima corda
Humano generi dare se natura fatetur,
Quæ lacrimas dedit.
Juvenal, Satire xv, 151.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
177
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
1
Mandeville well knew that, in spite of all their morality, men would have never been
better than monsters, had not nature bestowed on them a sense of compassion, to aid
their reason: but he did not see that from this quality alone flow all those social
virtues, of which he denied man the possession. But what is generosity, clemency or
humanity but compassion applied to the weak, to the guilty, or to mankind in general?
Even benevolence and friendship are, if we judge rightly, only the effects of
compassion, constantly set upon a particular object: for how is it different to wish that
another person may not suffer pain and uneasiness and to wish him happy? Were it
even true that pity is no more than a feeling, which puts us in the place of the sufferer,
a feeling, obscure yet lively in a savage, developed yet feeble in civilised man; this
truth would have no other consequence than to confirm my argument. Compassion
must, in fact, be the stronger, the more the animal beholding any kind of distress
identifies himself with the animal that suffers. Now, it is plain that such identification
must have been much more perfect in a state of nature than it is in a state of reason. It
is reason that engenders self-respect, and reflection that confirms it: it is reason which
turns man’s mind back upon itself, and divides him from everything that could disturb
or afflict him. It is philosophy that isolates him, and bids him say, at sight of the
misfortunes of others: “Perish if you will, I am secure.” Nothing but such general
evils as threaten the whole community can disturb the tranquil sleep of the
philosopher, or tear him from his bed. A murder may with impunity be committed
under his window; he has only to put his hands to his ears and argue a little with
himself, to prevent nature, which is shocked within him, from identifying itself with
the unfortunate sufferer. Uncivilised man has not this admirable talent; and for want
of reason and wisdom, is always foolishly ready to obey the first promptings of
humanity. It is the populace that flocks together at riots and street-brawls, while the
wise man prudently makes off. It is the mob and the market-women, who part the
combatants, and hinder gentle-folks from cutting one another’s throats.
It is then certain that compassion is a natural feeling, which, by moderating the
violence of love of self in each individual, contributes to the preservation of the whole
species. It is this compassion that hurries us without reflection to the relief of those
who are in distress: it is this which in a state of nature supplies the place of laws,
morals and virtues, with the advantage that none are tempted to disobey its gentle
voice: it is this which will always prevent a sturdy savage from robbing a weak child
or a feeble old man of the sustenance they may have with pain and difficulty acquired,
if he sees a possibility of providing for himself by other means: it is this which,
instead of inculcating that sublime maxim of rational justice, Do to others as you
would have them do unto you, inspires all men with that other maxim of natural
goodness, much less perfect indeed, but perhaps more useful; Do good to yourself
with as little evil as possible to others. In a word, it is rather in this natural feeling
than in any subtle arguments that we must look for the cause of that repugnance,
which every man would experience in doing evil, even independently of the maxims
of education. Although it might belong to Socrates and other minds of the like craft to
acquire virtue by reason, the human race would long since have ceased to be, had its
preservation depended only on the reasonings of the individuals composing it.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
178
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
With passions so little active, and so good a curb, men, being rather wild than wicked,
and more intent to guard themselves against the mischief that might be done them,
than to do mischief to others, were by no means subject to very perilous dissensions.
They maintained no kind of intercourse with one another, and were consequently
strangers to vanity, deference, esteem and contempt; they had not the least idea of
meum and tuum, and no true conception of justice; they looked upon every violence to
which they were subjected, rather as an injury that might easily be repaired than as a
crime that ought to be punished; and they never thought of taking revenge, unless
perhaps mechanically and on the spot, as a dog will sometimes bite the stone which is
thrown at him. Their quarrels therefore would seldom have very bloody
consequences; for the subject of them would be merely the question of subsistence.
But I am aware of one greater danger, which remains to be noticed.
Of the passions that stir the heart of man, there is one which makes the sexes
necessary to each other, and is extremely ardent and impetuous; a terrible passion that
braves danger, surmounts all obstacles, and in its transports seems calculated to bring
destruction on the human race which it is really destined to preserve. What must
become of men who are left to this brutal and boundless rage, without modesty,
without shame, and daily upholding their amours at the price of their blood?
It must, in the first place, be allowed that, the more violent the passions are, the more
are laws necessary to keep them under restraint. But, setting aside the inadequacy of
laws to effect this purpose, which is evident from the crimes and disorders to which
these passions daily give rise among us, we should do well to inquire if these evils did
not spring up with the laws themselves; for in this case, even if the laws were capable
of repressing such evils, it is the least that could be expected from them, that they
should check a mischief which would not have arisen without them.
Let us begin by distinguishing between the physical and moral ingredients in the
feeling of love. The physical part of love is that general desire which urges the sexes
to union with each other. The moral part is that which determines and fixes this desire
exclusively upon one particular object; or at least gives it a greater degree of energy
toward the object thus preferred. It is easy to see that the moral part of love is a
factitious feeling, born of social usage, and enhanced by the women with much care
and cleverness, to establish their empire, and put in power the sex which ought to
obey. This feeling, being founded on certain ideas of beauty and merit which a savage
is not in a position to acquire, and on comparisons which he is incapable of making,
must be for him almost non-existent; for, as his mind cannot form abstract ideas of
proportion and regularity, so his heart is not susceptible of the feelings of love and
admiration, which are even insensibly produced by the application of these ideas. He
follows solely the character nature has implanted in him, and not tastes which he
could never have acquired; so that every woman equally answers his purpose.
Men in a state of nature being confined merely to what is physical in love, and
fortunate enough to be ignorant of those excellences, which whet the appetite while
they increase the difficulty of gratifying it, must be subject to fewer and less violent
fits of passion, and consequently fall into fewer and less violent disputes. The
imagination, which causes such ravages among us, never speaks to the heart of
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
179
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
savages, who quietly await the impulses of nature, yield to them involuntarily, with
more pleasure than ardour, and, their wants once satisfied, lose the desire. It is
therefore incontestable that love, as well as all other passions, must have acquired in
society that glowing impetuosity, which makes it so often fatal to mankind. And it is
the more absurd to represent savages as continually cutting one another’s throats to
indulge their brutality, because this opinion is directly contrary to experience; the
Caribeans, who have as yet least of all deviated from the state of nature, being in fact
the most peaceable of people in their amours, and the least subject to jealousy, though
they live in a hot climate which seems always to inflame the passions.
With regard to the inferences that might be drawn, in the case of several species of
animals, the males of which fill our poultry-yards with blood and slaughter, or in
spring make the forests resound with their quarrels over their females; we must begin
by excluding all those species, in which nature has plainly established, in the
comparative power of the sexes, relations different from those which exist among us:
thus we can base no conclusion about men on the habits of fighting cocks. In those
species where the proportion is better observed, these battles must be entirely due to
the scarcity of females in comparison with males; or, what amounts to the same thing,
to the intervals during which the female constantly refuses the advances of the male:
for if each female admits the male but during two months in the year, it is the same as
if the number of females were five-sixths less. Now, neither of these two cases is
applicable to the human species, in which the number of females usually exceeds that
of males, and among whom it has never been observed, even among savages, that the
females have, like those of other animals, their stated times of passion and
indifference. Moreover, in several of these species, the individuals all take fire at
once, and there comes a fearful moment of universal passion, tumult and disorder
among them; a scene which is never beheld in the human species, whose love is not
thus seasonal. We must not then conclude from the combats of such animals for the
enjoyment of the females, that the case would be the same with mankind in a state of
nature: and, even if we drew such a conclusion, we see that such contests do not
exterminate other kinds of animals, and we have no reason to think they would be
more fatal to ours. It is indeed clear that they would do still less mischief than is the
case in a state of society; especially in those countries in which, morals being still
held in some repute, the jealousy of lovers and the vengeance of husbands are the
daily cause of duels, murders, and even worse crimes; where the obligation of eternal
fidelity only occasions adultery, and the very laws of honour and continence
necessarily increase debauchery and lead to the multiplication of abortions.
Let us conclude then that man in a state of nature, wandering up and down the forests,
without industry, without speech, and without home, an equal stranger to war and to
all ties, neither standing in need of his fellow-creatures nor having any desire to hurt
them, and perhaps even not distinguishing them one from another; let us conclude
that, being self-sufficient and subject to so few passions, he could have no feelings or
knowledge but such as befitted his situation; that he felt only his actual necessities,
and disregarded everything he did not think himself immediately concerned to notice,
and that his understanding made no greater progress than his vanity. If by accident he
made any discovery, he was the less able to communicate it to others, as he did not
know even his own children. Every art would necessarily perish with its inventor,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
180
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
where there was no kind of education among men, and generations succeeded
generations without the least advance; when, all setting out from the same point,
centuries must have elapsed in the barbarism of the first ages; when the race was
already old, and man remained a child.
If I have expatiated at such length on this supposed primitive state, it is because I had
so many ancient errors and inveterate prejudices to eradicate, and therefore thought it
incumbent on me to dig down to their very root, and show, by means of a true picture
of the state of nature, how far even the natural inequalities of mankind are from
having that reality and influence which modern writers suppose.
It is in fact easy to see that many of the differences which distinguish men are merely
the effect of habit and the different methods of life men adopt in society. Thus a
robust or delicate constitution, and the strength or weakness attaching to it, are more
frequently the effects of a hardy or effeminate method of education than of the
original endowment of the body. It is the same with the powers of the mind; for
education not only makes a difference between such as are cultured and such as are
not, but even increases the differences which exist among the former, in proportion to
their respective degrees of culture: as the distance between a giant and a dwarf on the
same road increases with every step they take. If we compare the prodigious diversity,
which obtains in the education and manner of life of the various orders of men in the
state of society, with the uniformity and simplicity of animal and savage life, in which
every one lives on the same kind of food and in exactly the same manner, and does
exactly the same things, it is easy to conceive how much less the difference between
man and man must be in a state of nature than in a state of society, and how greatly
the natural inequality of mankind must be increased by the inequalities of social
institutions.
But even if nature really affected, in the distribution of her gifts, that partiality which
is imputed to her, what advantage would the greatest of her favourites derive from it,
to the detriment of others, in a state that admits of hardly any kind of relation between
them? Where there is no love, of what advantage is beauty? Of what use is wit to
those who do not converse, or cunning to those who have no business with others? I
hear it constantly repeated that, in such a state, the strong would oppress the weak; but
what is here meant by oppression? Some, it is said, would violently domineer over
others, who would groan under a servile submission to their caprices. This indeed is
exactly what I observe to be the case among us; but I do not see how it can be inferred
of men in a state of nature, who could not easily be brought to conceive what we
mean by dominion and servitude. One man, it is true, might seize the fruits which
another had gathered, the game he had killed, or the cave he had chosen for shelter;
but how would he ever be able to exact obedience, and what ties of dependence could
there be among men without possessions? If, for instance, I am driven from one tree, I
can go to the next; if I am disturbed in one place, what hinders me from going to
another? Again, should I happen to meet with a man so much stronger than myself,
and at the same time so depraved, so indolent, and so barbarous, as to compel me to
provide for his sustenance while he himself remains idle; he must take care not to
have his eyes off me for a single moment; he must bind me fast before he goes to
sleep, or I shall certainly either knock him on the head or make my escape. That is to
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
181
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
say, he must in such a case voluntarily expose himself to much greater trouble than he
seeks to avoid, or can give me. After all this, let him be off his guard ever so little; let
him but turn his head aside at any sudden noise, and I shall be instantly twenty paces
off, lost in the forest, and, my fetters burst asunder, he would never see me again.
Without my expatiating thus uselessly on these details, every one must see that as the
bonds of servitude are formed merely by the mutual dependence of men on one
another and the reciprocal needs that unite them, it is impossible to make any man a
slave, unless he be first reduced to a situation in which he cannot do without the help
of others: and, since such a situation does not exist in a state of nature, every one is
there his own master, and the law of the strongest is of no effect.
Having proved that the inequality of mankind is hardly felt, and that its influence is
next to nothing in a state of nature, I must next show its origin and trace its progress
in the successive developments of the human mind. Having shown that human
perfectibility, the social virtues, and the other faculties which natural man potentially
possessed, could never develop of themselves, but must require the fortuitous
concurrence of many foreign causes that might never arise, and without which he
would have remained for ever in his primitive condition, I must now collect and
consider the different accidents which may have improved the human understanding
while depraving the species, and made man wicked while making him sociable; so as
to bring him and the world from that distant period to the point at which we now
behold them.
I confess that, as the events I am going to describe might have happened in various
ways, I have nothing to determine my choice but conjectures: but such conjectures
become reasons, when they are the most probable that can be drawn from the nature
of things, and the only means of discovering the truth. The consequences, however,
which I mean to deduce will not be barely conjectural; as, on the principles just laid
down, it would be impossible to form any other theory that would not furnish the
same results, and from which I could not draw the same conclusions.
This will be a sufficient apology for my not dwelling on the manner in which the
lapse of time compensates for the little probability in the events; on the surprising
power of trivial causes, when their action is constant; on the impossibility, on the one
hand, of destroying certain hypotheses, though on the other we cannot give them the
certainty of known matters of fact; on its being within the province of history, when
two facts are given as real, and have to be connected by a series of intermediate facts,
which are unknown or supposed to be so, to supply such facts as may connect them;
and on its being in the province of philosophy when history is silent, to determine
similar facts to serve the same end; and lastly, on the influence of similarity, which, in
the case of events, reduces the facts to a much smaller number of different classes
than is commonly imagined. It is enough for me to offer these hints to the
consideration of my judges, and to have so arranged that the general reader has no
need to consider them at all.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
182
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
THE SECOND PART
The first man who, having enclosed a piece of ground, bethought himself of saying
This is mine, and found people simple enough to believe him, was the real founder of
civil society. From how many crimes, wars and murders, from how many horrors and
misfortunes might not any one have saved mankind, by pulling up the stakes, or
filling up the ditch, and crying to his fellows, “Beware of listening to this impostor;
you are undone if you once forget that the fruits of the earth belong to us all, and the
earth itself to nobody.” But there is great probability that things had then already
come to such a pitch, that they could no longer continue as they were; for the idea of
property depends on many prior ideas, which could only be acquired successively,
and cannot have been formed all at once in the human mind. Mankind must have
made very considerable progress, and acquired considerable knowledge and industry
which they must also have transmitted and increased from age to age, before they
arrived at this last point of the state of nature. Let us then go farther back, and
endeavour to unify under a single point of view that slow succession of events and
discoveries in the most natural order.
Man’s first feeling was that of his own existence, and his first care that of self-
preservation. The produce of the earth furnished him with all he needed, and instinct
told him how to use it. Hunger and other appetites made him at various times
experience various modes of existence; and among these was one which urged him to
propagate his species—a blind propensity that, having nothing to do with the heart,
produced a merely animal act. The want once gratified, the two sexes knew each other
no more; and even the offspring was nothing to its mother, as soon as it could do
without her.
Such was the condition of infant man; the life of an animal limited at first to mere
sensations, and hardly profiting by the gifts nature bestowed on him, much less
capable of entertaining a thought of forcing anything from her. But difficulties soon
presented themselves, and it became necessary to learn how to surmount them: the
height of the trees, which prevented him from gathering their fruits, the competition
of other animals desirous of the same fruits, and the ferocity of those who needed
them for their own preservation, all obliged him to apply himself to bodily exercises.
He had to be active, swift of foot, and vigorous in fight. Natural weapons, stones and
sticks, were easily found: he learnt to surmount the obstacles of nature, to contend in
case of necessity with other animals, and to dispute for the means of subsistence even
with other men, or to indemnify himself for what he was forced to give up to a
stronger.
In proportion as the human race grew more numerous, men’s cares increased. The
difference of soils, climates and seasons, must have introduced some differences into
their manner of living. Barren years, long and sharp winters, scorching summers
which parched the fruits of the earth, must have demanded a new industry. On the
seashore and the banks of rivers, they invented the hook and line, and became
fishermen and eaters of fish. In the forests they made bows and arrows, and became
huntsmen and warriors. In cold countries they clothed themselves with the skins of the
beasts they had slain. The lightning, a volcano, or some lucky chance acquainted them
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
183
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
with fire, a new resource against the rigours of winter: they next learned how to
preserve this element, then how to reproduce it, and finally how to prepare with it the
flesh of animals which before they had eaten raw.
This repeated relevance of various beings to himself, and one to another, would
naturally give rise in the human mind to the perceptions of certain relations between
them. Thus the relations which we denote by the terms, great, small, strong, weak,
swift, slow, fearful, bold, and the like, almost insensibly compared at need, must have
at length produced in him a kind of reflection, or rather a mechanical prudence, which
would indicate to him the precautions most necessary to his security.
The new intelligence which resulted from this development increased his superiority
over other animals, by making him sensible of it. He would now endeavour, therefore,
to ensnare them, would play them a thousand tricks, and though many of them might
surpass him in swiftness or in strength, would in time become the master of some and
the scourge of others. Thus, the first time he looked into himself, he felt the first
emotion of pride; and, at a time when he scarce knew how to distinguish the different
orders of beings, by looking upon his species as of the highest order, he prepared the
way for assuming pre-eminence as an individual.
Other men, it is true, were not then to him what they now are to us, and he had no
greater intercourse with them than with other animals; yet they were not neglected in
his observations. The conformities, which he would in time discover between them,
and between himself and his female, led him to judge of others which were not then
perceptible; and finding that they all behaved as he himself would have done in like
circumstances, he naturally inferred that their manner of thinking and acting was
altogether in conformity with his own. This important truth, once deeply impressed on
his mind, must have induced him, from an intuitive feeling more certain and much
more rapid than any kind of reasoning, to pursue the rules of conduct, which he had
best observe towards them, for his own security and advantage.
Taught by experience that the love of well-being is the sole motive of human actions,
he found himself in a position to distinguish the few cases, in which mutual interest
might justify him in relying upon the assistance of his fellows; and also the still fewer
cases in which a conflict of interests might give cause to suspect them. In the former
case, he joined in the same herd with them, or at most in some kind of loose
association, that laid no restraint on its members, and lasted no longer than the
transitory occasion that formed it. In the latter case, every one sought his own private
advantage, either by open force, if he thought himself strong enough, or by address
and cunning, if he felt himself the weaker.
In this manner, men may have insensibly acquired some gross ideas of mutual
undertakings, and of the advantages of fulfilling them: that is, just so far as their
present and apparent interest was concerned: for they were perfect strangers to
foresight, and were so far from troubling themselves about the distant future, that they
hardly thought of the morrow. If a deer was to be taken, every one saw that, in order
to succeed, he must abide faithfully by his post: but if a hare happened to come within
the reach of any one of them, it is not to be doubted that he pursued it without scruple,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
184
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
and, having seized his prey, cared very little, if by so doing he caused his companions
to miss theirs.
It is easy to understand that such intercourse would not require a language much more
refined than that of rooks or monkeys, who associate together for much the same
purpose. Inarticulate cries, plenty of gestures and some imitative sounds, must have
been for a long time the universal language; and by the addition, in every country, of
some conventional articulate sounds (of which, as I have already intimated, the first
institution is not too easy to explain) particular languages were produced; but these
were rude and imperfect, and nearly such as are now to be found among some savage
nations.
Hurried on by the rapidity of time, by the abundance of things I have to say, and by
the almost insensible progress of things in their beginnings, I pass over in an instant a
multitude of ages; for the slower the events were in their succession, the more rapidly
may they be described.
These first advances enabled men to make others with greater rapidity. In proportion
as they grew enlightened, they grew industrious. They ceased to fall asleep under the
first tree, or in the first cave that afforded them shelter; they invented several kinds of
implements of hard and sharp stones, which they used to dig up the earth, and to cut
wood; they then made huts out of branches, and afterwards learnt to plaster them over
with mud and clay. This was the epoch of a first revolution, which established and
distinguished families, and introduced a kind of property, in itself the source of a
thousand quarrels and conflicts. As, however, the strongest were probably the first to
build themselves huts which they felt themselves able to defend, it may be concluded
that the weak found it much easier and safer to imitate, than to attempt to dislodge
them: and of those who were once provided with huts, none could have any
inducement to appropriate that of his neighbour; not indeed so much because it did
not belong to him, as because it could be of no use, and he could not make himself
master of it without exposing himself to a desperate battle with the family which
occupied it.
The first expansions of the human heart were the effects of a novel situation, which
united husbands and wives, fathers and children, under one roof. The habit of living
together soon gave rise to the finest feelings known to humanity, conjugal love and
paternal affection. Every family became a little society, the more united because
liberty and reciprocal attachment were the only bonds of its union. The sexes, whose
manner of life had been hitherto the same, began now to adopt different ways of
living. The women became more sedentary, and accustomed themselves to mind the
hut and their children, while the men went abroad in search of their common
subsistence. From living a softer life, both sexes also began to lose something of their
strength and ferocity: but, if individuals became to some extent less able to encounter
wild beasts separately, they found it, on the other hand, easier to assemble and resist
in common.
The simplicity and solitude of man’s life in this new condition, the paucity of his
wants, and the implements he had invented to satisfy them, left him a great deal of
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
185
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
leisure, which he employed to furnish himself with many conveniences unknown to
his fathers: and this was the first yoke he inadvertently imposed on himself, and the
first source of the evils he prepared for his descendants. For, besides continuing thus
to enervate both body and mind, these conveniences lost with use almost all their
power to please, and even degenerated into real needs, till the want of them became
far more disagreeable than the possession of them had been pleasant. Men would have
been unhappy at the loss of them, though the possession did not make them happy.
We can here see a little better how the use of speech became established, and
insensibly improved in each family, and we may form a conjecture also concerning
the manner in which various causes may have extended and accelerated the progress
of language, by making it more and more necessary. Floods or earthquakes
surrounded inhabited districts with precipices or waters: revolutions of the globe tore
off portions from the continent, and made them islands. It is readily seen that among
men thus collected and compelled to live together, a common idiom must have arisen
much more easily than among those who still wandered through the forests of the
continent. Thus it is very possible that after their first essays in navigation the
islanders brought over the use of speech to the continent: and it is at least very
probable that communities and languages were first established in islands, and even
came to perfection there before they were known on the mainland.
Everything now begins to change its aspect. Men, who have up to now been roving in
the woods, by taking to a more settled manner of life, come gradually together, form
separate bodies, and at length in every country arises a distinct nation, united in
character and manners, not by regulations or laws, but by uniformity of life and food,
and the common influence of climate. Permanent neighbourhood could not fail to
produce, in time, some connection between different families. Among young people
of opposite sexes, living in neighbouring huts, the transient commerce required by
nature soon led, through mutual intercourse, to another kind not less agreeable, and
more permanent. Men began now to take the difference between objects into account,
and to make comparisons; they acquired imperceptibly the ideas of beauty and merit,
which soon gave rise to feelings of preference. In consequence of seeing each other
often, they could not do without seeing each other constantly. A tender and pleasant
feeling insinuated itself into their souls, and the least opposition turned it into an
impetuous fury: with love arose jealousy; discord triumphed, and human blood was
sacrificed to the gentlest of all passions.
As ideas and feelings succeeded one another, and heart and head were brought into
play, men continued to lay aside their original wildness; their private connections
became every day more intimate as their limits extended. They accustomed
themselves to assemble before their huts round a large tree; singing and dancing, the
true offspring of love and leisure, became the amusement, or rather the occupation, of
men and women thus assembled together with nothing else to do. Each one began to
consider the rest, and to wish to be considered in turn; and thus a value came to be
attached to public esteem. Whoever sang or danced best, whoever was the
handsomest, the strongest, the most dexterous, or the most eloquent, came to be of
most consideration; and this was the first step towards inequality, and at the same
time towards vice. From these first distinctions arose on the one side vanity and
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
186
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
contempt and on the other shame and envy: and the fermentation caused by these new
leavens ended by producing combinations fatal to innocence and happiness.
As soon as men began to value one another, and the idea of consideration had got a
footing in the mind, every one put in his claim to it, and it became impossible to
refuse it to any with impunity. Hence arose the first obligations of civility even among
savages; and every intended injury became an affront; because, besides the hurt which
might result from it, the party injured was certain to find in it a contempt for his
person, which was often more insupportable than the hurt itself.
Thus, as every man punished the contempt shown him by others, in proportion to his
opinion of himself, revenge became terrible, and men bloody and cruel. This is
precisely the state reached by most of the savage nations known to us: and it is for
want of having made a proper distinction in our ideas, and seen how very far they
already are from the state of nature, that so many writers have hastily concluded that
man is naturally cruel, and requires civil institutions to make him more mild; whereas
nothing is more gentle than man in his primitive state, as he is placed by nature at an
equal distance from the stupidity of brutes, and the fatal ingenuity of civilised man.
Equally confined by instinct and reason to the sole care of guarding himself against
the mischiefs which threaten him, he is restrained by natural compassion from doing
any injury to others, and is not led to do such a thing even in return for injuries
received. For, according to the axiom of the wise Locke, There can be no injury,
where there is no property.
But it must be remarked that the society thus formed, and the relations thus
established among men, required of them qualities different from those which they
possessed from their primitive constitution. Morality began to appear in human
actions, and every one, before the institution of law, was the only judge and avenger
of the injuries done him, so that the goodness which was suitable in the pure state of
nature was no longer proper in the new-born state of society. Punishments had to be
made more severe, as opportunities of offending became more frequent, and the dread
of vengeance had to take the place of the rigour of the law. Thus, though men had
become less patient, and their natural compassion had already suffered some
diminution, this period of expansion of the human faculties, keeping a just mean
between the indolence of the primitive state and the petulant activity of our egoism,
must have been the happiest and most stable of epochs. The more we reflect on it, the
more we shall find that this state was the least subject to revolutions, and altogether
the very best man could experience; so that he can have departed from it only through
some fatal accident, which, for the public good, should never have happened. The
example of savages, most of whom have been found in this state, seems to prove that
men were meant to remain in it, that it is the real youth of the world, and that all
subsequent advances have been apparently so many steps towards the perfection of
the individual, but in reality towards the decrepitude of the species.
So long as men remained content with their rustic huts, so long as they were satisfied
with clothes made of the skins of animals and sewn together with thorns and fish-
bones, adorned themselves only with feathers and shells, and continued to paint their
bodies different colours, to improve and beautify their bows and arrows and to make
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
187
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
with sharp-edged stones fishing boats or clumsy musical instruments; in a word, so
long as they undertook only what a single person could accomplish, and confined
themselves to such arts as did not require the joint labour of several hands, they lived
free, healthy, honest and happy lives, so long as their nature allowed, and as they
continued to enjoy the pleasures of mutual and independent intercourse. But from the
moment one man began to stand in need of the help of another; from the moment it
appeared advantageous to any one man to have enough provisions for two, equality
disappeared, property was introduced, work became indispensable, and vast forests
became smiling fields, which man had to water with the sweat of his brow, and where
slavery and misery were soon seen to germinate and grow up with the crops.
Metallurgy and agriculture were the two arts which produced this great revolution.
The poets tell us it was gold and silver, but, for the philosophers, it was iron and corn,
which first civilised men, and ruined humanity. Thus both were unknown to the
savages of America, who for that reason are still savage: the other nations also seem
to have continued in a state of barbarism while they practised only one of these arts.
One of the best reasons, perhaps, why Europe has been, if not longer, at least more
constantly and highly civilised than the rest of the world, is that it is at once the most
abundant in iron and the most fertile in corn.
It is difficult to conjecture how men first came to know and use iron; for it is
impossible to suppose they would of themselves think of digging the ore out of the
mine, and preparing it for smelting, before they knew what would be the result. On
the other hand, we have the less reason to suppose this discovery the effect of any
accidental fire, as mines are only formed in barren places, bare of trees and plants; so
that it looks as if nature had taken pains to keep the fatal secret from us. There
remains, therefore, only the extraordinary accident of some volcano which, by
ejecting metallic substances already in fusion, suggested to the spectators the idea of
imitating the natural operation. And we must further conceive them as possessed of
uncommon courage and foresight, to undertake so laborious a work, with so distant a
prospect of drawing advantage from it; yet these qualities are united only in minds
more advanced than we can suppose those of these first discoverers to have been.
With regard to agriculture, the principles of it were known long before they were put
in practice; and it is indeed hardly possible that men, constantly employed in drawing
their subsistence from plants and trees, should not readily acquire a knowledge of the
means made use of by nature for the propagation of vegetables. It was in all
probability very long, however, before their industry took that turn, either because
trees, which together with hunting and fishing afforded them food, did not require
their attention; or because they were ignorant of the use of corn, or without
instruments to cultivate it; or because they lacked foresight to future needs; or lastly,
because they were without means of preventing others from robbing them of the fruit
of their labour.
When they grew more industrious, it is natural to believe that they began, with the
help of sharp stones and pointed sticks, to cultivate a few vegetables or roots around
their huts; though it was long before they knew how to prepare corn, or were provided
with the implements necessary for raising it in any large quantity; not to mention how
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
188
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
essential it is, for husbandry, to consent to immediate loss, in order to reap a future
gain—a precaution very foreign to the turn of a savage’s mind; for, as I have said, he
hardly foresees in the morning what he will need at night.
The invention of the other arts must therefore have been necessary to compel mankind
to apply themselves to agriculture. No sooner were artificers wanted to smelt and
forge iron, than others were required to maintain them; the more hands that were
employed in manufactures, the fewer were left to provide for the common
subsistence, though the number of mouths to be furnished with food remained the
same: and as some required commodities in exchange for their iron, the rest at length
discovered the method of making iron serve for the multiplication of commodities. By
this means the arts of husbandry and agriculture were established on the one hand,
and the art of working metals and multiplying their uses on the other.
The cultivation of the earth necessarily brought about its distribution; and property,
once recognised, gave rise to the first rules of justice; for, to secure each man his own,
it had to be possible for each to have something. Besides, as men began to look
forward to the future, and all had something to lose, every one had reason to
apprehend that reprisals would follow any injury he might do to another. This origin
is so much the more natural, as it is impossible to conceive how property can come
from anything but manual labour: for what else can a man add to things which he does
not originally create, so as to make them his own property? It is the husbandman’s
labour alone that, giving him a title to the produce of the ground he has tilled, gives
him a claim also to the land itself, at least till harvest; and so, from year to year, a
constant possession which is easily transformed into property. When the ancients,
says Grotius, gave to Ceres the title of Legislatrix, and to a festival celebrated in her
honour the name of Thesmophoria, they meant by that that the distribution of lands
had produced a new kind of right: that is to say, the right of property, which is
different from the right deducible from the law of nature.
In this state of affairs, equality might have been sustained, had the talents of
individuals been equal, and had, for example, the use of iron and the consumption of
commodities always exactly balanced each other; but, as there was nothing to
preserve this balance, it was soon disturbed; the strongest did most work; the most
skilful turned his labour to best account; the most ingenious devised methods of
diminishing his labour: the husbandman wanted more iron, or the smith more corn,
and, while both laboured equally, the one gained a great deal by his work, while the
other could hardly support himself. Thus natural inequality unfolds itself insensibly
with that of combination, and the difference between men, developed by their
different circumstances, becomes more sensible and permanent in its effects, and
begins to have an influence, in the same proportion, over the lot of individuals.
Matters once at this pitch, it is easy to imagine the rest. I shall not detain the reader
with a description of the successive invention of other arts, the development of
language, the trial and utilisation of talents, the inequality of fortunes, the use and
abuse of riches, and all the details connected with them which the reader can easily
supply for himself. I shall confine myself to a glance at mankind in this new situation.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
189
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Behold then all human faculties developed, memory and imagination in full play,
egoism interested, reason active, and the mind almost at the highest point of its
perfection. Behold all the natural qualities in action, the rank and condition of every
man assigned him; not merely his share of property and his power to serve or injure
others, but also his wit, beauty, strength or skill, merit or talents: and these being the
only qualities capable of commanding respect, it soon became necessary to possess or
to affect them.
It now became the interest of men to appear what they really were not. To be and to
seem became two totally different things; and from this distinction sprang insolent
pomp and cheating trickery, with all the numerous vices that go in their train. On the
other hand, free and independent as men were before, they were now, in consequence
of a multiplicity of new wants, brought into subjection, as it were, to all nature, and
particularly to one another; and each became in some degree a slave even in becoming
the master of other men: if rich, they stood in need of the services of others; if poor, of
their assistance; and even a middle condition did not enable them to do without one
another. Man must now, therefore, have been perpetually employed in getting others
to interest themselves in his lot, and in making them, apparently at least, if not really,
find their advantage in promoting his own. Thus he must have been sly and artful in
his behaviour to some, and imperious and cruel to others; being under a kind of
necessity to ill-use all the persons of whom he stood in need, when he could not
frighten them into compliance, and did not judge it his interest to be useful to them.
Insatiable ambition, the thirst of raising their respective fortunes, not so much from
real want as from the desire to surpass others, inspired all men with a vile propensity
to injure one another, and with a secret jealousy, which is the more dangerous, as it
puts on the mask of benevolence, to carry its point with greater security. In a word,
there arose rivalry and competition on the one hand, and conflicting interests on the
other, together with a secret desire on both of profiting at the expense of others. All
these evils were the first effects of property, and the inseparable attendants of growing
inequality.
Before the invention of signs to represent riches, wealth could hardly consist in
anything but lands and cattle, the only real possessions men can have. But, when
inheritances so increased in number and extent as to occupy the whole of the land, and
to border on one another, one man could aggrandise himself only at the expense of
another; at the same time the supernumeraries, who had been too weak or too indolent
to make such acquisitions, and had grown poor without sustaining any loss, because,
while they saw everything change around them, they remained still the same, were
obliged to receive their subsistence, or steal it, from the rich; and this soon bred,
according to their different characters, dominion and slavery, or violence and rapine.
The wealthy, on their part, had no sooner begun to taste the pleasure of command,
than they disdained all others, and, using their old slaves to acquire new, thought of
nothing but subduing and enslaving their neighbours; like ravenous wolves, which,
having once tasted human flesh, despise every other food and thenceforth seek only
men to devour.
Thus, as the most powerful or the most miserable considered their might or misery as
a kind of right to the possessions of others, equivalent, in their opinion, to that of
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
190
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
property, the destruction of equality was attended by the most terrible disorders.
Usurpations by the rich, robbery by the poor, and the unbridled passions of both,
suppressed the cries of natural compassion and the still feeble voice of justice, and
filled men with avarice, ambition and vice. Between the title of the strongest and that
of the first occupier, there arose perpetual conflicts, which never ended but in battles
and bloodshed. The new-born state of society thus gave rise to a horrible state of war;
men thus harassed and depraved were no longer capable of retracing their steps or
renouncing the fatal acquisitions they had made, but, labouring by the abuse of the
faculties which do them honour, merely to their own confusion, brought themselves to
the brink of ruin.
Attonitus novitate mali, divesque miserque,
Effugere optat opes; et quæ modo voverat odit.1
It is impossible that men should not at length have reflected on so wretched a
situation, and on the calamities that overwhelmed them. The rich, in particular, must
have felt how much they suffered by a constant state of war, of which they bore all the
expense; and in which, though all risked their lives, they alone risked their property.
Besides, however speciously they might disguise their usurpations, they knew that
they were founded on precarious and false titles; so that, if others took from them by
force what they themselves had gained by force, they would have no reason to
complain. Even those who had been enriched by their own industry, could hardly base
their proprietorship on better claims. It was in vain to repeat, “I built this well; I
gained this spot by my industry.” Who gave you your standing, it might be answered,
and what right have you to demand payment of us for doing what we never asked you
to do? Do you not know that numbers of your fellow-creatures are starving, for want
of what you have too much of? You ought to have had the express and universal
consent of mankind, before appropriating more of the common subsistence than you
needed for your own maintenance. Destitute of valid reasons to justify and sufficient
strength to defend himself, able to crush individuals with ease, but easily crushed
himself by a troop of bandits, one against all, and incapable, on account of mutual
jealousy, of joining with his equals against numerous enemies united by the common
hope of plunder, the rich man, thus urged by necessity, conceived at length the
profoundest plan that ever entered the mind of man: this was to employ in his favour
the forces of those who attacked him, to make allies of his adversaries, to inspire them
with different maxims, and to give them other institutions as favourable to himself as
the law of nature was unfavourable.
With this view, after having represented to his neighbours the horror of a situation
which armed every man against the rest, and made their possessions as burdensome to
them as their wants, and in which no safety could be expected either in riches or in
poverty, he readily devised plausible arguments to make them close with his design.
“Let us join,” said he, “to guard the weak from oppression, to restrain the ambitious,
and secure to every man the possession of what belongs to him: let us institute rules of
justice and peace, to which all without exception may be obliged to conform; rules
that may in some measure make amends for the caprices of fortune, by subjecting
equally the powerful and the weak to the observance of reciprocal obligations. Let us,
in a word, instead of turning our forces against ourselves, collect them in a supreme
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
191
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
power which may govern us by wise laws, protect and defend all the members of the
association, repulse their common enemies, and maintain eternal harmony among us.”
Far fewer words to this purpose would have been enough to impose on men so
barbarous and easily seduced; especially as they had too many disputes among
themselves to do without arbitrators, and too much ambition and avarice to go long
without masters. All ran headlong to their chains, in hopes of securing their liberty;
for they had just wit enough to perceive the advantages of political institutions,
without experience enough to enable them to foresee the dangers. The most capable of
foreseeing the dangers were the very persons who expected to benefit by them; and
even the most prudent judged it not inexpedient to sacrifice one part of their freedom
to ensure the rest; as a wounded man has his arm cut off to save the rest of his body.
Such was, or may well have been, the origin of society and law, which bound new
fetters on the poor, and gave new powers to the rich; which irretrievably destroyed
natural liberty, eternally fixed the law of property and inequality, converted clever
usurpation into unalterable right, and, for the advantage of a few ambitious
individuals, subjected all mankind to perpetual labour, slavery and wretchedness. It is
easy to see how the establishment of one community made that of all the rest
necessary, and how, in order to make head against united forces, the rest of mankind
had to unite in turn. Societies soon multiplied and spread over the face of the earth, till
hardly a corner of the world was left in which a man could escape the yoke, and
withdraw his head from beneath the sword which he saw perpetually hanging over
him by a thread. Civil right having thus become the common rule among the members
of each community, the law of nature maintained its place only between different
communities, where, under the name of the right of nations, it was qualified by certain
tacit conventions, in order to make commerce practicable, and serve as a substitute for
natural compassion, which lost, when applied to societies, almost all the influence it
had over individuals, and survived no longer except in some great cosmopolitan
spirits, who, breaking down the imaginary barriers that separate different peoples,
follow the example of our Sovereign Creator, and include the whole human race in
their benevolence.
But bodies politic, remaining thus in a state of nature among themselves, presently
experienced the inconveniences which had obliged individuals to forsake it; for this
state became still more fatal to these great bodies than it had been to the individuals of
whom they were composed. Hence arose national wars, battles, murders, and
reprisals, which shock nature and outrage reason; together with all those horrible
prejudices which class among the virtues the honour of shedding human blood. The
most distinguished men hence learned to consider cutting each other’s throats a duty;
at length men massacred their fellow-creatures by thousands without so much as
knowing why, and committed more murders in a single day’s fighting, and more
violent outrages in the sack of a single town, than were committed in the state of
nature during whole ages over the whole earth. Such were the first effects which we
can see to have followed the division of mankind into different communities. But let
us return to their institutions.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
192
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
I know that some writers have given other explanations of the origin of political
societies, such as the conquest of the powerful, or the association of the weak. It is,
indeed, indifferent to my argument which of these causes we choose. That which I
have just laid down, however, appears to me the most natural for the following
reasons. First: because, in the first case, the right of conquest, being no right in itself,
could not serve as a foundation on which to build any other; the victor and the
vanquished people still remained with respect to each other in the state of war, unless
the vanquished, restored to the full possession of their liberty, voluntarily made choice
of the victor for their chief. For till then, whatever capitulation may have been made
being founded on violence, and therefore ipso facto void, there could not have been
on this hypothesis either a real society or body politic, or any law other than that of
the strongest. Secondly: because the words strong and weak are, in the second case,
ambiguous; for during the interval between the establishment of a right of property, or
prior occupancy, and that of political government, the meaning of these words is
better expressed by the terms rich and poor: because, in fact, before the institution of
laws, men had no other way of reducing their equals to submission, than by attacking
their goods, or making some of their own over to them. Thirdly: because, as the poor
had nothing but their freedom to lose, it would have been in the highest degree absurd
for them to resign voluntarily the only good they still enjoyed, without getting
anything in exchange: whereas the rich having feelings, if I may so express myself, in
every part of their possessions, it was much easier to harm them, and therefore more
necessary for them to take precautions against it; and, in short, because it is more
reasonable to suppose a thing to have been invented by those to whom it would be of
service, than by those whom it must have harmed.
Government had, in its infancy, no regular and constant form. The want of experience
and philosophy prevented men from seeing any but present inconveniences, and they
thought of providing against others only as they presented themselves. In spite of the
endeavours of the wisest legislators, the political state remained imperfect, because it
was little more than the work of chance; and, as it had begun ill, though time revealed
its defects and suggested remedies, the original faults were never repaired. It was
continually being patched up, when the first task should have been to get the site
cleared and all the old materials removed, as was done by Lycurgus at Sparta, if a
stable and lasting edifice was to be erected. Society consisted at first merely of a few
general conventions, which every member bound himself to observe; and for the
performance of covenants the whole body went security to each individual.
Experience only could show the weakness of such a constitution, and how easily it
might be infringed with impunity, from the difficulty of convicting men of faults,
where the public alone was to be witness and judge: the laws could not but be eluded
in many ways; disorders and inconveniences could not but multiply continually, till it
became necessary to commit the dangerous trust of public authority to private
persons, and the care of enforcing obedience to the deliberations of the people to the
magistrate. For to say that chiefs were chosen before the confederacy was formed, and
that the administrators of the laws were there before the laws themselves, is too
absurd a supposition to consider seriously.
It would be as unreasonable to suppose that men at first threw themselves
irretrievably and unconditionally into the arms of an absolute master, and that the first
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
193
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
expedient which proud and unsubdued men hit upon for their common security was to
run headlong into slavery. For what reason, in fact, did they take to themselves
superiors, if it was not in order that they might be defended from oppression, and have
protection for their lives, liberties and properties, which are, so to speak, the
constituent elements of their being? Now, in the relations between man and man, the
worst that can happen is for one to find himself at the mercy of another, and it would
have been inconsistent with common-sense to begin by bestowing on a chief the only
things they wanted his help to preserve. What equivalent could he offer them for so
great a right? And if he had presumed to exact it under pretext of defending them,
would he not have received the answer recorded in the fable: “What more can the
enemy do to us?” It is therefore beyond dispute, and indeed the fundamental maxim
of all political right, that people have set up chiefs to protect their liberty, and not to
enslave them. If we have a prince, said Pliny to Trajan, it is to save ourselves from
having a master.
Politicians indulge in the same sophistry about the love of liberty as philosophers
about the state of nature. They judge, by what they see, of very different things, which
they have not seen; and attribute to man a natural propensity to servitude, because the
slaves within their observation are seen to bear the yoke with patience; they fail to
reflect that it is with liberty as with innocence and virtue; the value is known only to
those who possess them, and the taste for them is forfeited when they are forfeited
themselves. “I know the charms of your country,” said Brasidas to a Satrap, who was
comparing the life at Sparta with that at Persepolis, “but you cannot know the
pleasures of mine.”
An unbroken horse erects his mane, paws the ground and starts back impetuously at
the sight of the bridle; while one which is properly trained suffers patiently even whip
and spur: so savage man will not bend his neck to the yoke to which civilised man
submits without a murmur, but prefers the most turbulent state of liberty to the most
peaceful slavery. We cannot therefore, from the servility of nations already enslaved,
judge of the natural disposition of mankind for or against slavery; we should go by the
prodigious efforts of every free people to save itself from oppression. I know that the
former are for ever holding forth in praise of the tranquillity they enjoy in their chains,
and that they call a state of wretched servitude a state of peace: miserriman servitutem
pacem appellant.1 But when I observe the latter sacrificing pleasure, peace, wealth,
power and life itself to the preservation of that one treasure, which is so disdained by
those who have lost it; when I see free-born animals dash their brains out against the
bars of their cage, from an innate impatience of captivity; when I behold numbers of
naked savages, that despise European pleasures, braving hunger, fire, the sword and
death, to preserve nothing but their independence, I feel that it is not for slaves to
argue about liberty.
With regard to paternal authority, from which some writers have derived absolute
government and all society, it is enough, without going back to the contrary
arguments of Locke and Sidney, to remark that nothing on earth can be further from
the ferocious spirit of despotism than the mildness of that authority which looks more
to the advantage of him who obeys than to that of him who commands; that, by the
law of nature, the father is the child’s master no longer than his help is necessary; that
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
194
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
from that time they are both equal, the son being perfectly independent of the father,
and owing him only respect and not obedience. For gratitude is a duty which ought to
be paid, but not a right to be exacted: instead of saying that civil society is derived
from paternal authority, we ought to say rather that the latter derives its principal
force from the former. No individual was ever acknowledged as the father of many,
till his sons and daughters remained settled around him. The goods of the father, of
which he is really the master, are the ties which keep his children in dependence, and
he may bestow on them, if he pleases, no share of his property, unless they merit it by
constant deference to his will. But the subjects of an arbitrary despot are so far from
having the like favour to expect from their chief, that they themselves and everything
they possess are his property, or at least are considered by him as such; so that they
are forced to receive, as a favour, the little of their own he is pleased to leave them.
When he despoils them, he does but justice, and mercy in that he permits them to live.
By proceeding thus to test fact by right, we should discover as little reason as truth in
the voluntary establishment of tyranny. It would also be no easy matter to prove the
validity of a contract binding on only one of the parties, where all the risk is on one
side, and none on the other; so that no one could suffer but he who bound himself.
This hateful system is indeed, even in modern times, very far from being that of wise
and good monarchs, and especially of the kings of France; as may be seen from
several passages in their edicts; particularly from the following passage in a
celebrated edict published in 1667 in the name and by order of Louis XIV.
“Let it not, therefore, be said that the Sovereign is not subject to the laws of his State;
since the contrary is a true proposition of the right of nations, which flattery has
sometimes attacked but good princes have always defended as the tutelary divinity of
their dominions. How much more legitimate is it to say with the wise Plato, that the
perfect felicity of a kingdom consists in the obedience of subjects to their prince, and
of the prince to the laws, and in the laws being just and constantly directed to the
public good!”1
I shall not stay here to inquire whether, as liberty is the noblest faculty of man, it is
not degrading our very nature, reducing ourselves to the level of the brutes, which are
mere slaves of instinct, and even an affront to the Author of our being, to renounce
without reserve the most precious of all His gifts, and to bow to the necessity of
committing all the crimes He has forbidden, merely to gratify a mad or a cruel master;
or if this sublime craftsman ought not to be less angered at seeing His workmanship
entirely destroyed than thus dishonoured. I will waive (if my opponents please) the
authority of Barbeyrac, who, following Locke, roundly declares that no man can so
far sell his liberty as to submit to an arbitrary power which may use him as it likes.
For, he adds, this would be to sell his own life, of which he is not master. I shall ask
only what right those who were not afraid thus to debase themselves could have to
subject their posterity to the same ignominy, and to renounce for them those blessings
which they do not owe to the liberality of their progenitors, and without which life
itself must be a burden to all who are worthy of it.
Puffendorf says that we may divest ourselves of our liberty in favour of other men,
just as we transfer our property from one to another by contracts and agreements. But
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
195
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
this seems a very weak argument. For in the first place, the property I alienate
becomes quite foreign to me, nor can I suffer from the abuse of it; but it very nearly
concerns me that my liberty should not be abused, and I cannot without incurring the
guilt of the crimes I may be compelled to commit, expose myself to become an
instrument of crime. Besides, the right of property being only a convention of human
institution, men may dispose of what they possess as they please: but this is not the
case with the essential gifts of nature, such as life and liberty, which every man is
permitted to enjoy, and of which it is at least doubtful whether any have a right to
divest themselves. By giving up the one, we degrade our being; by giving up the
other, we do our best to annul it; and, as no temporal good can indemnify us for the
loss of either, it would be an offence against both reason and nature to renounce them
at any price whatsoever. But, even if we could transfer our liberty, as we do our
property, there would be a great difference with regard to the children, who enjoy the
father’s substance only by the transmission of his right; whereas, liberty being a gift
which they hold from nature as being men, their parents have no right whatever to
deprive them of it. As then, to establish slavery, it was necessary to do violence to
nature, so, in order to perpetuate such a right, nature would have to be changed.
Jurists, who have gravely determined that the child of a slave comes into the world a
slave, have decided, in other words, that a man shall come into the world not a man.
I regard it then as certain, that government did not begin with arbitrary power, but that
this is the depravation, the extreme term, of government, and brings it back, finally, to
just the law of the strongest, which it was originally designed to remedy. Supposing,
however, it had begun in this manner, such power, being in itself illegitimate, could
not have served as a basis for the laws of society, nor, consequently, for the inequality
they instituted.
Without entering at present upon the investigations which still remain to be made into
the nature of the fundamental compact underlying all government, I content myself
with adopting the common opinion concerning it, and regard the establishment of the
political body as a real contract between the people and the chiefs chosen by them: a
contract by which both parties bind themselves to observe the laws therein expressed,
which form the ties of their union. The people having in respect of their social
relations concentrated all their wills in one, the several articles, concerning which this
will is explained, become so many fundamental laws, obligatory on all the members
of the State without exception, and one of these articles regulates the choice and
power of the magistrates appointed to watch over the execution of the rest. This
power extends to everything which may maintain the constitution, without going so
far as to alter it. It is accompanied by honours, in order to bring the laws and their
administrators into respect. The ministers are also distinguished by personal
prerogatives, in order to recompense them for the cares and labour which good
administration involves. The magistrate, on his side, binds himself to use the power he
is entrusted with only in conformity with the intention of his constituents, to maintain
them all in the peaceable possession of what belongs to them, and to prefer on every
occasion the public interest to his own.
Before experience had shown, or knowledge of the human heart enabled men to
foresee, the unavoidable abuses of such a constitution, it must have appeared so much
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
196
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
the more excellent, as those who were charged with the care of its preservation had
themselves most interest in it; for magistracy and the rights attaching to it being based
solely on the fundamental laws, the magistrates would cease to be legitimate as soon
as these ceased to exist; the people would no longer owe them obedience; and as not
the magistrates, but the laws, are essential to the being of a State, the members of it
would regain the right to their natural liberty.
If we reflect with ever so little attention on this subject, we shall find new arguments
to confirm this truth, and be convinced from the very nature of the contract that it
cannot be irrevocable: for, if there were no superior power capable of ensuring the
fidelity of the contracting parties, or compelling them to perform their reciprocal
engagements, the parties would be sole judges in their own cause, and each would
always have a right to renounce the contract, as soon as he found that the other had
violated its terms, or that they no longer suited his convenience. It is upon this
principle that the right of abdication may possibly be founded. Now, if, as here, we
consider only what is human in this institution, it is certain that, if the magistrate, who
has all the power in his own hands, and appropriates to himself all the advantages of
the contract, has none the less a right to renounce his authority, the people, who suffer
for all the faults of their chief, must have a much better right to renounce their
dependence. But the terrible and innumerable quarrels and disorders that would
necessarily arise from so dangerous a privilege, show, more than anything else, how
much human governments stood in need of a more solid basis than mere reason, and
how expedient it was for the public tranquillity that the divine will should interpose to
invest the sovereign authority with a sacred and inviolable character, which might
deprive subjects of the fatal right of disposing of it. If the world had received no other
advantages from religion, this would be enough to impose on men the duty of
adopting and cultivating it, abuses and all, since it has been the means of saving more
blood than fanaticism has ever spilt. But let us follow the thread of our hypothesis.
The different forms of government owe their origin to the differing degrees of
inequality which existed between individuals at the time of their institution. If there
happened to be any one man among them pre-eminent in power, virtue, riches or
personal influence, he became sole magistrate, and the State assumed the form of
monarchy. If several, nearly equal in point of eminence, stood above the rest, they
were elected jointly, and formed an aristocracy. Again, among a people who had
deviated less from a state of nature, and between whose fortune or talents there was
less disproportion, the supreme administration was retained in common, and a
democracy was formed. It was discovered in process of time which of these forms
suited men the best. Some peoples remained altogether subject to the laws; others
soon came to obey their magistrates. The citizens laboured to preserve their liberty;
the subjects, irritated at seeing others enjoying a blessing they had lost, thought only
of making slaves of their neighbours. In a word, on the one side arose riches and
conquests, and on the other happiness and virtue.
In these different governments, all the offices were at first elective; and when the
influence of wealth was out of the question, the preference was given to merit, which
gives a natural ascendancy, and to age, which is experienced in business and
deliberate in council. The Elders of the Hebrews, the Gerontes at Sparta, the Senate at
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
197
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Rome, and the very etymology of our word Seigneur, show how old age was once
held in veneration. But the more often the choice fell upon old men, the more often
elections had to be repeated, and the more they became a nuisance; intrigues set in,
factions were formed, party feeling grew bitter, civil wars broke out; the lives of
individuals were sacrificed to the pretended happiness of the State; and at length men
were on the point of relapsing into their primitive anarchy. Ambitious chiefs profited
by these circumstances to perpetuate their offices in their own families: at the same
time the people, already used to dependence, ease, and the conveniences of life, and
already incapable of breaking its fetters, agreed to an increase of its slavery, in order
to secure its tranquillity. Thus magistrates, having become hereditary, contracted the
habit of considering their offices as a family estate, and themselves as proprietors of
the communities of which they were at first only the officers, of regarding their
fellow-citizens as their slaves, and numbering them, like cattle, among their
belongings, and of calling themselves the equals of the gods and kings of kings.
If we follow the progress of inequality in these various revolutions, we shall find that
the establishment of laws and of the right of property was its first term, the institution
of magistracy the second, and the conversion of legitimate into arbitrary power the
third and last; so that the condition of rich and poor was authorised by the first period;
that of powerful and weak by the second; and only by the third that of master and
slave, which is the last degree of inequality, and the term at which all the rest remain,
when they have got so far, till the government is either entirely dissolved by new
revolutions, or brought back again to legitimacy.
To understand this progress as necessary we must consider not so much the motives
for the establishment of the body politic, as the forms it assumes in actuality, and the
faults that necessarily attend it: for the flaws which make social institutions necessary
are the same as make the abuse of them unavoidable. If we except Sparta, where the
laws were mainly concerned with the education of children, and where Lycurgus
established such morality as practically made laws needless—for laws as a rule, being
weaker than the passions, restrain men without altering them—it would not be
difficult to prove that every government, which scrupulously complied with the ends
for which it was instituted, and guarded carefully against change and corruption, was
set up unnecessarily. For a country, in which no one either evaded the laws or made a
bad use of magisterial power, could require neither laws nor magistrates.
Political distinctions necessarily produce civil distinctions. The growing equality
between the chiefs and the people is soon felt by individuals, and modified in a
thousand ways according to passions, talents and circumstances. The magistrate could
not usurp any illegitimate power, without giving distinction to the creatures with
whom he must share it. Besides, individuals only allow themselves to be oppressed so
far as they are hurried on by blind ambition, and, looking rather below than above
them, come to love authority more than independence, and submit to slavery, that they
may in turn enslave others. It is no easy matter to reduce to obedience a man who has
no ambition to command; nor would the most adroit politician find it possible to
enslave a people whose only desire was to be independent. But inequality easily
makes its way among cowardly and ambitious minds, which are ever ready to run the
risks of fortune, and almost indifferent whether they command or obey, as it is
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
198
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
favourable or adverse. Thus, there must have been a time, when the eyes of the people
were so fascinated, that their rulers had only to say to the least of men, “Be great, you
and all your posterity,” to make him immediately appear great in the eyes of every
one as well as in his own. His descendants took still more upon them, in proportion to
their distance from him; the more obscure and uncertain the cause, the greater the
effect: the greater the number of idlers one could count in a family, the more
illustrious it was held to be.
If this were the place to go into details, I could readily explain how, even without the
intervention of government, inequality of credit and authority became unavoidable
among private persons, as soon as their union in a single society made them compare
themselves one with another, and take into account the differences which they found
out from the continual intercourse every man had to have with his neighbours.1 These
differences are of several kinds; but riches, nobility or rank, power and personal merit
being the principal distinctions by which men form an estimate of each other in
society, I could prove that the harmony or conflict of these different forces is the
surest indication of the good or bad constitution of a State. I could show that among
these four kinds of inequality, personal qualities being the origin of all the others,
wealth is the one to which they are all reduced in the end; for, as riches tend most
immediately to the prosperity of individuals, and are easiest to communicate, they are
used to purchase every other distinction. By this observation we are enabled to judge
pretty exactly how far a people has departed from its primitive constitution, and of its
progress towards the extreme term of corruption. I could explain how much this
universal desire for reputation, honours and advancement, which inflames us all,
exercises and holds up to comparison our faculties and powers; how it excites and
multiplies our passions, and, by creating universal competition and rivalry, or rather
enmity, among men, occasions numberless failures, successes and disturbances of all
kinds by making so many aspirants run the same course. I could show that it is to this
desire of being talked about, and this unremitting rage of distinguishing ourselves,
that we owe the best and the worst things we possess, both our virtues and our vices,
our science and our errors, our conquerors and our philosophers; that is to say, a great
many bad things, and a very few good ones. In a word, I could prove that, if we have
a few rich and powerful men on the pinnacle of fortune and grandeur, while the crowd
grovels in want and obscurity, it is because the former prize what they enjoy only in
so far as others are destitute of it; and because, without changing their condition, they
would cease to be happy the moment the people ceased to be wretched.
These details alone, however, would furnish matter for a considerable work, in which
the advantages and disadvantages of every kind of government might be weighed, as
they are related to man in the state of nature, and at the same time all the different
aspects, under which inequality has up to the present appeared, or may appear in ages
yet to come, according to the nature of the several governments, and the alterations
which time must unavoidably occasion in them, might be demonstrated. We should
then see the multitude oppressed from within, in consequence of the very precautions
it had taken to guard against foreign tyranny. We should see oppression continually
gain ground without it being possible for the oppressed to know where it would stop,
or what legitimate means was left them of checking its progress. We should see the
rights of citizens, and the freedom of nations slowly extinguished, and the complaints,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
199
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
protests and appeals of the weak treated as seditious murmurings. We should see the
honour of defending the common cause confined by statecraft to a mercenary part of
the people. We should see taxes made necessary by such means, and the disheartened
husbandman deserting his fields even in the midst of peace, and leaving the plough to
gird on the sword. We should see fatal and capricious codes of honour established;
and the champions of their country sooner or later becoming its enemies, and for ever
holding their daggers to the breasts of their fellow-citizens. The time would come
when they would be heard saying to the oppressor of their country—
Pectore si fratris gladium juguloque parentis
Condere me jubeas, gravidæque in viscera partu
Conjugis, invitâ peragam tamen omnia dextrâ.
Lucan. i, 376.
From great inequality of fortunes and conditions, from the vast variety of passions and
of talents, of useless and pernicious arts, of vain sciences, would arise a multitude of
prejudices equally contrary to reason, happiness and virtue. We should see the
magistrates fomenting everything that might weaken men united in society, by
promoting dissension among them; everything that might sow in it the seeds of actual
division, while it gave society the air of harmony; everything that might inspire the
different ranks of people with mutual hatred and distrust, by setting the rights and
interests of one against those of another, and so strengthen the power which
comprehended them all.
It is from the midst of this disorder and these revolutions, that despotism, gradually
raising up its hideous head and devouring everything that remained sound and
untainted in any part of the State, would at length trample on both the laws and the
people, and establish itself on the ruins of the republic. The times which immediately
preceded this last change would be times of trouble and calamity; but at length the
monster would swallow up everything, and the people would no longer have either
chiefs or laws, but only tyrants. From this moment there would be no question of
virtue or morality; for despotism cui ex honesto nulla est spes, wherever it prevails,
admits no other master; it no sooner speaks than probity and duty lose their weight
and blind obedience is the only virtue which slaves can still practise.
This is the last term of inequality, the extreme point that closes the circle, and meets
that from which we set out. Here all private persons return to their first equality,
because they are nothing; and, subjects having no law but the will of their master, and
their master no restraint but his passions, all notions of good and all principles of
equity again vanish. There is here a complete return to the law of the strongest, and so
to a new state of nature, differing from that we set out from; for the one was a state of
nature in its first purity, while this is the consequence of excessive corruption. There
is so little difference between the two states in other respects, and the contract of
government is so completely dissolved by despotism, that the despot is master only so
long as he remains the strongest; as soon as he can be expelled, he has no right to
complain of violence. The popular insurrection that ends in the death or deposition of
a Sultan is as lawful an act as those by which he disposed, the day before, of the lives
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
200
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
and fortunes of his subjects. As he was maintained by force alone, it is force alone
that overthrows him. Thus everything takes place according to the natural order; and,
whatever may be the result of such frequent and precipitate revolutions, no one man
has reason to complain of the injustice of another, but only of his own ill-fortune or
indiscretion.
If the reader thus discovers and retraces the lost and forgotten road, by which man
must have passed from the state of nature to the state of society; if he carefully
restores, along with the intermediate situations which I have just described, those
which want of time has compelled me to suppress, or my imagination has failed to
suggest, he cannot fail to be struck by the vast distance which separates the two states.
It is in tracing this slow succession that he will find the solution of a number of
problems of politics and morals, which philosophers cannot settle. He will feel that,
men being different in different ages, the reason why Diogenes could not find a man
was that he sought among his contemporaries a man of an earlier period. He will see
that Cato died with Rome and liberty, because he did not fit the age in which he lived;
the greatest of men served only to astonish a world which he would certainly have
ruled, had he lived five hundred years sooner. In a word, he will explain how the soul
and the passions of men insensibly change their very nature; why our wants and
pleasures in the end seek new objects; and why, the original man having vanished by
degrees, society offers to us only an assembly of artificial men and factitious passions,
which are the work of all these new relations, and without any real foundation in
nature. We are taught nothing on this subject, by reflection, that is not entirely
confirmed by observation. The savage and the civilised man differ so much in the
bottom of their hearts and in their inclinations, that what constitutes the supreme
happiness of one would reduce the other to despair. The former breathes only peace
and liberty; he desires only to live and be free from labour; even the ataraxia of the
Stoic falls far short of his profound indifference to every other object. Civilised man,
on the other hand, is always moving, sweating, toiling and racking his brains to find
still more laborious occupations: he goes on in drudgery to his last moment, and even
seeks death to put himself in a position to live, or renounces life to acquire
immortality. He pays his court to men in power, whom he hates, and to the wealthy,
whom he despises; he stops at nothing to have the honour of serving them; he is not
ashamed to value himself on his own meanness and their protection; and, proud of his
slavery, he speaks with disdain of those, who have not the honour of sharing it. What
a sight would the perplexing and envied labours of a European minister of State
present to the eyes of a Caribean! How many cruel deaths would not this indolent
savage prefer to the horrors of such a life, which is seldom even sweetened by the
pleasure of doing good! But, for him to see into the motives of all this solicitude, the
words power and reputation, would have to bear some meaning in his mind; he would
have to know that there are men who set a value on the opinion of the rest of the
world; who can be made happy and satisfied with themselves rather on the testimony
of other people than on their own. In reality, the source of all these differences is, that
the savage lives within himself, while social man lives constantly outside himself, and
only knows how to live in the opinion of others, so that he seems to receive the
consciousness of his own existence merely from the judgment of others concerning
him. It is not to my present purpose to insist on the indifference to good and evil
which arises from this disposition, in spite of our many fine works on morality, or to
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
201
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
show how, everything being reduced to appearances, there is but art and mummery in
even honour, friendship, virtue, and often vice itself, of which we at length learn the
secret of boasting; to show, in short, how, always asking others what we are, and
never daring to ask ourselves, in the midst of so much philosophy, humanity and
civilisation, and of such sublime codes of morality, we have nothing to show for
ourselves but a frivolous and deceitful appearance, honour without virtue, reason
without wisdom, and pleasure without happiness. It is sufficient that I have proved
that this is not by any means the original state of man, but that it is merely the spirit of
society, and the inequality which society produces, that thus transform and alter all
our natural inclinations.
I have endeavoured to trace the origin and progress of inequality, and the institution
and abuse of political societies, as far as these are capable of being deduced from the
nature of man merely by the light of reason, and independently of those sacred
dogmas which give the sanction of divine right to sovereign authority. It follows from
this survey that, as there is hardly any inequality in the state of nature, all the
inequality which now prevails owes its strength and growth to the development of our
faculties and the advance of the human mind, and becomes at last permanent and
legitimate by the establishment of property and laws. Secondly, it follows that moral
inequality, authorised by positive right alone, clashes with natural right, whenever it is
not proportionate to physical inequality; a distinction which sufficiently determines
what we ought to think of that species of inequality which prevails in all civilised
countries; since it is plainly contrary to the law of nature, however defined, that
children should command old men, fools wise men, and that the privileged few should
gorge themselves with superfluities, while the starving multitude are in want of the
bare necessities of life.
APPENDIX1
A famous author, reckoning up the good and evil of human life, and comparing the
aggregates, finds that our pains greatly exceed our pleasures: so that, all things
considered, human life is not at all a valuable gift. This conclusion does not surprise
me; for the writer drew all his arguments from man in civilisation. Had he gone back
to the state of nature, his inquiries would clearly have had a different result, and man
would have been seen to be subject to very few evils not of his own creation. It has
indeed cost us not a little trouble to make ourselves as wretched as we are. When we
consider, on the one hand, the immense labours of mankind, the many sciences
brought to perfection, the arts invented, the powers employed, the deeps filled up, the
mountains levelled, the rocks shattered, the rivers made navigable, the tracts of land
cleared, the lakes emptied, the marshes drained, the enormous structures erected on
land, and the teeming vessels that cover the sea; and, on the other hand, estimate with
ever so little thought, the real advantages that have accrued from all these works to
mankind, we cannot help being amazed at the vast disproportion there is between
these things, and deploring the infatuation of man, which, to gratify his silly pride and
vain self-admiration, induces him eagerly to pursue all the miseries he is capable of
feeling, though beneficent nature had kindly placed them out of his way.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
202
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
That men are actually wicked, a sad and continual experience of them proves beyond
doubt: but, all the same, I think I have shown that man is naturally good. What then
can have depraved him to such an extent, except the changes that have happened in
his constitution, the advances he has made, and the knowledge he has acquired? We
may admire human society as much as we please; it will be none the less true that it
necessarily leads men to hate each other in proportion as their interests clash, and to
do one another apparent services, while they are really doing every imaginable
mischief. What can be thought of a relation, in which the interest of every individual
dictates rules directly opposite to those the public reason dictates to the community in
general—in which every man finds his profit in the misfortunes of his neighbour?
There is not perhaps any man in a comfortable position who has not greedy heirs, and
perhaps even children, secretly wishing for his death; not a ship at sea, of which the
loss would not be good news to some merchant or other; not a house, which some
debtor of bad faith would not be glad to see reduced to ashes with all the papers it
contains; not a nation which does not rejoice at the disasters that befall its neighbours.
Thus it is that we find our advantage in the misfortunes of our fellow-creatures, and
that the loss of one man almost always constitutes the prosperity of another. But it is
still more pernicious that public calamities are the objects of the hopes and
expectations of innumerable individuals. Some desire sickness, some mortality, some
war, and some famine. I have seen men wicked enough to weep for sorrow at the
prospect of a plentiful season; and the great and fatal fire of London, which cost so
many unhappy persons their lives or their fortunes, made the fortunes of perhaps ten
thousand others. I know that Montaigne censures Demades the Athenian for having
caused to be punished a workman who, by selling his coffins very dear, was a great
gainer by the deaths of his fellow-citizens; but, the reason alleged by Montaigne being
that everybody ought to be punished, my point is clearly confirmed by it. Let us
penetrate, therefore, the superficial appearances of benevolence, and survey what
passes in the inmost recesses of the heart. Let us reflect what must be the state of
things, when men are forced to caress and destroy one another at the same time; when
they are born enemies by duty, and knaves by interest. It will perhaps be said that
society is so formed that every man gains by serving the rest. That would be all very
well, if he did not gain still more by injuring them. There is no legitimate profit so
great, that it cannot be greatly exceeded by what may be made illegitimately; we
always gain more by hurting our neighbours than by doing them good. Nothing is
required but to know how to act with impunity; and to this end the powerful employ
all their strength, and the weak all their cunning.
Savage man, when he has dined, is at peace with all nature, and the friend of all his
fellow-creatures. If a dispute arises about a meal, he rarely comes to blows, without
having first compared the difficulty of conquering his antagonist with the trouble of
finding subsistence elsewhere: and, as pride does not come in, it all ends in a few
blows; the victor eats, and the vanquished seeks provision somewhere else, and all is
at peace. The case is quite different with man in the state of society, for whom first
necessaries have to be provided, and then superfluities; delicacies follow next, then
immense wealth, then subjects, and then slaves. He enjoys not a moment’s relaxation;
and what is yet stranger, the less natural and pressing his wants, the more headstrong
are his passions, and, still worse, the more he has it in his power to gratify them; so
that after a long course of prosperity, after having swallowed up treasures and ruined
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
203
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
multitudes, the hero ends up by cutting every throat till he finds himself, at last, sole
master of the world. Such is in miniature the moral picture, if not of human life, at
least of the secret pretensions of the heart of civilised man.
Compare without partiality the state of the citizen with that of the savage, and trace
out, if you can, how many inlets the former has opened to pain and death, besides
those of his vices, his wants and his misfortunes. If you reflect on the mental
afflictions that prey on us, the violent passions that waste and exhaust us, the
excessive labour with which the poor are burdened, the still more dangerous
indolence to which the wealthy give themselves up, so that the poor perish of want,
and the rich of surfeit; if you reflect but a moment on the heterogeneous mixtures and
pernicious seasonings of foods; the corrupt state in which they are frequently eaten;
on the adulteration of medicines, the wiles of those who sell them, the mistakes of
those who administer them, and the poisonous vessels in which they are prepared; on
the epidemics bred by foul air in consequence of great numbers of men being crowded
together, or those which are caused by our delicate way of living, by our passing from
our houses into the open air and back again, by the putting on or throwing off our
clothes with too little care, and by all the precautions which sensuality has converted
into necessary habits, and the neglect of which sometimes costs us our life or health;
if you take into account the conflagrations and earthquakes, which, devouring or
overwhelming whole cities, destroy the inhabitants by thousands; in a word, if you
add together all the dangers with which these causes are always threatening us, you
will see how dearly nature makes us pay for the contempt with which we have treated
her lessons.
I shall not here repeat, what I have elsewhere said of the calamities of war; but wish
that those, who have sufficient knowledge, were willing or bold enough to make
public the details of the villainies committed in armies by the contractors for
commissariat and hospitals: we should see plainly that their monstrous frauds, already
none too well concealed, which cripple the finest armies in less than no time, occasion
greater destruction among the soldiers than the swords of the enemy.
The number of people who perish annually at sea, by famine, the scurvy, pirates, fire
and shipwrecks, affords matter for another shocking calculation. We must also place
to the credit of the establishment of property, and consequently to the institution of
society, assassinations, poisonings, highway robberies, and even the punishments
inflicted on the wretches guilty of these crimes; which, though expedient to prevent
greater evils, yet by making the murder of one man cost the lives of two or more,
double the loss to the human race.
What shameful methods are sometimes practised to prevent the birth of men, and
cheat nature; either by brutal and depraved appetites which insult her most beautiful
work—appetites unknown to savages or mere animals, which can spring only from
the corrupt imagination of mankind in civilised countries; or by secret abortions, the
fitting effects of debauchery and vitiated notions of honour; or by the exposure or
murder of multitudes of infants, who fall victims to the poverty of their parents, or the
cruel shame of their mothers; or, finally, by the mutilation of unhappy wretches, part
of whose life, with their hope of posterity, is given up to vain singing, or, still worse,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
204
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
the brutal jealousy of other men: a mutilation which, in the last case, becomes a
double outrage against nature from the treatment of those who suffer it, and from the
use to which they are destined. But is it not a thousand times more common and more
dangerous for paternal rights openly to offend against humanity? How many talents
have not been thrown away, and inclinations forced, by the unwise constraint of
fathers? How many men, who would have distinguished themselves in a fitting estate,
have died dishonoured and wretched in another for which they had no taste! How
many happy, but unequal, marriages have been broken or disturbed, and how many
chaste wives have been dishonoured, by an order of things continually in
contradiction with that of nature! How many good and virtuous husbands and wives
are reciprocally punished for having been ill-assorted! How many young and unhappy
victims of their parents’ avarice plunge into vice, or pass their melancholy days in
tears, groaning in the indissoluble bonds which their hearts repudiate and gold alone
has formed! Fortunate sometimes are those whose courage and virtue remove them
from life before inhuman violence makes them spend it in crime or in despair. Forgive
me, father and mother, whom I shall ever regret: my complaint embitters your griefs;
but would they might be an eternal and terrible example to every one who dares, in
the name of nature, to violate her most sacred right.
If I have spoken only of those ill-starred unions which are the result of our system, is
it to be thought that those over which love and sympathy preside are free from
disadvantages? What if I should undertake to show humanity attacked in its very
source, and even in the most sacred of all ties, in which fortune is consulted before
nature, and, the disorders of society confounding all virtue and vice, continence
becomes a criminal precaution, and a refusal to give life to a fellow-creature, an act of
humanity? But, without drawing aside the veil which hides all these horrors, let us
content ourselves with pointing out the evil which others will have to remedy.
To all this add the multiplicity of unhealthy trades, which shorten men’s lives or
destroy their bodies, such as working in the mines, and the preparing of metals and
minerals, particularly lead, copper, mercury, cobalt, and arsenic: add those other
dangerous trades which are daily fatal to many tilers, carpenters, masons and miners:
put all these together and we can see, in the establishment and perfection of societies,
the reasons for that diminution of our species, which has been noticed by many
philosophers.
Luxury, which cannot be prevented among men who are tenacious of their own
convenience and of the respect paid them by others, soon completes the evil society
had begun, and, under the pretence of giving bread to the poor, whom it should never
have made such, impoverishes all the rest, and sooner or later depopulates the State.
Luxury is a remedy much worse than the disease it sets up to cure; or rather it is in
itself the greatest of all evils, for every State, great or small: for, in order to maintain
all the servants and vagabonds it creates, it brings oppression and ruin on the citizen
and the labourer; it is like those scorching winds, which, covering the trees and plants
with devouring insects, deprive useful animals of their subsistence and spread famine
and death wherever they blow.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
205
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
From society and the luxury to which it gives birth arise the liberal and mechanical
arts, commerce, letters, and all those superfluities which make industry flourish, and
enrich and ruin nations. The reason for such destruction is plain. It is easy to see, from
the very nature of agriculture, that it must be the least lucrative of all the arts; for, its
produce being the most universally necessary, the price must be proportionate to the
abilities of the very poorest of mankind.
From the same principle may be deduced this rule, that the arts in general are more
lucrative in proportion as they are less useful; and that, in the end, the most useful
becomes the most neglected. From this we may learn what to think of the real
advantages of industry and the actual effects of its progress.
Such are the sensible causes of all the miseries, into which opulence at length plunges
the most celebrated nations. In proportion as arts and industry flourish, the despised
husbandman, burdened with the taxes necessary for the support of luxury, and
condemned to pass his days between labour and hunger, forsakes his native field, to
seek in towns the bread he ought to carry thither. The more our capital cities strike the
vulgar eye with admiration, the greater reason is there to lament the sight of the
abandoned countryside, the large tracts of land that lie uncultivated, the roads
crowded with unfortunate citizens turned beggars or highwaymen, and doomed to end
their wretched lives either on a dunghill or on the gallows. Thus the State grows rich
on the one hand, and feeble and depopulated on the other; the mightiest monarchies,
after having taken immense pains to enrich and depopulate themselves, fall at last a
prey to some poor nation, which has yielded to the fatal temptation of invading them,
and then, growing opulent and weak in its turn, is itself invaded and ruined by some
other.
Let any one inform us what produced the swarms of barbarians, who overran Europe,
Asia and Africa for so many ages. Was their prodigious increase due to their industry
and arts, to the wisdom of their laws, or to the excellence of their political system? Let
the learned tell us why, instead of multiplying to such a degree, these fierce and brutal
men, without sense or science, without education, without restraint, did not destroy
each other hourly in quarrelling over the productions of their fields and woods. Let
them tell us how these wretches could have the presumption to oppose such clever
people as we were, so well trained in military discipline, and possessed of such
excellent laws and institutions: and why, since society has been brought to perfection
in northern countries, and so much pains taken to instruct their inhabitants in their
social duties and in the art of living happily and peaceably together, we see them no
longer produce such numberless hosts as they used once to send forth to be the plague
and terror of other nations. I fear some one may at last answer me by saying, that all
these fine things, arts, sciences and laws, were wisely invented by men, as a salutary
plague, to prevent the too great multiplication of mankind, lest the world, which was
given us for a habitation, should in time be too small for its inhabitants.
What, then, is to be done? Must societies be totally abolished? Must meum and tuum
be annihilated, and must we return again to the forests to live among bears? This is a
deduction in the manner of my adversaries, which I would as soon anticipate as let
them have the shame of drawing. O you, who have never heard the voice of heaven,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
206
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
who think man destined only to live this little life and die in peace; you, who can
resign in the midst of populous cities your fatal acquisitions, your restless spirits, your
corrupt hearts and endless desires; resume, since it depends entirely on yourselves,
your ancient and primitive innocence: retire to the woods, there to lose the sight and
remembrance of the crimes of your contemporaries; and be not apprehensive of
degrading your species, by renouncing its advances in order to renounce its vices. As
for men like me, whose passions have destroyed their original simplicity, who can no
longer subsist on plants or acorns, or live without laws and magistrates; those who
were honoured in their first father with supernatural instructions; those who discover,
in the design of giving human actions at the start a morality which they must
otherwise have been so long in acquiring, the reason for a precept in itself indifferent
and inexplicable on every other system; those, in short, who are persuaded that the
Divine Being has called all mankind to be partakers in the happiness and perfection of
celestial intelligences, all these will endeavour to merit the eternal prize they are to
expect from the practice of those virtues, which they make themselves follow in
learning to know them. They will respect the sacred bonds of their respective
communities; they will love their fellow-citizens, and serve them with all their might:
they will scrupulously obey the laws, and all those who make or administer them;
they will particularly honour those wise and good princes, who find means of
preventing, curing or even palliating all these evils and abuses, by which we are
constantly threatened; they will animate the zeal of their deserving rulers, by showing
them, without flattery or fear, the importance of their office and the severity of their
duty. But they will not therefore have less contempt for a constitution that cannot
support itself without the aid of so many splendid characters, much oftener wished for
than found; and from which, notwithstanding all their pains and solicitude, there
always arise more real calamities than even apparent advantages.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
207
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[Back to Table of Contents]
A DISCOURSE ON POLITICAL ECONOMY
A DISCOURSE ON POLITICAL ECONOMY
The word Economy, or Œconomy, is derived from ο?κός, a house, and νόμος, law,
and meant originally only the wise and legitimate government of the house for the
common good of the whole family. The meaning of the term was then extended to the
government of that great family, the State. To distinguish these two senses of the
word, the latter is called general or political economy, and the former domestic or
particular economy. The first only is discussed in the present discourse.
Even if there were as close an analogy as many authors maintain between the State
and the family, it would not follow that the rules of conduct proper for one of these
societies would be also proper for the other. They differ too much in extent to be
regulated in the same manner; and there will always be a great difference between
domestic government, in which a father can see everything for himself, and civil
government, where the chief sees hardly anything save through the eyes of others. To
put both on an equality in this respect, the talents, strength, and all the faculties of the
father would have to increase in proportion to the size of his family, and the soul of a
powerful monarch would have to be, to that of an ordinary man, as the extent of his
empire is to that of a private person’s estate.
But how could the government of the State be like that of the family, when the basis
on which they rest is so different? The father being physically stronger than his
children, his paternal authority, as long as they need his protection, may be reasonably
said to be established by nature. But in the great family, all the members of which are
naturally equal, the political authority, being purely arbitrary as far as its institution is
concerned, can be founded only on conventions, and the Magistrate can have no
authority over the rest, except by virtue of the laws. The duties of a father are dictated
to him by natural feelings, and in a manner that seldom allows him to neglect them.
For rulers there is no such principle, and they are really obliged to the people only by
what they themselves have promised to do, and the people have therefore a right to
require of them. Another more important difference is that since the children have
nothing but what they receive from their father, it is plain that all the rights of
property belong to him, or emanate from him; but quite the opposite is the case in the
great family, where the general administration is established only to secure individual
property, which is antecedent to it. The principal object of the work of the whole
house is to preserve and increase the patrimony of the father, in order that he may be
able some day to distribute it among his children without impoverishing them;
whereas the wealth of the exchequer is only a means, often ill understood, of keeping
the individuals in peace and plenty. In a word, the little family is destined to be
extinguished, and to resolve itself some day into several families of a similar nature;
but the great family, being constituted to endure for ever in the same condition, need
not, like the small one, increase for the purpose of multiplying, but need only
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
208
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
maintain itself; and it can easily be proved that any increase does it more harm than
good.
In the family, it is clear, for several reasons which lie in its very nature, that the father
ought to command. In the first place, the authority ought not to be equally divided
between father and mother; the government must be single, and in every division of
opinion there must be one preponderant voice to decide. Secondly, however lightly
we may regard the disadvantages peculiar to women, yet, as they necessarily occasion
intervals of inaction, this is a sufficient reason for excluding them from this supreme
authority: for when the balance is perfectly even, a straw is enough to turn the scale.
Besides, the husband ought to be able to superintend his wife’s conduct, because it is
of importance for him to be assured that the children, whom he is obliged to
acknowledge and maintain, belong to no-one but himself. Thirdly, children should be
obedient to their father, at first of necessity, and afterwards from gratitude: after
having had their wants satisfied by him during one half of their lives, they ought to
consecrate the other half to providing for his. Fourthly, servants owe him their
services in exchange for the provision he makes for them, though they may break off
the bargain as soon as it ceases to suit them. I say nothing here of slavery, because it
is contrary to nature, and cannot be authorised by any right or law.
There is nothing of all this in political society, in which the chief is so far from having
any natural interest in the happiness of the individuals, that it is not uncommon for
him to seek his own in their misery. If the magistracy is hereditary, a community of
men is often governed by a child. If it be elective, innumerable inconveniences arise
from such election; while in both cases all the advantages of paternity are lost. If you
have but a single ruler, you lie at the discretion of a master who has no reason to love
you: and if you have several, you must bear at once their tyranny and their divisions.
In a word, abuses are inevitable and their consequences fatal in every society where
the public interest and the laws have no natural force, and are perpetually attacked by
personal interest and the passions of the ruler and the members.
Although the functions of the father of a family and those of the chief magistrate
ought to make for the same object, they must do so in such different ways, and their
duty and rights are so essentially distinct, that we cannot confound them without
forming very false ideas about the fundamental laws of society, and falling into errors
which are fatal to mankind. In fact, if the voice of nature is the best counsellor to
which a father can listen in the discharge of his duty, for the Magistrate it is a false
guide, which continually prevents him from performing his, and leads him on sooner
or later to the ruin of himself and of the State, if he is not restrained by the most
sublime virtue. The only precaution necessary for the father of a family is to guard
himself against depravity, and prevent his natural inclinations from being corrupted;
whereas it is these themselves which corrupt the Magistrate. In order to act aright, the
first has only to consult his heart; the other becomes a traitor the moment he listens to
his. Even his own reason should be suspect to him, nor should he follow any rule
other than the public reason, which is the law. Thus nature has made a multitude of
good fathers of families; but it is doubtful whether, from the very beginning of the
world, human wisdom has made ten men capable of governing their peers.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
209
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
From all that has just been said, it follows that public economy, which is my subject,
has been rightly distinguished from private economy, and that, the State having
nothing in common with the family except the obligations which their heads lie under
of making both of them happy, the same rules of conduct cannot apply to both. I have
considered these few lines enough to overthrow the detestable system which Sir
Robert Filmer has endeavoured to establish in his Patriarcha; a work to which two
celebrated writers have done too much honour in writing books to refute it. Moreover,
this error is of very long standing; for Aristotle himself thought proper to combat it
with arguments which may be found in the first book of his Politics.
I must here ask my readers to distinguish also between public economy, which is my
subject and which I call government, and the supreme authority, which I call
Sovereignty; a distinction which consists in the fact that the latter has the right of
legislation, and in certain cases binds the body of the nation itself, while the former
has only the right of execution, and is binding only on individuals.
I shall take the liberty of making use of a very common, and in some respects
inaccurate, comparison, which will serve to illustrate my meaning.
The body politic, taken individually, may be considered as an organised, living body,
resembling that of man. The sovereign power represents the head; the laws and
customs are the brain, the source of the nerves and seat of the understanding, will and
senses, of which the Judges and Magistrates are the organs: commerce, industry, and
agriculture are the mouth and stomach which prepare the common subsistence; the
public income is the blood, which a prudent economy, in performing the functions of
the heart, causes to distribute through the whole body nutriment and life: the citizens
are the body and the members, which make the machine live, move and work; and no
part of this machine can be damaged without the painful impression being at once
conveyed to the brain, if the animal is in a state of health.
The life of both bodies is the self common to the whole, the reciprocal sensibility and
internal correspondence of all the parts. Where this communication ceases, where the
formal unity disappears, and the contiguous parts belong to one another only by
juxtaposition, the man is dead, or the State is dissolved.
The body politic, therefore, is also a moral being possessed of a will; and this general
will, which tends always to the preservation and welfare of the whole and of every
part, and is the source of the laws, constitutes for all the members of the State, in their
relations to one another and to it, the rule of what is just or unjust: a truth which
shows, by the way, how idly some writers have treated as theft the subtlety prescribed
to children at Sparta for obtaining their frugal repasts, as if everything ordained by the
law were not lawful.
It is important to observe that this rule of justice, though certain with regard to all
citizens, may be defective with regard to foreigners. The reason is clear. The will of
the State, though general in relation to its own members, is no longer so in relation to
other States and their members, but becomes, for them, a particular and individual
will, which has its rule of justice in the law of nature. This, however, enters equally
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
210
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
into the principle here laid down; for in such a case, the great city of the world
becomes the body politic, whose general will is always the law of nature, and of
which the different States and peoples are individual members. From these
distinctions, applied to each political society and its members, are derived the most
certain and universal rules, by which we can judge whether a government is good or
bad, and in general of the morality of all human actions.
Every political society is composed of other smaller societies of different kinds, each
of which has its interests and its rules of conduct: but those societies which everybody
perceives, because they have an external and authorised form, are not the only ones
that actually exist in the State: all individuals who are united by a common interest
compose as many others, either transitory or permanent, whose influence is none the
less real because it is less apparent, and the proper observation of whose various
relations is the true knowledge of public morals and manners. The influence of all
these tacit or formal associations causes, by the influence of their will, as many
different modifications of the public will. The will of these particular societies has
always two relations; for the members of the association, it is a general will; for the
great society, it is a particular will; and it is often right with regard to the first object,
and wrong as to the second. An individual may be a devout priest, a brave soldier, or a
zealous senator, and yet a bad citizen. A particular resolution may be advantageous to
the smaller community, but pernicious to the greater. It is true that particular societies
being always subordinate to the general society in preference to others, the duty of a
citizen takes precedence of that of a senator, and a man’s duty of that of a citizen: but
unhappily personal interest is always found in inverse ratio to duty, and increases in
proportion as the association grows narrower, and the engagement less sacred; which
irrefragably proves that the most general will is always the must just also, and that the
voice of the people is in fact the voice of God.
It does not follow that the public decisions are always equitable; they may possibly,
for reasons which I have given, not be so when they have to do with foreigners. Thus
it is not impossible that a Republic, though in itself well governed, should enter upon
an unjust war. Nor is it less possible for the Council of a Democracy to pass unjust
decrees, and condemn the innocent; but this never happens unless the people is
seduced by private interests, which the credit or eloquence of some clever persons
substitutes for those of the State: in which case the general will will be one thing, and
the result of the public deliberation another. This is not contradicted by the case of the
Athenian Democracy; for Athens was in fact not a Democracy, but a very tyrannical
Aristocracy, governed by philosophers and orators. Carefully determine what happens
in every public deliberation, and it will be seen that the general will is always for the
common good; but very often there is a secret division, a tacit confederacy, which, for
particular ends, causes the natural disposition of the assembly to be set at nought. In
such a case the body of society is really divided into other bodies, the members of
which acquire a general will, which is good and just with respect to these new bodies,
but unjust and bad with regard to the whole, from which each is thus dismembered.
We see then how easy it is, by the help of these principles, to explain those apparent
contradictions, which are noticed in the conduct of many persons who are
scrupulously honest in some respects, and cheats and scoundrels in others, who
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
211
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
trample under foot the most sacred duties, and yet are faithful to the death to
engagements that are often illegitimate. Thus the most depraved of men always pay
some sort of homage to public faith; and even robbers, who are the enemies of virtue
in the great society, pay some respect to the shadow of it in their secret caves.
In establishing the general will as the first principle of public economy, and the
fundamental rule of government, I have not thought it necessary to inquire seriously
whether the Magistrates belong to the people, or the people to the Magistrates; or
whether in public affairs the good of the State should be taken into account, or only
that of its rulers. That question indeed has long been decided one way in theory, and
another in practice; and in general it would be ridiculous to expect that those who are
in fact masters will prefer any other interest to their own. It would not be improper,
therefore, further to distinguish public economy as popular or tyrannical. The former
is that of every State, in which there reigns between the people and the rulers unity of
interest and will: the latter will necessarily exist wherever the government and the
people have different interests, and, consequently, opposing wills. The rules of the
latter are written at length in the archives of history, and in the satires of Macchiavelli.
The rules of the former are found only in the writings of those philosophers who
venture to proclaim the rights of humanity.
I. The first and most important rule of legitimate or popular government, that is to say,
of government whose object is the good of the people, is therefore, as I have
observed, to follow in everything the general will. But to follow this will it is
necessary to know it, and above all to distinguish it from the particular will, beginning
with one’s self: this distinction is always very difficult to make, and only the most
sublime virtue can afford sufficient illumination for it. As, in order to will, it is
necessary to be free, a difficulty no less great than the former arises—that of
preserving at once the public liberty and the authority of government. Look into the
motives which have induced men, once united by their common needs in a general
society, to unite themselves still more intimately by means of civil societies: you will
find no other motive than that of assuring the property, life and liberty of each
member by the protection of all. But can men be forced to defend the liberty of any
one among them, without trespassing on that of others? And how can they provide for
the public needs, without alienating the individual property of those who are forced to
contribute to them? With whatever sophistry all this may be covered over, it is certain
that if any constraint can be laid on my will, I am no longer free, and that I am no
longer master of my own property, if any one else can lay a hand on it. This difficulty,
which would have seemed insurmountable, has been removed, like the first, by the
most sublime of all human institutions, or rather by a divine inspiration, which
teaches mankind to imitate here below the unchangeable decrees of the Deity. By
what inconceivable art has a means been found of making men free by making them
subject; of using in the service of the State the properties, the persons and even the
lives of all its members, without constraining and without consulting them; of
confining their will by their own admission; of overcoming their refusal by that
consent, and forcing them to punish themselves, when they act against their own will?
How can it be that all should obey, yet nobody take upon him to command, and that
all should serve, and yet have no masters, but be the more free, as, in apparent
subjection, each loses no part of his liberty but what might be hurtful to that of
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
212
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
another? These wonders are the work of law. It is to law alone that men owe justice
and liberty. It is this salutary organ of the will of all which establishes, in civil right,
the natural equality between men. It is this celestial voice which dictates to each
citizen the precepts of public reason, and teaches him to act according to the rules of
his own judgment, and not to behave inconsistently with himself. It is with this voice
alone that political rulers should speak when they command; for no sooner does one
man, setting aside the law, claim to subject another to his private will, than he departs
from the state of civil society, and confronts him face to face in the pure state of
nature, in which obedience is prescribed solely by necessity.
The most pressing interest of the ruler, and even his most indispensable duty,
therefore, is to watch over the observation of the laws of which he is the minister, and
on which his whole authority is founded. At the same time, if he exacts the
observance of them from others, he is the more strongly bound to observe them
himself, since he enjoys all their favour. For his example is of such force, that even if
the people were willing to permit him to release himself from the yoke of the law, he
ought to be cautious in availing himself of so dangerous a prerogative, which others
might soon claim to usurp in their turn, and often use to his prejudice. At bottom, as
all social engagements are mutual in nature, it is impossible for any one to set himself
above the law, without renouncing its advantages; for nobody is bound by any
obligation to one who claims that he is under no obligations to others. For this reason
no exemption from the law will ever be granted, on any ground whatsoever, in a well-
regulated government. Those citizens who have deserved well of their country ought
to be rewarded with honours, but never with privileges: for the Republic is at the eve
of its fall, when any one can think it fine not to obey the laws. If the nobility or the
soldiery should ever adopt such a maxim, all would be lost beyond redemption.
The power of the laws depends still more on their own wisdom than on the severity of
their administrators, and the public will derives its greatest weight from the reason
which has dictated it. Hence Plato looked upon it as a very necessary precaution to
place at the head of all edicts a preamble, setting forth their justice and utility. In fact,
the first of all laws is to respect the laws: the severity of penalties is only a vain
resource, invented by little minds in order to substitute terror for that respect which
they have no means of obtaining. It has constantly been observed that in those
countries where legal punishments are most severe, they are also most frequent; so
that the cruelty of such punishments is a proof only of the multitude of criminals, and,
punishing everything with equal severity, induces those who are guilty to commit
crimes, in order to escape being punished for their faults.
But though the government be not master of the law, it is much to be its guarantor,
and to possess a thousand means of inspiring the love of it. In this alone the talent of
reigning consists. With force in one’s hands, there is no art required to make the
whole world tremble, nor indeed much to gain men’s hearts; for experience has long
since taught the people to give its rulers great credit for all the evil they abstain from
doing it, and to adore them if they do not absolutely hate it. A fool, if he be obeyed,
may punish crimes as well as another: but the true statesman is he who knows how to
prevent them: it is over the wills, even more than the actions, of his subjects that his
honourable rule is extended. If he could secure that every one should act aright, he
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
213
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
would no longer have anything to do; and the masterpiece of his labours would be to
be able to remain unemployed. It is certain, at least, that the greatest talent a ruler can
possess is to disguise his power, in order to render it less odious, and to conduct the
State so peaceably as to make it seem to have no need of conductors.
I conclude, therefore, that, as the first duty of the legislator is to make the laws
conformable to the general will, the first rule of public economy is that the
administration of justice should be conformable to the laws. It will even be enough to
prevent the State from being ill governed, that the Legislator shall have provided, as
he should, for every need of place, climate, soil, custom, neighbourhood, and all the
rest of the relations peculiar to the people he had to institute. Not but what there still
remains an infinity of details of administration and economy, which are left to the
wisdom of the government: but there are two infallible rules for its good conduct on
these occasions; one is, that the spirit of the law ought to decide in every particular
case that could not be foreseen; the other is that the general will, the source and
supplement of all laws, should be consulted wherever they fail. But how, I shall be
asked, can the general will be known in cases in which it has not expressed itself?
Must the whole nation be assembled together at every unforeseen event? Certainly
not. It ought the less to be assembled, because it is by no means certain that its
decision would be the expression of the general will; besides, the method would be
impracticable in a great people, and is hardly ever necessary where the government is
well-intentioned: for the rulers well know that the general will is always on the side
which is most favourable to the public interest, that is to say, most equitable; so that it
is needful only to act justly, to be certain of following the general will. When this is
flouted too openly, it makes itself felt, in spite of the formidable restraint of the public
authority. I shall cite the nearest possible examples that may be followed in such
cases.
In China, it is the constant maxim of the Prince to decide against his officers, in every
dispute that arises between them and the people. If bread be too dear in any province,
the Intendant of that province is thrown into prison. If there be an insurrection in
another, the Governor is dismissed, and every Mandarin answers with his head for all
the mischief that happens in his department. Not that these affairs do not subsequently
undergo a regular examination; but long experience has caused the judgment to be
thus anticipated. There is seldom any injustice to be repaired; in the meantime, the
Emperor, being satisfied that public outcry does not arise without cause, always
discovers, through the seditious clamours which he punishes, just grievances to
redress.
It is a great thing to preserve the rule of peace and order through all the parts of the
Republic; it is a great thing that the State should be tranquil, and the law respected:
but if nothing more is done, there will be in all this more appearance than reality; for
that government which confines itself to mere obedience will find difficulty in getting
itself obeyed. If it is good to know how to deal with men as they are, it is much better
to make them what there is need that they should be. The most absolute authority is
that which penetrates into a man’s inmost being, and concerns itself no less with his
will than with his actions. It is certain that all peoples become in the long run what the
government makes them; warriors, citizens, men, when it so pleases; or merely
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
214
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
populace and rabble, when it chooses to make them so. Hence every prince who
despises his subjects, dishonours himself, in confessing that he does not know how to
make them worthy of respect. Make men, therefore, if you would command men: if
you would have them obedient to the laws, make them love the laws, and then they
will need only to know what is their duty to do it. This was the great art of ancient
governments, in those distant times when philosophers gave laws to men, and made
use of their authority only to render them wise and happy. Thence arose the numerous
sumptuary laws, the many regulations of morals, and all the public rules of conduct
which were admitted or rejected with the greatest care. Even tyrants did not forget this
important part of administration, but took as great pains to corrupt the morals of their
slaves, as Magistrates took to correct those of their fellow-citizens. But our modern
governments, which imagine they have done everything when they have raised
money, conceive that it is unnecessary and even impossible to go a step further.
II. The second essential rule of public economy is no less important than the first. If
you would have the general will accomplished, bring all the particular wills into
conformity with it; in other words, as virtue is nothing more than this conformity of
the particular wills with the general will, establish the reign of virtue.
If our politicians were less blinded by their ambition, they would see how impossible
it is for any establishment whatever to act in the spirit of its institution, unless it is
guided in accordance with the law of duty; they would feel that the greatest support of
public authority lies in the hearts of the citizens, and that nothing can take the place of
morality in the maintenance of government. It is not only upright men who know how
to administer the laws; but at bottom only good men know how to obey them. The
man who once gets the better of remorse, will not shrink before punishments which
are less severe, and less lasting, and from which there is at least the hope of escaping:
whatever precautions are taken, those who only require impunity in order to do wrong
will not fail to find means of eluding the law, and avoiding its penalties. In this case,
as all particular interests unite against the general interest, which is no longer that of
any individual, public vices have a greater effect in enervating the laws than the laws
in the repression of such vices: so that the corruption of the people and of their rulers
will at length extend to the government, however wise it may be. The worst of all
abuses is to pay an apparent obedience to the laws, only in order actually to break
them with security. For in this case the best laws soon become the most pernicious;
and it would be a hundred times better that they should not exist. In such a situation, it
is vain to add edicts to edicts and regulations to regulations. Everything serves only to
introduce new abuses, without correcting the old. The more laws are multiplied, the
more they are despised, and all the new officials appointed to supervise them are only
so many more people to break them, and either to share the plunder with their
predecessors, or to plunder apart on their own. The reward of virtue soon becomes
that of robbery; the vilest of men rise to the greatest credit; the greater they are the
more despicable they become; their infamy appears even in their dignities, and their
very honours dishonour them. If they buy the influence of the leaders or the protection
of women, it is only that they may sell justice, duty, and the State in their turn: in the
meantime, the people, feeling that its vices are not the first cause of its misfortunes,
murmurs and complains that all its misfortunes come solely from those whom it pays
to protect it from such things.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
215
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
It is under these circumstances that the voice of duty no longer speaks in men’s hearts,
and their rulers are obliged to substitute the cry of terror, or the lure of an apparent
interest, of which they subsequently trick their creatures. In this situation they are
compelled to have recourse to all the petty and despicable shifts which they call rules
of State and mysteries of the cabinet. All the vigour that is left in the government is
used by its members in ruining and supplanting one another, while the public business
is neglected, or is transacted only as personal interest requires and directs. In short,
the whole art of those great politicians lies in so mesmerising those they stand in need
of, that each may think he is labouring for his own interest in working for theirs: I say
theirs on the false supposition that it is the real interest of rulers to annihilate a people
in order to make it subject, and to ruin their own property in order to secure their
possession of it.
But when the citizens love their duty, and the guardians of the public authority
sincerely apply themselves to the fostering of that love by their own example and
assiduity, every difficulty vanishes; and government becomes so easy that it needs
none of that art of darkness, whose blackness is its only mystery. Those enterprising
spirits, so dangerous and so much admired, all those great ministers, whose glory is
inseparable from the miseries of the people, are no longer regretted: public morality
supplies what is wanting in the genius of the rulers; and the more virtue reigns, the
less need there is for talent. Even ambition is better served by duty than by usurpation:
when the people is convinced that its rulers are labouring only for its happiness, its
deference saves them the trouble of labouring to strengthen their power: and history
shows us, in a thousand cases, that the authority of one who is beloved over those
whom he loves is a hundred times more absolute than all the tyranny of usurpers. This
does not mean that the government ought to be afraid to make use of its power, but
that it ought to make use of it only in a lawful manner. We find in history a thousand
examples of pusillanimous or ambitious rulers, who were ruined by their slackness or
their pride; not one who suffered for having been strictly just. But we ought not to
confound negligence with moderation, or clemency with weakness. To be just, it is
necessary to be severe; to permit vice, when one has the right and the power to
suppress it, is to be oneself vicious.
It is not enough to say to the citizens, be good; they must be taught to be so; and even
example, which is in this respect the first lesson, is not the sole means to be
employed; patriotism is the most efficacious: for, as I have said already, every man is
virtuous when his particular will is in all things conformable to the general will, and
we voluntarily will what is willed by those whom we love. It appears that the feeling
of humanity evaporates and grows feeble in embracing all mankind, and that we
cannot be affected by the calamities of Tartary or Japan, in the same manner as we are
by those of European nations. It is necessary in some degree to confine and limit our
interest and compassion in order to make it active. Now, as this sentiment can be
useful only to those with whom we have to live, it is proper that our humanity should
confine itself to our fellow-citizens, and should receive a new force because we are in
the habit of seeing them, and by reason of the common interest which unites them. It
is certain that the greatest miracles of virtue have been produced by patriotism: this
fine and lively feeling, which gives to the force of self-love all the beauty of virtue,
lends it an energy which, without disfiguring it, makes it the most heroic of all
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
216
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
passions. This it is that produces so many immortal actions, the glory of which
dazzles our feeble eyes; and so many great men, whose old-world virtues pass for
fables now that patriotism is made mock of. This is not surprising; the transports of
susceptible hearts appear altogether fanciful to any one who has never felt them; and
the love of one’s country, which is a hundred times more lively and delightful than the
love of a mistress, cannot be conceived except by experiencing it. But it is easy to
perceive in every heart that is warmed by it, in all the actions it inspires, a glowing
and sublime ardour which does not attend the purest virtue, when separated from it.
Contrast Socrates even with Cato; the one was the greater philosopher, the other more
of the citizen. Athens was already ruined in the time of Socrates, and he had no other
country than the world at large. Cato had the cause of his country always at heart; he
lived for it alone, and could not bear to outlive it. The virtue of Socrates was that of
the wisest of men; but, compared with Cæsar and Pompey, Cato seems a God among
mortals. Socrates instructed a few individuals, opposed the Sophists, and died for
truth: but Cato defended his country, its liberty and its laws, against the conquerors of
the world, and at length departed from the earth, when he had no longer a country to
serve. A worthy pupil of Socrates would be the most virtuous of his contemporaries;
but a worthy follower of Cato would be one of the greatest. The virtue of the former
would be his happiness; the latter would seek his happiness in that of all. We should
be taught by the one, and led by the other; and this alone is enough to determine
which to prefer: for no people has ever been made into a nation of philosophers, but it
is not impossible to make a people happy.
Do we wish men to be virtuous? Then let us begin by making them love their country:
but how can they love it, if their country be nothing more to them than to strangers,
and afford them nothing but what it can refuse nobody? It would be still worse, if they
did not enjoy even the privilege of social security, and if their lives, liberties and
property lay at the mercy of persons in power, without their being permitted, or it
being possible for them, to get relief from the laws. For in that case, being subjected
to the duties of the state of civil society, without enjoying even the common privileges
of the state of nature, and without being able to use their strength in their own
defence, they would be in the worst condition in which freemen could possibly find
themselves, and the word country would mean for them something merely odious and
ridiculous. It must not be imagined that a man can break or lose an arm, without the
pain being conveyed to his head: nor is it any more credible that the general will
should consent that any one member of the State, whoever he might be, should wound
or destroy another, than it is that the fingers of a man in his senses should wilfully
scratch his eyes out. The security of individuals is so intimately connected with the
public confederation that, apart from the regard that must be paid to human weakness,
that convention would in point of right be dissolved, if in the State a single citizen
who might have been relieved were allowed to perish, or if one were wrongfully
confined in prison, or if in one case an obviously unjust sentence were given. For the
fundamental conventions being broken, it is impossible to conceive of any right or
interest that could retain the people in the social union; unless they were restrained by
force, which alone causes the dissolution of the state of civil society.
In fact, does not the undertaking entered into by the whole body of the nation bind it
to provide for the security of the least of its members with as much care as for that of
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
217
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
all the rest? Is the welfare of a single citizen any less the common cause than that of
the whole State? It may be said that it is good that one should perish for all. I am
ready to admire such a saying when it comes from the lips of a virtuous and worthy
patriot, voluntarily and dutifully sacrificing himself for the good of his country: but if
we are to understand by it, that it is lawful for the government to sacrifice an innocent
man for the good of the multitude, I look upon it as one of the most execrable rules
tyranny ever invented, the greatest falsehood that can be advanced, the most
dangerous admission that can be made, and a direct contradiction of the fundamental
laws of society. So little is it the case that any one person ought to perish for all, that
all have pledged their lives and properties for the defence of each, in order that the
weakness of individuals may always be protected by the strength of the public, and
each member by the whole State. Suppose we take from the whole people one
individual after another, and then press the advocates of this rule to explain more
exactly what they mean by the body of the State, and we shall see that it will at length
be reduced to a small number of persons, who are not the people, but the officers of
the people, and who, having bound themselves by personal oath to perish for the
welfare of the people, would thence infer that the people is to perish for their own.
Need we look for examples of the protection which the State owes to its members,
and the respect it owes to their persons? It is only among the most illustrious and
courageous nations that they are to be found; it is only among free peoples that the
dignity of man is realised. It is well known into what perplexity the whole republic of
Sparta was thrown, when the question of punishing a guilty citizen arose.
In Macedon, the life of a man was a matter of such importance, that Alexander the
Great, at the height of his glory, would not have dared to put a Macedonian criminal
to death in cold blood, till the accused had appeared to make his defence before his
fellow-citizens, and had been condemned by them. But the Romans distinguished
themselves above all other peoples by the regard which their government paid to the
individual, and by its scrupulous attention to the preservation of the inviolable rights
of all the members of the State. Nothing was so sacred among them as the life of a
citizen; and no less than an assembly of the whole people was needed to condemn
one. Not even the Senate, nor the Consuls, in all their majesty, possessed the right; but
the crime and punishment of a citizen were regarded as a public calamity among the
most powerful people in the world. So hard indeed did it seem to shed blood for any
crime whatsoever, that by the Lex Porcia, the penalty of death was commuted into
that of banishment for all those who were willing to survive the loss of so great a
country. Everything both at Rome, and in the Roman armies, breathed that love of
fellow-citizens one for another, and that respect for the Roman name, which raised the
courage and inspired the virtue of every one who had the honour to bear it. The cap of
a citizen delivered from slavery, the civic crown of him who had saved the life of
another, were looked upon with the greatest pleasure amid the pomp of their triumphs;
and it is remarkable that among the crowns which were bestowed in honour of
splendid actions in war, the civic crown and that of the triumphant general alone were
of laurel, all the others being merely of gold. It was thus that Rome was virtuous and
became the mistress of the world. Ambitious rulers! A herdsman governs his dogs and
cattle, and yet is only the meanest of mankind. If it be a fine thing to command, it is
when those who obey us are capable of doing us honour. Show respect, therefore, to
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
218
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
your fellow-citizens, and you will render yourselves worthy of respect; show respect
to liberty, and your power will increase daily. Never exceed your rights, and they will
soon become unlimited.
Let our country then show itself the common mother of her citizens; let the
advantages they enjoy in their country endear it to them; let the government leave
them enough share in the public administration to make them feel that they are at
home; and let the laws be in their eyes only the guarantees of the common liberty.
These rights, great as they are, belong to all men: but without seeming to attack them
directly, the ill-will of rulers may in fact easily reduce their effect to nothing. The law,
which they thus abuse, serves the powerful at once as a weapon of offence, and as a
shield against the weak; and the pretext of the public good is always the most
dangerous scourge of the people. What is most necessary, and perhaps most difficult,
in government, is rigid integrity in doing strict justice to all, and above all in
protecting the poor against the tyranny of the rich. The greatest evil has already come
about, when there are poor men to be defended, and rich men to be restrained. It is on
the middle classes alone that the whole force of the law is exerted; they are equally
powerless against the treasures of the rich and the penury of the poor. The first mocks
them, the second escapes them. The one breaks the meshes, the other passes through
them.
It is therefore one of the most important functions of government to prevent extreme
inequality of fortunes; not by taking away wealth from its possessors, but by
depriving all men of means to accumulate it; not by building hospitals for the poor,
but by securing the citizens from becoming poor. The unequal distribution of
inhabitants over the territory, when men are crowded together in one place, while
other places are depopulated; the encouragement of the arts that minister to luxury
and of purely industrial arts at the expense of useful and laborious crafts; the sacrifice
of agriculture to commerce; the necessitation of the tax-farmer by the mal-
administration of the funds of the State; and in short, venality pushed to such an
extreme that even public esteem is reckoned at a cash value, and virtue rated at a
market price: these are the most obvious causes of opulence and of poverty, of public
interest, of mutual hatred among citizens, of indifference to the common cause, of the
corruption of the people, and of the weakening of all the springs of government. Such
are the evils, which are with difficulty cured when they make themselves felt, but
which a wise administration ought to prevent, if it is to maintain, along with good
morals, respect for the laws, patriotism, and the influence of the general will.
But all these precautions will be inadequate, unless rulers go still more to the root of
the matter. I conclude this part of public economy where I ought to have begun it.
There can be no patriotism without liberty, no liberty without virtue, no virtue without
citizens; create citizens, and you have everything you need; without them, you will
have nothing but debased slaves, from the rulers of the State downwards. To form
citizens is not the work of a day; and in order to have men it is necessary to educate
them when they are children. It will be said, perhaps, that whoever has men to govern,
ought not to seek, beyond their nature, a perfection of which they are incapable; that
he ought not to desire to destroy their passions; and that the execution of such an
attempt is no more desirable than it is possible. I will agree, further, that a man
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
219
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
without passions would certainly be a bad citizen; but it must be agreed also that, if
men are not taught not to love some things, it is impossible to teach them to love one
object more than another—to prefer that which is truly beautiful to that which is
deformed. If, for example, they were early accustomed to regard their individuality
only in its relation to the body of the State, and to be aware, so to speak, of their own
existence merely as a part of that of the State, they might at length come to identify
themselves in some degree with this greater whole, to feel themselves members of
their country, and to love it with that exquisite feeling which no isolated person has
save for himself; to lift up their spirits perpetually to this great object, and thus to
transform into a sublime virtue that dangerous disposition which gives rise to all our
vices. Not only does philosophy demonstrate the possibility of giving feeling these
new directions; history furnishes us with a thousand striking examples. If they are so
rare among us moderns, it is because nobody troubles himself whether citizens exist
or not, and still less does anybody think of attending to the matter soon enough to
make them. It is too late to change our natural inclinations, when they have taken their
course, and egoism is confirmed by habit: it is too late to lead us out of ourselves
when once the human Ego, concentrated in our hearts, has acquired that contemptible
activity which absorbs all virtue and constitutes the life and being of little minds. How
can patriotism germinate in the midst of so many other passions which smother it?
And what can remain, for fellow-citizens, of a heart already divided between avarice,
a mistress, and vanity?
From the first moment of life, men ought to begin learning to deserve to live; and, as
at the instant of birth we partake of the rights of citizenship, that instant ought to be
the beginning of the exercise of our duty. If there are laws for the age of maturity,
there ought to be laws for infancy, teaching obedience to others: and as the reason of
each man is not left to be the sole arbiter of his duties, government ought the less
indiscriminately to abandon to the intelligence and prejudices of fathers the education
of their children, as that education is of still greater importance to the State than to the
fathers: for, according to the course of nature, the death of the father often deprives
him of the final fruits of education; but his country sooner or later perceives its
effects. Families dissolve, but the State remains.
Should the public authority, by taking the place of the father, and charging itself with
that important function, acquire his rights by discharging his duties, he would have
the less cause to complain, as he would only be changing his title, and would have in
common, under the name of citizen, the same authority over his children, as he was
exercising separately under the name of father, and would not be less obeyed when
speaking in the name of the law, than when he spoke in that of nature. Public
education, therefore, under regulations prescribed by the government, and under
magistrates established by the Sovereign, is one of the fundamental rules of popular or
legitimate government. If children are brought up in common in the bosom of
equality; if they are imbued with the laws of the State and the precepts of the general
will; if they are taught to respect these above all things; if they are surrounded by
examples and objects which constantly remind them of the tender mother who
nourishes them, of the love she bears them, of the inestimable benefits they receive
from her, and of the return they owe her, we cannot doubt that they will learn to
cherish one another mutually as brothers, to will nothing contrary to the will of
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
220
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
society, to substitute the actions of men and citizens for the futile and vain babbling of
sophists, and to become in time defenders and fathers of the country of which they
will have been so long the children.
I shall say nothing of the Magistrates destined to preside over such an education,
which is certainly the most important business of the State. It is easy to see that if
such marks of public confidence were conferred on slight grounds, if this sublime
function were not, for those who have worthily discharged all other offices, the
reward of labour, the pleasant and honourable repose of old age, and the crown of all
honours, the whole enterprise would be useless and the education void of success. For
whereever the lesson is not supported by authority, and the precept by example, all
instruction is fruitless; and virtue itself loses its credit in the mouth of one who does
not practise it. But let illustrious warriors, bent under the weight of their laurels,
preach courage: let upright Magistrates, grown white in the purple and on the bench
teach justice. Such teachers as these would thus get themselves virtuous successors,
and transmit from age to age, to generations to come, the experience and talents of
rulers, the courage and virtue of citizens, and common emulation in all to live and die
for their country.
I know of but three peoples which once practised public education, the Cretans, the
Lacedemonians, and the ancient Persians: among all these it was attended with the
greatest success, and indeed it did wonders among the two last. Since the world has
been divided into nations too great to admit of being well governed, this method has
been no longer practicable, and the reader will readily perceive other reasons why
such a thing has never been attempted by any modern people. It is very remarkable
that the Romans were able to dispense with it; but Rome was for five hundred years
one continued miracle which the world cannot hope to see again. The virtue of the
Romans, engendered by their horror of tyranny and the crimes of tyrants, and by an
innate patriotism, made all their houses so many schools of citizenship; while the
unlimited power of fathers over their children made the individual authority so rigid
that the father was more feared than the Magistrate, and was in his family tribunal
both censor of morals and avenger of the laws.
Thus a careful and well-intentioned government, vigilant incessantly to maintain or
restore patriotism and morality among the people, provides beforehand against the
evils which sooner or later result from the indifference of the citizens to the fate of the
Republic, keeping within narrow bounds that personal interest which so isolates the
individual that the State is enfeebled by his power, and has nothing to hope from his
good-will. Wherever men love their country, respect the laws, and live simply, little
remains to be done in order to make them happy; and in public administration, where
chance has less influence than in the lot of individuals, wisdom is so nearly allied to
happiness, that the two objects are confounded.
III. It is not enough to have citizens and to protect them, it is also necessary to
consider their subsistence. Provision for the public wants is an obvious inference from
the general will, and the third essential duty of government. This duty is not, we
should feel, to fill the granaries of individuals and thereby to grant them a
dispensation from labour, but to keep plenty so within their reach that labour is
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
221
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
always necessary and never useless for its acquisition. It extends also to everything
regarding the management of the exchequer, and the expenses of public
administration. Having thus treated of general economy with reference to the
government of persons, we must now consider it with reference to the administration
of property.
This part presents no fewer difficulties to solve, and contradictions to remove, than
the preceding. It is certain that the right of property is the most sacred of all the rights
of citizenship, and even more important in some respects than liberty itself; either
because it more nearly affects the preservation of life, or because, property being
more easily usurped and more difficult to defend than life, the law ought to pay a
greater attention to what is most easily taken away; or finally, because property is the
true foundation of civil society, and the real guarantee of the undertakings of citizens:
for if property were not answerable for personal actions, nothing would be easier than
to evade duties and laugh at the laws. On the other hand, it is no less certain that the
maintenance of the State and the government involves costs and outgoings; and as
every one who agrees to the end must acquiesce in the means, it follows that the
members of a society ought to contribute from their property to its support. Besides, it
is difficult to secure the property of individuals on one side, without attacking it on
another; and it is impossible that all the regulations which govern the order of
succession, will, contracts, &c. should not lay individuals under some constraint as to
the disposition of their goods, and should not consequently restrict the right of
property.
But besides what I have said above of the agreement between the authority of law and
the liberty of the citizen, there remains to be made, with respect to the disposition of
goods, an important observation which removes many difficulties. As Puffendorf has
shown, the right of property, by its very nature, does not extend beyond the life of the
proprietor, and the moment a man is dead his goods cease to belong to him. Thus, to
prescribe the conditions according to which he can dispose of them, is in reality less
to alter his right as it appears, than to extend it in fact.
In general, although the institution of the laws which regulate the power of individuals
in the disposition of their own goods belongs only to the Sovereign, the spirit of these
laws, which the government ought to follow in their application, is that, from father to
son, and from relation to relation, the goods of a family should go as little out of it and
be as little alienated as possible. There is a sensible reason for this in favour of
children, to whom the right of property would be quite useless, if the father left them
nothing, and who besides, having often contributed by their labour to the acquisition
of their father’s wealth, are in their own right associates with him in his right of
property. But another reason, more distant, though not less important, is that nothing
is more fatal to morality and to the Republic than the continual shifting of rank and
fortune among the citizens: such changes are both the proof and the source of a
thousand disorders, and overturn and confound everything; for those who were
brought up to one thing find themselves destined for another; and neither those who
rise nor those who fall are able to assume the rules of conduct, or to possess
themselves of the qualifications requisite for their new condition, still less to
discharge the duties it entails. I proceed to the object of public finance.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
222
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
If the people governed itself and there were no intermediary between the
administration of the State and the citizens, they would have no more to do than to
assess themselves occasionally, in proportion to the public needs and the abilities of
individuals: and as they would all keep in sight the recovery and employment of such
assessments, no fraud or abuse could slip into the management of them; the State
would never be involved in debt, or the people over-burdened with taxes; or at least
the knowledge of how the money would be used would be a consolation for the
severity of the tax. But things cannot be carried on in this manner: on the contrary,
however small any State may be, civil societies are always too populous to be under
the immediate government of all their members. It is necessary that the public money
should go through the hands of the rulers, all of whom have, besides the interests of
the State, their own individual interests, which are not the last to be listened to. The
people, on its side, perceiving rather the cupidity and ridiculous expenditure of its
rulers than the public needs, murmurs at seeing itself stripped of necessaries to furnish
others with superfluities; and when once these complaints have reached a certain
degree of bitterness, the most upright administration will find it impossible to restore
confidence. In such a case, voluntary contributions bring in nothing, and forced
contributions are illegitimate. This cruel alternative of letting the State perish, or of
violating the sacred right of property, which is its support, constitutes the great
difficulty of just and prudent economy.
The first step which the founder of a republic ought to take after the establishment of
laws, is to settle a sufficient fund for the maintenance of the Magistrates and other
Officials, and for other public expenses. This fund, if it consist of money, is called
ærarium or fisc, and public demesne if it consist of lands. This, for obvious reasons, is
much to be preferred. Whoever has reflected on this matter must be of the opinion of
Bodin, who looks upon the public demesne as the most reputable and certain means of
providing for the needs of the State. It is remarkable also that Romulus, in his division
of lands, made it his first care to set apart a third for the use of the State. I confess it is
not impossible for the produce of the demesne, if it be badly managed, to be reduced
to nothing; but it is not of the essence of public demesnes to be badly administered.
Before any use is made of this fund, it should be assigned or accepted by an assembly
of the people, or of the estates of the country, which should determine its future use.
After this solemnity, which makes such funds inalienable, their very nature is, in a
manner, changed, and the revenues become so sacred, that it is not only the most
infamous theft, but actual treason, to misapply them or pervert them from the purpose
for which they were destined. It reflects great dishonour on Rome that the integrity of
Cato the censor was something so very remarkable, and that an Emperor, on
rewarding the talents of a singer with a few crowns, thought it necessary to observe
that the money came from his own private purse, and not from that of the State. But if
we find few Galbas, where are we to look for a Cato? For when vice is no longer
dishonourable, what chiefs will be so scrupulous as to abstain from touching the
public revenues that are left to their discretion, and even not in time to impose on
themselves, by pretending to confound their own expensive and scandalous
dissipations with the glory of the State, and the means of extending their own
authority with the means of augmenting its power? It is particularly in this delicate
part of the administration that virtue is the only effective instrument, and that the
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
223
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
integrity of the Magistrate is the only real check upon his avarice. Books and auditing
of accounts, instead of exposing frauds, only conceal them; for prudence is never so
ready to conceive new precautions as knavery is to elude them. Never mind, then,
about account books and papers; place the management of finance in honest hands:
that is the only way to get it faithfully conducted.
When public funds are once established, the rulers of the State become of right the
administrators of them: for this administration constitutes a part of government which
is always essential, though not always equally so. Its influence increases in proportion
as that of other resources is diminished; and it may justly be said that a government
has reached the last stage of corruption, when it has ceased to have sinews other than
money. Now as every government constantly tends to become lax, this is enough to
show why no State can subsist unless its revenues constantly increase.
The first sense of the necessity of this increase is also the first sign of the internal
disorder of the State; and the prudent administrator, in his endeavours to find means
to provide for the present necessity, will neglect nothing to find out the distant cause
of the new need; just as a mariner when he finds the water gaining on his vessel, does
not neglect, while he is working the pumps, to discover and stop the leak.
From this rule is deduced the most important rule in the administration of finance,
which is, to take more pains to guard against needs than to increase revenues. For,
whatever diligence be employed, the relief which only comes after, and more slowly
than, the evil, always leaves some injury behind. While a remedy is being found for
one evil, another is beginning to make itself felt, and even the remedies themselves
produce new difficulties: so that at length the nation is involved in debt and the people
oppressed, while the government loses its influence and can do very little with a great
deal of money. I imagine it was owing to the recognition of this rule that such
wonders were done by ancient governments, which did more with their parsimony
than ours do with all their treasures; and perhaps from this comes the common use of
the word economy, which means rather the prudent management of what one has than
ways of getting what one has not.
But apart from the public demesne, which is of service to the State in proportion to
the uprightness of those who govern, any one sufficiently acquainted with the whole
force of the general administration, especially when it confines itself to legitimate
methods, would be astonished at the resources the rulers can make use of for guarding
against public needs, without trespassing on the goods of individuals. As they are
masters of the whole commerce of the State, nothing is easier for them than to direct it
into such channels as to provide for every need, without appearing to interfere. The
distribution of provisions, money, and merchandise in just proportions, according to
times and places, is the true secret of finance and the source of wealth, provided those
who administer it have foresight enough to suffer a present apparent loss, in order
really to obtain immense profits in the future. When we see a government paying
bounties, instead of receiving duties, on the exportation of corn in time of plenty, and
on its importation in time of scarcity, we must have such facts before our eyes if we
are to be persuaded of their reality. We should hold such facts to be idle tales, if they
had happened in ancient times. Let us suppose that, in order to prevent a scarcity in
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
224
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
bad years, a proposal were made to establish public granaries; would not the
maintenance of so useful an institution serve in most countries as an excuse for new
taxes? At Geneva, such granaries, established and kept up by a prudent
administration, are a public resource in bad years, and the principal revenue of the
State at all times. Alit et ditat is the inscription which stands, rightly and properly, on
the front of the building. To set forth in this place the economic system of a good
government, I have often turned my eyes to that of this Republic, rejoicing to find in
my own country an example of that wisdom and happiness which I should be glad to
see prevail in every other.
If we ask how the needs of a State grow, we shall find they generally arise, like the
wants of individuals, less from any real necessity than from the increase of useless
desires, and that expenses are often augmented only to give a pretext for raising
receipts: so that the State would sometimes gain by not being rich, and apparent
wealth is in reality more burdensome than poverty itself would be. Rulers may indeed
hope to keep the peoples in stricter dependence, by thus giving them with one hand
what they take from them with the other; and this was in fact the policy of Joseph
towards the Egyptians: but this political sophistry is the more fatal to the State, as the
money never returns into the hands it went out of. Such principles only enrich the idle
at the expense of the industrious.
A desire for conquest is one of the most evident and dangerous causes of this increase.
This desire, occasioned often by a different species of ambition from that which it
seems to proclaim, is not always what it appears to be, and has not so much, for its
real motive, the apparent desire to aggrandise the Nation as a secret desire to increase
the authority of the rulers at home, by increasing the number of troops, and by the
diversion which the objects of war occasion in the minds of the citizens.
It is at least certain, that no peoples are so oppressed and wretched as conquering
nations, and that their successes only increase their misery. Did not history inform us
of the fact, reason would suffice to tell us that, the greater a State grows, the heavier
and more burdensome in proportion its expenses become: for every province has to
furnish its share to the general expense of government, and besides has to be at the
expense of its own administration, which is as great as if it were really independent.
Add to this that great fortunes are always acquired in one place and spent in another.
Production therefore soon ceases to balance consumption, and a whole country is
impoverished merely to enrich a single town.
Another source of the increase of public wants, which depends on the foregoing, is
this. There may come a time when the citizens, no longer looking upon themselves as
interested in the common cause, will cease to be the defenders of their country, and
the Magistrates will prefer the command of mercenaries to that of free-men; if for no
other reason than that, when the time comes, they may use them to reduce free-men to
submission. Such was the state of Rome towards the end of the Republic and under
the Emperors: for all the victories of the early Romans, like those of Alexander, had
been won by brave citizens, who were ready, at need, to give their blood in the service
of their country, but would never sell it. Only at the siege of Veii did the practice of
paying the Roman infantry begin. Marius, in the Jugurthine war, dishonoured the
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
225
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
legions by introducing freedmen, vagabonds and other mercenaries. Tyrants, the
enemies of the very people it was their duty to make happy, maintained regular
troops, apparently to withstand the foreigner, but really to enslave their countrymen.
To form such troops, it was necessary to take men from the land; the lack of their
labour then diminished the amount of provisions, and their maintenance introduced
those taxes which increased prices. This first disorder gave rise to murmurs among the
people; in order to suppress them, the number of troops had to be increased, and
consequently the misery of the people also got worse; and the growing despair led to
still further increases in the cause in order to guard against its effects. On the other
hand, the mercenaries, whose merit we may judge of by the price at which they sold
themselves, proud of their own meanness, and despising the laws that protected them,
as well as their fellows whose bread they ate, imagined themselves more honoured in
being Cæsar’s satellites than in being defenders of Rome. As they were given over to
blind obedience, their swords were always at the throats of their fellow-citizens, and
they were prepared for general butchery at the first sign. It would not be difficult to
show that this was one of the principal causes of the ruin of the Roman Empire.
The invention of artillery and fortifications has forced the princes of Europe, in
modern times, to return to the use of regular troops, in order to garrison their towns;
but, however lawful their motives, it is to be feared the effect may be no less fatal.
There is no better reason now than formerly for depopulating the country to form
armies and garrisons, nor should the people be oppressed to support them; in a word,
these dangerous establishments have increased of late years with such rapidity in this
part of the world, that they evidently threaten to depopulate Europe, and sooner or
later to ruin its inhabitants.
Be this as it may, it ought to be seen that such institutions necessarily subvert the true
economic system, which draws the principal revenue of the State from the public
demesne, and leave only the troublesome resource of subsidies and imposts; with
which it remains to deal.
It should be remembered that the foundation of the social compact is property; and its
first condition, that every one should be maintained in the peaceful possession of what
belongs to him. It is true that, by the same treaty, every one binds himself, at least
tacitly, to be assessed toward the public wants: but as this undertaking cannot
prejudice the fundamental law, and presupposes that the need is clearly recognised by
all who contribute to it, it is plain that such assessment, in order to be lawful, must be
voluntary; it must depend, not indeed on a particular will, as if it were necessary to
have the consent of each individual, and that he should give no more than just what he
pleased, but on a general will, decided by vote of a majority, and on the basis of a
proportional rating which leaves nothing arbitrary in the imposition of the tax.
That taxes cannot be legitimately established except by the consent of the people or its
representatives, is a truth generally admitted by all philosophers and jurists of any
repute on questions of public right, not even excepting Bodin. If any of them have laid
down rules which seem to contradict this, their particular motives for doing so may
easily be seen; and they introduce so many conditions and restrictions that the
argument comes at bottom to the same thing: for whether the people has it in its
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
226
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
power to refuse, or the Sovereign ought not to exact, is a matter of indifference with
regard to right; and if the point in question concerns only power, it is useless to
inquire whether it is legitimate or not. Contributions levied on the people are two
kinds; real, levied on commodities, and personal, paid by the head. Both are called
taxes or subsidies: when the people fixes the sum to be paid, it is called subsidy; but
when it grants the product of an imposition, it is called a tax. We are told in the Spirit
of the Laws that a capitation tax is most suited to slavery, and a real tax most in
accordance with liberty. This would be incontestable, if the circumstances of every
person were equal; for otherwise nothing can be more disproportionate than such a
tax; and it is in the observations of exact proportions that the spirit of liberty consists.
But if a tax by heads were exactly proportioned to the circumstances of individuals, as
what is called the capitation tax in France might be, is would be the most equitable
and consequently the most proper for free-men.
These proportions appear at first very easy to note, because, being relative to each
man’s position in the world, their incidence is always public: but proper regard is
seldom paid to all the elements that should enter into such a calculation, even apart
from deception arising from avarice, fraud and self-interest. In the first place, we have
to consider the relation of quantities, according to which, ceteris paribus, the person
who has ten times the property of another man ought to pay ten times as much to the
State. Secondly, the relation of the use made, that is to say, the distinction between
necessaries and superfluities. He who possesses only the common necessaries of life
should pay nothing at all, while the tax on him who is in possession of superfluities
may justly be extended to everything he has over and above mere necessaries. To this
he will possibly object that, when his rank is taken into account, what may be
superfluous to a man of inferior station is necessary for him. But this is false: for a
grandee has two legs just like a cow-herd, and, like him again, but one belly. Besides,
these pretended necessaries are really so little necessary to his rank, that if he should
renounce them on any worthy occasion, he would only be the more honoured. The
populace would be ready to adore a Minister who went to Council on foot, because he
had sold off his carriages to supply a pressing need of the State. Lastly, to no man
does the law prescribe magnificence; and propriety is no argument against right.
A third relation, which is never taken into account, though it ought to be the chief
consideration, is the advantage that every person derives from the social confederacy;
for this provides a powerful protection for the immense possessions of the rich, and
hardly leaves the poor man in quiet possession of the cottage he builds with his own
hands. Are not all the advantages of society for the rich and powerful? Are not all
lucrative posts in their hands? Are not all privileges and exemptions reserved for them
alone? Is not the public authority always on their side? If a man of eminence robs his
creditors, or is guilty of other knaveries, is he not always assured of impunity? Are
not the assaults, acts of violence, assassinations, and even murders committed by the
great, matters that are hushed up in a few months, and of which nothing more is
thought? But if a great man himself is robbed or insulted, the whole police force is
immediately in motion, and woe even to innocent persons who chance to be
suspected. If he has to pass through any dangerous road, the country is up in arms to
escort him. If the axle-tree of his chaise breaks, everybody flies to his assistance. If
there is a noise at his door, he speaks but a word, and all is silent. If he is incommoded
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
227
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
by the crowd, he waves his hand and every one makes way. If his coach is met on the
road by a wagon, his servants are ready to beat the driver’s brains out, and fifty honest
pedestrians going quietly about their business had better be knocked on the head than
an idle jackanapes be delayed in his coach. Yet all this respect costs him not a
farthing: it is the rich man’s right, and not what he buys with his wealth. How
different is the case of the poor man! the more humanity owes him, the more society
denies him. Every door is shut against him, even when he has a right to its being
opened: and if ever he obtains justice, it is with much greater difficulty than others
obtain favours. If the militia is to be raised or the highway to be mended, he is always
given the preference; he always bears the burden which his richer neighbour has
influence enough to get exempted from. On the least accident that happens to him,
everybody avoids him: if his cart be overturned in the road, so far is he from receiving
any assistance, that he is lucky if he does not get horse-whipped by the impudent
lackeys of some young Duke; in a word, all gratuitous assistance is denied to the poor
when they need it, just because they cannot pay for it. I look upon any poor man as
totally undone, if he has the misfortune to have an honest heart, a fine daughter, and a
powerful neighbour.
Another no less important fact is that the losses of the poor are much harder to repair
than those of the rich, and that the difficulty of acquisition is always greater in
proportion as there is more need for it. “Nothing comes out of nothing,” is as true of
life as in physics: money is the seed of money, and the first guinea is sometimes more
difficult to acquire than the second million. Add to this that what the poor pay is lost
to them for ever, and remains in, or returns to, the hands of the rich: and as, to those
who share in the government or to their dependents, the whole produce of the taxes
must sooner or later pass, although they pay their share, these persons have always a
sensible interest in increasing them.
The terms of the social compact between these two estates of men may be summed up
in a few words. “You have need of me, because I am rich and you are poor. We will
therefore come to an agreement. I will permit you to have the honour of serving me,
on condition that you bestow on me the little you have left, in return for the pains I
shall take to command you.”
Putting all these considerations carefully together, we shall find that, in order to levy
taxes in a truly equitable and proportionate manner, the imposition ought not to be in
simple ratio to the property of the contributors, but in compound ratio to the
difference of their conditions and the superfluity of their possessions. This very
important and difficult operation is daily made by numbers of honest clerks, who
know their arithmetic; but a Plato or a Montesquieu would not venture to undertake it
without the greatest diffidence, or without praying to Heaven for understanding and
integrity.
Another disadvantage of personal taxes is that they may be too much felt or raised
with too great severity. This, however, does not prevent them from being frequently
evaded; for it is much easier for persons to escape a tax than for their possessions.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
228
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
Of all impositions, that on land, or real taxation, has always been regarded as most
advantageous in countries where more attention is paid to what the tax will produce,
and to the certainty of recovering the product, than to securing the least discomfort for
the people. It has been even maintained that it is necessary to burden the peasant in
order to rouse him from indolence, and that he would never work if he had no taxes to
pay. But in all countries experience confutes this ridiculous notion. In England and
Holland the farmer pays very little, and in China nothing: yet these are the countries
in which the land is best cultivated. On the other hand, in those countries where the
husbandman is taxed in proportion to the produce of his lands, he leaves them
uncultivated, or reaps just as much from them as suffices for bare subsistence. For to
him who loses the fruit of his labour, it is some gain to do nothing. To lay a tax on
industry is a very singular expedient for banishing idleness.
Taxes on land or corn, especially when they are excessive, lead to two results so fatal
in their effect that they cannot but depopulate and ruin, in the long run, all countries in
which they are established.
The first of these arises from the defective circulation of specie; for industry and
commerce draw all the money from the country into the capitals: and as the tax
destroys the proportion there might otherwise be between the needs of the
husbandman and the price of his corn, money is always leaving and never returning.
Thus the richer the city the poorer the country. The product of the taxes passes from
the hands of the Prince or his financial officers into those of artists and traders; and
the husbandman, who receives only the smallest part of it, is at length exhausted by
paying always the same, and receiving constantly less. How could a human body
subsist if it had veins and no arteries, or if its arteries conveyed the blood only within
four inches of the heart? Chardin tells us that in Persia the royal dues on commodities
are paid in kind: this custom, which, Herodotus informs us, prevailed long ago in the
same country down to the time of Darius, might prevent the evil of which I have been
speaking. But unless Intendants, Directors, Commissioners and Warehousemen in
Persia are a different kind of people from what they are elsewhere, I can hardly
believe that the smallest part of this produce ever reaches the king, or that the corn is
not spoilt in every granary, and the greater part of the warehouses not consumed by
fire.
The second evil effect arises from an apparent advantage, which aggravates the evil
before it can be perceived. That is that corn is a commodity whose price is not
enhanced by taxes in the country producing it, and which, in spite of its absolute
necessity, may be diminished in quantity without the price being increased. Hence,
many people die of hunger, although corn remains cheap, and the husbandman bears
the whole charge of a tax, for which he cannot indemnify himself by the price of his
corn. It must be observed that we ought not to reason about a land-tax in the same
manner as about duties laid on various kinds of merchandise; for the effect of such
duties is to raise the price, and they are paid by the buyers rather than the sellers. For
these duties, however heavy, are still voluntary, and are paid by the merchant only in
proportion to the quantity he buys; and as he buys only in proportion to his sale, he
himself gives the law its particular application; but the farmer who is obliged to pay
his rent at stated times, whether he sells or not, cannot wait till he can get his own
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
229
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
price for his commodity: even if he is not forced to sell for mere subsistence, he must
sell to pay the taxes; so that it is frequently the heaviness of the tax that keeps the
price of corn low.
It is further to be noticed that the resources of commerce and industry are so far from
rendering the tax more supportable through abundance of money, that they only
render it more burdensome. I shall not insist on what is very evident; i. e. that,
although a greater or less quantity of money in a State may give it the greater or less
credit in the eye of the foreigner, it makes not the least difference to the real fortune of
the citizens, and does not make their condition any more or less comfortable. But I
must make these two important remarks: first, unless a State possesses superfluous
commodities, and abundance of money results from foreign trade, only trading cities
are sensible of the abundance; while the peasant only becomes relatively poorer.
Secondly, as the price of everything is enhanced by the increase of money, taxes also
must be proportionately increased; so that the farmer will find himself still more
burdened without having more resources.
It ought to be observed that the tax on land is a real duty on the produce. It is
universally agreed, however, that nothing is so dangerous as a tax on corn paid by the
purchaser: but how comes it we do not see that it is a hundred times worse when the
duty is paid by the cultivator himself? Is not this an attack on the substance of the
State at its very source? Is it not the directest possible method of depopulating a
country, and therefore in the end ruining it? For the worst kind of scarcity a nation can
suffer from is lack of inhabitants.
Only the real statesman can rise, in imposing taxes, above the mere financial object:
he alone can transform heavy burdens into useful regulations, and make the people
even doubtful whether such establishments were not calculated rather for the good of
the nation in general, than merely for the raising of money.
Duties on the importation of foreign commodities, of which the natives are fond,
without the country standing in need of them; on the exportation of those of the
growth of the country which are not too plentiful, and which foreigners cannot do
without; on the productions of frivolous and all too lucrative arts; on the importation
of all pure luxuries; and in general on all objects of luxury; will answer the two-fold
end in view. It is by such taxes, indeed, by which the poor are eased, and the burdens
thrown on the rich, that it is possible to prevent the continual increase of inequality of
fortune; the subjection of such a multitude of artisans and useless servants to the rich,
the multiplication of idle persons in our cities, and the depopulation of the country-
side.
It is important that the value of any commodity and the duties laid on it should be so
proportioned that the avarice of individuals may not be too strongly tempted to fraud
by the greatness of the possible profit. To make smuggling difficult, those
commodities should be singled out which are hardest to conceal. All duties should be
rather paid by the consumer of the commodity taxed than by him who sells it: as the
quantity of duty he would be obliged to pay would lay him open to greater
temptations, and afford him more opportunities for fraud.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
230
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
This is the constant custom in China, a country where the taxes are greater and yet
better paid than in any other part of the world. The merchant himself there pays no
duty; the buyer alone, without murmuring or sedition, meets the whole charge; for as
the necessaries of life, such as rice and corn, are absolutely exempt from taxation, the
common people is not oppressed, and the duty falls only on those who are well-to-do.
Precautions against smuggling ought not to be dictated so much by the fear of it
occurring, as by the attention which the government should pay to securing
individuals from being seduced by illegitimate profits, which first make them bad
citizens, and afterwards soon turn them into dishonest men.
Heavy taxes should be laid on servants in livery, on equipages, rich furniture, fine
clothes, on spacious courts and gardens, on public entertainments of all kinds, on
useless professions, such as dancers, singers, players, and in a word, on all that
multiplicity of objects of luxury, amusement and idleness, which strike the eyes of all,
and can the less be hidden, as their whole purpose is to be seen, without which they
would be useless. We need be under no apprehension of the produce of these taxes
being arbitrary, because they are laid on things not absolutely necessary. They must
know but little of mankind who imagine that, after they have been once seduced by
luxury, they can ever renounce it: they would a hundred times sooner renounce
common necessaries, and had much rather die of hunger than of shame. The increase
in their expense is only an additional reason for supporting them, when the vanity of
appearing wealthy reaps its profit from the price of the thing and the charge of the tax.
As long as there are rich people in the world, they will be desirous of distinguishing
themselves from the poor, nor can the State devise a revenue less burdensome or more
certain than what arises from this distinction.
For the same reason, industry would have nothing to suffer from an economic system
which increased the revenue, encouraged agriculture by relieving the husbandman,
and insensibly tended to bring all fortunes nearer to that middle condition which
constitutes the genuine strength of the State. These taxes might, I admit, bring certain
fashionable articles of dress and amusement to an untimely end; but it would be only
to substitute others, by which the artificer would gain, and the exchequer suffer no
loss. In a word, suppose the spirit of government was constantly to tax only the
superfluities of the rich, one of two things must happen: either the rich would convert
their superfluous expenses into useful ones, which would redound to the profit of the
State, and thus the imposition of taxes would have the effect of the best sumptuary
laws, the expenses of the State would necessarily diminish with those of individuals,
and the treasury would not receive so much less as it would gain by having less to
pay; or, if the rich did not become less extravagant, the exchequer would have such
resources in the product of taxes on their expenditure as would provide for the needs
of the State. In the first case the treasury would be the richer by what it would save,
from having the less to do with its money; and in the second, it would be enriched by
the useless expenses of individuals.
We may add to all this a very important distinction in matters of political right, to
which governments, constantly tenacious of doing everything for themselves, ought to
pay great attention. It has been observed that personal taxes and duties on the
necessaries of life, as they directly trespass on the right of property, and consequently
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
231
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
on the true foundation of political society, are always liable to have dangerous results,
if they are not established with the express consent of the people or its representatives.
It is not the same with articles the use of which we can deny ourselves; for as the
individual is under no absolute necessity to pay, his contribution may count as
voluntary. The particular consent of each contributor then takes the place of the
general consent of the whole people: for why should a people oppose the imposition
of a tax which falls only on those who desire to pay it? It appears to me certain that
everything, which is not proscribed by law, or contrary to morality, and yet may be
prohibited by the government, may also be permitted on payment of a certain duty.
Thus, for example, if the government may prohibit the use of coaches, it may
certainly impose a tax on them; and this is a prudent and useful method of censuring
their use without absolutely forbidding it. In this case, the tax may be regarded as a
sort of fine, the product of which compensates for the abuse it punishes.
It may perhaps be objected that those, whom Bodin calls impostors, i. e. those who
impose or contrive the taxes, being in the class of the rich, will be far from sparing
themselves to relieve the poor. But this is quite beside the point. If, in every nation,
those to whom the Sovereign commits the government of the people, were, from their
position, its enemies, it would not be worth while to inquire what they ought to do to
make the people happy.
PRINTED BY THE TEMPLE PRESS AT LETCHWORTH IN GREAT BRITAIN
[1]The term “general” will means, in Rousseau, not so much “will held by several
persons,” as will having a general (universal) object. This is often misunderstood; but
the mistake matters the less, because the General Will must, in fact, be both.
[1]“Learned inquiries into public right are often only the history of past abuses; and
troubling to study them too deeply is a profitless infatuation” (Essay on the Interests
of France in Relation to its Neighbours, by the Marquis d’Argenson). This is exactly
what Grotius has done.
[2]See a short treatise of Plutarch’s entitled “That Animals Reason.”
[1]The Romans, who understood and respected the right of war more than any other
nation on earth, carried their scruples on this head so far that a citizen was not allowed
to serve as a volunteer without engaging himself expressly against the enemy, and
against such and such an enemy by name. A legion in which the younger Cato was
seeing his first service under Popilius having been reconstructed, the elder Cato wrote
to Popilius that, if he wished his son to continue serving under him, he must
administer to him a new military oath, because, the first having been annulled, he was
no longer able to bear arms against the enemy. The same Cato wrote to his son telling
him to take great care not to go into battle before taking this new oath. I know that the
siege of Clusium and other isolated events can be quoted against me; but I am citing
laws and customs. The Romans are the people that least often transgressed its laws;
and no other people has had such good ones.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
232
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[1]The real meaning of this word has been almost wholly lost in modern times; most
people mistake a town for a city, and a townsman for a citizen. They do not know that
houses make a town, but citizens a city. The same mistake long ago cost the
Carthaginians dear. I have never read of the title of citizens being given to the subjects
of any prince, not even the ancient Macedonians or the English of to-day, though they
are nearer liberty than any one else. The French alone everywhere familiarly adopt the
name of citizens, because, as can be seen from their dictionaries, they have no idea of
its meaning; otherwise they would be guilty in usurping it, of the crime of lèse-
majesté: among them, the name expresses a virtue, and not a right. When Bodin spoke
of our citizens and townsmen, he fell into a bad blunder in taking the one class for the
other. M. d’Alembert has avoided the error, and, in his article on Geneva, has clearly
distinguished the four orders of men (or even five, counting mere foreigners) who
dwell in our town, of which two only compose the Republic. No other French writer,
to my knowledge, has understood the real meaning of the word citizen.
[1]Under bad governments, this equality is only apparent and illusory: it serves only
to keep the pauper in his poverty and the rich man in the position he has usurped. In
fact, laws are always of use to those who possess and harmful to those who have
nothing: from which it follows that the social state is advantageous to men only when
all have something and none too much.
[1]To be general, a will need not always be unanimous; but every vote must be
counted: any exclusion is a breach of generality.
[1]“Every interest,” says the Marquis d’Argenson, “has different principles. The
agreement of two particular interests is formed by opposition to a third.” He might
have added that the agreement of all interests is formed by opposition to that of each.
If there were no different interests, the common interest would be barely felt, as it
would encounter no obstacle; all would go on of its own accord, and politics would
cease to be an art.
[1]“In fact,” says Macchiavelli, “there are some divisions that are harmful to a
Republic and some that are advantageous. Those which stir up sects and parties are
harmful; those attended by neither are advantageous. Since, then, the founder of a
Republic cannot help enmities arising, he ought at least to prevent them from growing
into sects” (History of Florence, Book vii). [Rousseau quotes the Italian.]
[1]Attentive readers, do not, I pray, be in a hurry to charge me with contradicting
myself. The terminology made it unavoidable, considering the poverty of the
language; but wait and see.
[1]I understand by this word, not merely an aristocracy or a democracy, but generally
any government directed by the general will, which is the law. To be legitimate, the
government must be, not one with the Sovereign, but its minister. In such a case even
a monarchy is a Republic. This will be made clearer in the following book.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
233
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[1]A people becomes famous only when its legislation begins to decline. We do not
know for how many centuries the system of Lycurgus made the Spartans happy
before the rest of Greece took any notice of it.
[2]Montesquieu, The Greatness and Decadence of the Romans, ch. i.
[1]Those who know Calvin only as a theologian much under-estimate the extent of his
genius. The codification of our wise edicts, in which he played a large part, does him
no less honour than his Institute. Whatever revolution time may bring in our religion,
so long as the spirit of patriotism and liberty still lives among us, the memory of this
great man will be for ever blessed.
[1]“In truth,” says Macchiavelli, “there has never been, in any country, an
extraordinary legislator who has not had recourse to God; for otherwise his laws
would not have been accepted: there are, in fact, many useful truths of which a wise
man may have knowledge without their having in themselves such clear reasons for
their being so as to be able to convince others” (Discourses on Livy, Bk. v, ch. xi).
[Rousseau quotes the Italian.]
[1]If there were two neighbouring peoples, one of which could not do without the
other, it would be very hard on the former, and very dangerous for the latter. Every
wise nation, in such a case, would make haste to free the other from dependence. The
Republic of Thlascala, enclosed by the Mexican Empire, preferred doing without salt
to buying from the Mexicans, or even getting it from them as a gift. The Thlascalans
were wise enough to see the snare hidden under such liberality. They kept their
freedom, and that little State, shut up in that great Empire, was finally the instrument
of its ruin.
[1]If the object is to give the State consistency, bring the two extremes as near to each
other as possible; allow neither rich men nor beggars. These two estates, which are
naturally inseparable, are equally fatal to the common good; from the one come the
friends of tyranny, and from the other tyrants. It is always between them that public
liberty is put up to auction; the one buys, and the other sells.
[1]“Any branch of foreign commerce,” says M. d’Argenson, “creates on the whole
only apparent advantage for the kingdom in general; it may enrich some individuals,
or even some towns; but the nation as a whole gains nothing by it, and the people is
no better off.”
[1]Thus at Venice the College, even in the absence of the Doge, is called “Most
Serene Prince.”
[1]The Palatine of Posen, father of the King of Poland, Duke of Lorraine. [I prefer
liberty with danger to peace with slavery.]
[1]It is clear that the word optimates meant, among the ancients, not the best, but the
most powerful.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
234
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[2]It is of great importance that the form of the election of magistrates should be
regulated by law; for if it is left at the discretion of the prince, it is impossible to avoid
falling into hereditary aristocracy, as the Republics of Venice and Berne actually did.
The first of these has therefore long been a State dissolved; the second, however, is
maintained by the extreme wisdom of the senate, and forms an honourable and highly
dangerous exception.
[1]Macchiavelli was a proper man and a good citizen; but, being attached to the court
of the Medici, he could not help veiling his love of liberty in the midst of his
country’s oppression. The choice of his detestable hero, Cæsar Borgia, clearly enough
shows his hidden aim; and the contradiction between the teaching of the Prince and
that of the Discourses on Livy and the History of Florence shows that this profound
political thinker has so far been studied only by superficial or corrupt readers. The
Court of Rome sternly prohibited his book. I can well believe it; for it is that Court it
most clearly portrays.
[1]Tacitus, Histories, i. 16. “For the best, and also the shortest way of finding out
what is good and what is bad is to consider what you would have wished to happen or
not to happen, had another than you been Emperor.”
[1]In the Politicus.
[1]This does not contradict what I said before (Book ii, ch. ix) about the
disadvantages of great States; for we were then dealing with the authority of the
government over the members, while here we are dealing with its force against the
subjects. Its scattered members serve it as rallying-points for action against the people
at a distance, but it has no rallying-point for direct action on its members themselves.
Thus the length of the lever is its weakness in the one case, and its strength in the
other.
[1]On the same principle it should be judged what centuries deserve the preference for
human prosperity. Those in which letters and arts have flourished have been too much
admired, because the hidden object of their culture has not been fathomed, and their
fatal effects not taken into account. “Idque apud imperitos humanitas vocabatur, cum
pars servitutis esset.” [“Fools called ‘humanity’ what was a part of slavery,” Tacitus,
Agricola, 31.] Shall we never see in the maxims books lay down the vulgar interest
that makes their writers speak? No, whatever they may say, when, despite its renown,
a country is depopulated, it is not true that all is well, and it is not enough that a poet
should have an income of 100,000 francs to make his age the best of all. Less
attention should be paid to the apparent repose and tranquillity of the rulers than to the
well-being of their nations as wholes, and above all of the most numerous States. A
hail-storm lays several cantons waste, but it rarely makes a famine. Outbreaks and
civil wars give rulers rude shocks, but they are not the real ills of peoples, who may
even get a respite, while there is a dispute as to who shall tyrannise over them. Their
true prosperity and calamities come from their permanent condition: it is when the
whole remains crushed beneath the yoke, that decay sets in, and that the rulers destroy
them at will, and “ubi solitudinem faciunt, pacem appellant.” [“Where they create
solitude, they call it peace,” Tacitus, Agricola, 31.] When the bickerings of the great
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
235
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
disturbed the kingdom of France, and the Coadjutor of Paris took a dagger in his
pocket to the Parliament, these things did not prevent the people of France from
prospering and multiplying in dignity, ease and freedom. Long ago Greece flourished
in the midst of the most savage wars; blood ran in torrents, and yet the whole country
was covered with inhabitants. It appeared, says Macchiavelli, that in the midst of
murder, proscription and civil war, our republic only throve: the virtue, morality and
independence of the citizens did more to strengthen it than all their dissensions had
done to enfeeble it. A little disturbance gives the soul elasticity; what makes the race
truly prosperous is not so much peace as liberty.
[1]The slow formation and the progress of the Republic of Venice in its lagoons are a
notable instance of this sequence; and it is most astonishing that, after more than
twelve hundred years’ existence, the Venetians seem to be still at the second stage,
which they reached with the Serrar di Consiglio in 1198. As for the ancient Dukes
who are brought up against them, it is proved, whatever the Squittinio della libertà
veneta may say of them, that they were in no sense Sovereigns.
A case certain to be cited against my view is that of the Roman Republic, which, it
will be said, followed exactly the opposite course, and passed from monarchy to
aristocracy and from aristocracy to democracy. I by no means take this view of it.
What Romulus first set up was a mixed government, which soon deteriorated into
despotism. From special causes, the State died an untimely death, as new-born
children sometimes perish without reaching manhood. The expulsion of the Tarquins
was the real period of the birth of the Republic. But at first it took on no constant
form, because, by not abolishing the patriciate, it left half its work undone. For, by
this means, hereditary aristocracy, the worst of all legitimate forms of administration,
remained in conflict with democracy, and the form of the government, as
Macchiavelli has proved, was only fixed on the establishment of the tribunate: only
then was there a true government and a veritable democracy. In fact, the people was
then not only Sovereign, but also magistrate and judge; the senate was only a
subordinate tribunal, to temper and concentrate the government, and the consuls
themselves, though they were patricians, first magistrates, and absolute generals in
war, were in Rome itself no more than presidents of the people.
From that point, the government followed its natural tendency, and inclined strongly
to aristocracy. The patriciate, we may say, abolished itself, and the aristocracy was
found no longer in the body of patricians as at Venice and Genoa, but in the body of
the senate, which was composed of patricians and plebeians, and even in the body of
tribunes when they began to usurp an active function: for names do not affect facts,
and, when the people has rulers who govern for it, whatever name they bear, the
government is an aristocracy.
The abuse of aristocracy led to the civil wars and the triumvirate. Sulla, Julius Cæsar
and Augustus became in fact real monarchs; and finally, under the despotism of
Tiberius, the State was dissolved. Roman history then confirms, instead of
invalidating, the principle I have laid down.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
236
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[1]Omnes enim et habentur et dicuntur tyranni, qui potestate utuntur perpetua in ea
civitate quæ libertate usa est (Cornelius Nepos, Life of Miltiades). [For all those are
called and considered tyrants, who hold perpetual power in a State that has known
liberty.] It is true that Aristotle (Nicomachean Ethics, Book viii, chapter x)
distinguishes the tyrant from the king by the fact that the former governs in his own
interest, and the latter only for the good of his subjects; but not only did all Greek
authors in general use the word tyrant in a different sense, as appears most clearly in
Xenophon’s Hiero, but also it would follow from Aristotle’s distinction that, from the
very beginning of the world, there has not yet been a single king.
[1]In nearly the same sense as this word has in the English Parliament. The similarity
of these functions would have brought the consuls and the tribunes into conflict, even
had all jurisdiction been suspended.
[1]To adopt in cold countries the luxury and effeminacy of the East is to desire to
submit to its chains; it is indeed to bow to them far more inevitably in our case than in
theirs.
[1]I had intended to do this in the sequel to this work, when in dealing with external
relations I came to the subject of confederations. The subject is quite new, and its
principles have still to be laid down.
[1]Provided, of course, he does not leave to escape his obligations and avoid having to
serve his country in the hour of need. Flight in such a case would be criminal and
punishable, and would be, not withdrawal, but desertion.
[1]This should of course be understood as applying to a free State; for elsewhere
family, goods, lack of a refuge, necessity, or violence may detain a man in a country
against his will; and then his dwelling there no longer by itself implies his consent to
the contract or to its violation.
[2]At Genoa, the word Liberty may be read over the front of the prisons and on the
chains of the galley-slaves. This application of the device is good and just. It is indeed
only malefactors of all estates who prevent the citizen from being free. In the country
in which all such men were in the galleys, the most perfect liberty would be enjoyed.
[1]I say “in the Campus Martius” because it was there that the comitia assembled by
centuries; in its two other forms the people assembled in the forum or elsewhere; and
then the capite censi had as much influence and authority as the foremost citizens.
[1]Custodes, diribitores, rogatores suffragiorum.
[1]The nomination was made secretly by night, as if there were something shameful
in setting a man above the laws.
[1]That is what he could not be sure of, if he proposed a dictator; for he dared not
nominate himself, and could not be certain that his colleague would nominate him.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
237
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[1]I merely call attention in this chapter to a subject with which I have dealt at greater
length in my Letter to M. d’Alembert.
[2]They were from another island, which the delicacy of our language forbids me to
name on this occasion.
[1]Nonne ea quæ possidet Chamos deus tuus, tibi jure debentur? (Judges xi. 24). Such
is the text in the Vulgate. Father de Carrières translates: “Do you not regard
yourselves as having a right to what your god possesses?” I do not know the force of
the Hebrew text: but I perceive that, in the Vulgate, Jephthah positively recognises the
right of the god Chamos, and that the French translator weakened this admission by
inserting an “according to you,” which is not in the Latin.
[2]It is quite clear that the Phocian war, which was called “the Sacred War,” was not a
war of religion. Its object was the punishment of acts of sacrilege, and not the
conquest of unbelievers.
[1]It should be noted that the clergy find their bond of union not so much in formal
assemblies, as in the communion of Churches. Communion and excommunication are
the social compact of the clergy, a compact which will always make them masters of
peoples and kings. All priests who communicate together are fellow-citizens, even if
they come from opposite ends of the earth. This invention is a masterpiece of
statesmanship: there is nothing like it among pagan priests; who have therefore never
formed a clerical corporate body.
[2]See, for instance, in a letter from Grotius to his brother (April 11, 1643), what that
learned man found to praise and to blame in the De Cive. It is true that, with a bent for
indulgence, he seems to pardon the writer the good for the sake of the bad; but all men
are not so forgiving.
[1]“In the republic,” says the Marquis d’Argenson, “each man is perfectly free in
what does not harm others.” This is the invariable limitation, which it is impossible to
define more exactly. I have not been able to deny myself the pleasure of occasionally
quoting from this manuscript, though it is unknown to the public, in order to do
honour to the memory of a good and illustrious man, who had kept even in the
Ministry the heart of a good citizen, and views on the government of his country that
were sane and right.
[1]Cæsar, pleading for Catiline, tried to establish the dogma that the soul is mortal:
Cato and Cicero, in refutation, did not waste time in philosophising. They were
content to show that Cæsar spoke like a bad citizen, and brought forward a doctrine
that would have a bad effect on the State. This, in fact, and not a problem of theology,
was what the Roman senate had to judge.
[1]Marriage, for instance, being a civil contract, has civil effects without which
society cannot even subsist. Suppose a body of clergy should claim the sole right of
permitting this act, a right which every intolerant religion must of necessity claim, is it
not clear that in establishing the authority of the Church in this respect, it will be
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
238
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
destroying that of the prince, who will have thenceforth only as many subjects as the
clergy choose to allow him? Being in a position to marry or not to marry people,
according to their acceptance of such and such a doctrine, their admission or rejection
of such and such a formula, their greater or less piety, the Church alone, by the
exercise of prudence and firmness, will dispose of all inheritances, offices and
citizens, and even of the State itself, which could not subsist if it were composed
entirely of bastards? But, I shall be told, there will be appeals on the ground of abuse,
summonses and decrees; the temporalities will be seized. How sad! The clergy,
however little, I will not say courage, but sense it has, will take no notice and go its
way: it will quietly allow appeals, summonses, decrees and seizures, and, in the end,
will remain the master. It is not, I think, a great sacrifice to give up a part, when one is
sure of securing all.
[1][Here I am, a barbarian, because men understand me not.]
[1]Sovereigns always see with pleasure a taste for the arts of amusement and
superfluity, which do not result in the exportation of bullion, increase among their
subjects. They very well know that, besides nourishing that littleness of mind which is
proper to slavery, the increase of artificial wants only binds so many more chains
upon the people. Alexander, wishing to keep the Ichthyophages in a state of
dependence, compelled them to give up fishing, and subsist on the customary food of
civilised nations. The American savages, who go naked, and live entirely on the
products of the chase, have been always impossible to subdue. What yoke, indeed,
can be imposed on men who stand in need of nothing?
[1]“I love,” said Montaigne, “to converse and hold an argument; but only with very
few people, and that for my own gratification. For to do so, by way of affording
amusement for the great, or of making a parade of one’s talents, is, in my opinion, a
trade very ill-becoming a man of honour.” It is the trade of all our intellectuals, save
one.
[1]I dare not speak of those happy nations, who did not even know the name of many
vices, which we find it difficult to suppress; the savages of America, whose simple
and natural mode of government Montaigne preferred, without hesitation, not only to
the laws of Plato, but to the most perfect visions of government philosophy can ever
suggest. He cites many examples, striking for those who are capable of appreciating
them. But, what of all that, says he, they can’t run to a pair of breeches!
[1]What are we to think was the real opinion of the Athenians themselves about
eloquence, when they were so very careful to banish declamation from that upright
tribunal, against whose decision even their gods made no appeal? What did the
Romans think of physicians, when they expelled medicine from the republic? And
when the relics of humanity left among the Spaniards induced them to forbid their
lawyers to set foot in America, what must they have thought of jurisprudence? May it
not be said that they thought, by this single expedient, to make reparation for all the
outrages they had committed against the unhappy Indians?
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
239
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
[1]It is easy to see the allegory in the fable of Prometheus: and it does not appear that
the Greeks, who chained him to the Caucasus, had a better opinion of him than the
Egyptians had of their god Theutus. The Satyr, says an ancient fable, the first time he
saw a fire, was going to kiss and embrace it; but Prometheus cried out to him to
forbear, or his beard would rue it. It burns, says he, everything that touches it.
[1]The less we know, the more we think we know. The peripatetics doubted of
nothing. Did not Descartes construct the universe with cubes and vortices? And is
there in all Europe one single physicist who does not boldly explain the inexplicable
mysteries of electricity, which will, perhaps, be for ever the despair of real
philosophers?
[1]I am far from thinking that the ascendancy which women have obtained over men
is an evil in itself. It is a present which nature has made them for the good of
mankind. If better directed, it might be productive of as much good, as it is now of
evil. We are not sufficiently sensible of what advantage it would be to society to give
a better education to that half of our species which governs the other. Men will always
be what women choose to make them. If you wish then that they should be noble and
virtuous, let women be taught what greatness of soul and virtue are. The reflections
which this subject arouses, and which Plato formerly made, deserve to be more fully
developed by a pen worthy of following so great a master, and defending so great a
cause.
[1]Pensées philosophiques (Diderot).
[1]Such was the education of the Spartans with regard to one of the greatest of their
kings. It is well worthy of notice, says Montaigne, that the excellent institutions of
Lycurgus, which were in truth miraculously perfect, paid as much attention to the
bringing up of youth as if this were their principal object, and yet, at the very seat of
the Muses, they make so little mention of learning that it seems as if their generous-
spirited youth disdained every other restraint, and required, instead of masters of the
sciences, instructors in valour, prudence and justice alone.
Let us hear next what the same writer says of the ancient Persians. Plato, says he,
relates that the heir to the throne was thus brought up. At his birth he was committed,
not to the care of women, but to eunuchs in the highest authority and near the person
of the king, on account of their virtue. These undertook to render his body beautiful
and healthy. At seven years of age they taught him to ride and go hunting. At fourteen
he was placed in the hands of four, the wisest, the most just, the most temperate and
the bravest persons in the kingdom. The first instructed him in religion, the second
taught him to adhere inviolably to truth, the third to conquer his passions, and the
fourth to be afraid of nothing. All, I may add, taught him to be a good man; but not
one taught him to be learned.
Astyages, in Xenophon, desires Cyrus to give him an account of his last lesson. It was
this, answered Cyrus, one of the big boys of the school having a small coat, gave it to
a little boy and took away from him his coat, which was larger. Our master having
appointed me arbiter in the dispute, I ordered that matters should stand as they were,
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
240
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
as each boy seemed to be better suited than before. The master, however,
remonstrated with me, saying that I considered only convenience, whereas justice
ought to have been the first concern, and justice teaches that no one should suffer
forcible interference with what belongs to him. He added that he was punished for his
wrong decision, just as boys are punished in our country schools when they forget the
first aorist of τύπτω. My tutor must make me a fine harangue, in genere
demonstrativo, before he will persuade me that his school is as good as this.
[1]If we consider the frightful disorders which printing has already caused in Europe,
and judge of the future by the progress of its evils from day to day, it is easy to
foresee that sovereigns will hereafter take as much pains to banish this dreadful art
from their dominions, as they ever took to encourage it. The Sultan Achmet, yielding
to the importunities of certain pretenders to taste, consented to have a press erected at
Constantinople; but it was hardly set to work before they were obliged to destroy it,
and throw the plant into a well.
It is related that the Caliph Omar, being asked what should be done with the library at
Alexandria, answered in these words. “If the books in the library contain anything
contrary to the Alcoran, they are evil and ought to be burnt; if they contain only what
the Alcoran teaches, they are superfluous.” This reasoning has been cited by our men
of letters as the height of absurdity; but if Gregory the Great had been in the place of
Omar, and the Gospel in the place of the Alcoran, the library would still have been
burnt, and it would have been perhaps the finest action of his life.
[1]See Appendix, p. 239.
[1][Justin. Hist. ii, 2. So much more does the ignorance of vice profit the one sort than
the knowledge of virtue the other.]
[2]Egoism must not be confused with self-respect: for they differ both in themselves
and in their effects. Self-respect is a natural feeling which leads every animal to look
to its own preservation, and which, guided in man by reason and modified by
compassion, creates humanity and virtue. Egoism is a purely relative and factitious
feeling, which arises in the state of society, leads each individual to make more of
himself than of any other, causes all the mutual damage men inflict one on another,
and is the real source of the “sense of honour.” This being understood, I maintain that,
in our primitive condition, in the true state of nature, egoism did not exist; for as each
man regarded himself as the only observer of his actions, the only being in the
universe who took any interest in him, and the sole judge of his deserts, no feeling
arising from comparisons he could not be led to make could take root in his soul; and
for the same reason, he could know neither hatred nor the desire for revenge, since
these passions can spring only from a sense of injury: and as it is the contempt or the
intention to hurt, and not the harm done, which constitutes the injury, men who
neither valued nor compared themselves could do one another much violence, when it
suited them, without feeling any sense of injury. In a word, each man, regarding his
fellows almost as he regarded animals of different species, might seize the prey of a
weaker or yield up his own to a stronger, and yet consider these acts of violence as
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
241
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638
mere natural occurrences, without the slightest emotion of insolence or despite, or any
other feeling than the joy or grief of success or failure.
[1][Nature avows she gave the human race the softest hearts, who gave them tears.]
[1][Ovid, Metamorphoses xi, 127.
Both rich and poor, shocked at their new-found ills,
Would fly from wealth, and lose what they had sought.]
[1][Tacitus, Hist. iv, 17. The most wretched slavery they call peace.]
[1]Of the Rights of the Most Christian Queen over various States of the Monarchy of
Spain, 1667.
[1]Distributive justice would oppose this rigorous equality of the state of nature, even
were it practicable in civil society; as all the members of the State owe it their services
in proportion to their talents and abilities, they ought, on their side, to be distinguished
and favoured in proportion to the services they have actually rendered. It is in this
sense we must understand that passage of Isocrates, in which he extols the primitive
Athenians, for having determined which of the two kinds of equality was the most
useful, viz. that which consists in dividing the same advantages indiscriminately
among all the citizens, or that which consists in distributing them to each according to
his deserts. These able politicians, adds the orator, banishing that unjust inequality
which makes no distinction between good and bad men, adhered inviolably to that
which rewards and punishes every man according to his deserts.
But in the first place, there never existed a society, however corrupt some may have
become, where no difference was made between the good and the bad; and with
regard to morality, where no measures can be prescribed by law exact enough to serve
as a practical rule for a magistrate, it is with great prudence that, in order not to leave
the fortune or quality of the citizens to his discretion, it prohibits him from passing
judgment on persons and confines his judgment to actions. Only morals such as those
of the ancient Romans can bear censors, and such a tribunal among us would throw
everything into confusion. The difference between good and bad men is determined
by public esteem; the magistrate being strictly a judge of right alone; whereas the
public is the truest judge of morals, and is of such integrity and penetration on this
head, that although it may be sometimes deceived, it can never be corrupted. The rank
of citizens ought, therefore, to be regulated, not according to their personal merit—for
this would put it in the power of the magistrate to apply the law almost arbirarily—but
according to the actual services done to the State, which are capable of being more
exactly estimated.
[1]See p. 185.
Online Library of Liberty: The Social Contract and Discourses
PLL v6.0 (generated September, 2011)
242
http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/638